Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-12T06:28:37.652Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

22 - The soul’s faculties

from IV - Soul and knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2014

Dag Nikolaus Hasse
Affiliation:
Julius-Maximilians-Universität Würzburg
Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Christina van Dyke
Affiliation:
Calvin College, Michigan
Get access

Summary

Most medieval thinkers assume that the human soul has several faculties or powers: basic faculties such as digestion or growth, more elaborate faculties such as movement, vision, or imagination, and the characteristically human faculties of will and intellect. This was the mainstream position, but it was not left unquestioned in the later Middle Ages and in early modern philosophy. Several nominalists, for instance, argue that the powers of the soul are nothing but different names for the soul itself, as it is active in different ways. Later, in the seventeenth century, mechanistic philosophers such as René Descartes claim that there is no real distinction between power and act, nor between soul and powers. Descartes reserves the term ‘soul’ for the mind, and so reduces the number of powers drastically; he claims that all lower powers, such as sense perception or imagination, are equivalent either to the mind or certain powers of the body. Even Thomistic authors of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, who usually defend the theory of the faculties, at times question the traditional set of faculties and reduce their number. Francisco Suárez, for example, holds that common sense, imagination, estimation, and memory are in fact one power, because all these functions can be attributed to one faculty.

Nevertheless, in spite of the criticisms voiced by nominalist and early modern philosophers, medieval faculty psychology itself was well supported by arguments that have their origin in Greek philosophy. In the Republic, for example, Plato proposes a threefold division of the soul into reason, spirit, and desire. He bases this theory on the fact that there are conflicts in the soul: we may desire an object and at the same time reject it, as when we desire to drink something but reject it because we think it is bad for us. This can be explained, he believes, only by assuming that the soul has distinct parts that can come into conflict with each other (435e–439d).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buridan, John, Quaest. de anima II.4, ed. Sobol; René Descartes, Traité de l’homme (ed. Adam and Tannery, XI: 201–2)
Chene, Dennis Des, Life’s Form: Late Aristotelian Conceptions of the Soul (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2000) pp. 143–51
Künzle, Pius, Das Verhältnis der Seele zu ihren Potenzen: Problemgeschichtliche Untersuchungen von Augustin bis und mit Thomas von Aquin (Fribourg: Universitätsverlag, 1956)
Park, Katharine, “The Organic Soul,” in Schmitt, C. et al. (eds.) The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 464–84
Wolfson, Harry A., “The Internal Senses in Latin, Arabic and Hebrew Philosophical Texts,” Harvard Theological Review 28 (1935) pp. 95–100Google Scholar
Gutas, Dimitri, “Intuition and Thinking: The Evolving Structure of Avicenna’s Epistemology,” in Wisnovsky, R. (ed.) Aspects of Avicenna (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001) 1–38
Hasse, Dag Nikolaus, Avicenna’s De anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul 1160–1300 (London: Warburg Institute, 2000) pp. 177–83
Jordan, Mark, “The Disappearance of Galen in Thirteenth-Century Philosophy and Theology,” in Zimmermann, A. et al. (eds.) Mensch und Natur im Mittelalter (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1992) 703–17
Hasse, D. N., “Pietro d’Abano’s ‘Conciliator’ and the Theory of the Soul in Paris,” in Aertsen, J. et al. (eds.) Nach der Verurteilung von 1277 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2001) 635–53
Sorabji, Richard, The Philosophy of the Commentators, 200–600 AD: A Sourcebook (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2005) I: 47–52,
Ferrari, Cleophea, “Der Duft des Apfels: Abū l-Faraj ʿAbdallāh ibn aṭ-Ṭayyib und sein Kommentar zu den Kategorien des Aristoteles,” in Celluprica, V. and Costa, C. D’Ancona (eds.) Aristotele e i suoi esegeti neoplatonici (Naples: Bibliopolis, 2004) 85–106
Black, Deborah L., “Estimation (Wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and Psychological Dimensions,” Dialogue 32 (1993) 219–58Google Scholar
Pasnau, Robert, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002) pp. 267–78
Perler, Dominik, “Intentionality and Action: Medieval Discussions on the Cognitive Capacities of Animals,” in Pacheco, M. and Meirinhos, J. (eds.) Intellect et imagination dans la philosophie médiévale (Turnhout: Brepols, 2006) I: 73–98
Steel, Carlos, Der Adler und die Nachteule: Thomas und Albert über die Möglichkeit der Metaphysik (Münster: Aschendorff, 2001) pp. 22–4

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • The soul’s faculties
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.028
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • The soul’s faculties
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.028
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • The soul’s faculties
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.028
Available formats
×