Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T14:53:10.413Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - The situation and tasks of the philosophy of art

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Richard Eldridge
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

Who needs a theory of art?

For almost all people in almost all cultures, either the fact (as in dance) or the product (as in painting) of some commanding performance that is both somehow significant and yet absorbing in its own right (rather than as an immediate instrument of knowledge or work) has raised strong emotions. The dramatic rhapsode Ion, in Plato’s dialogue, reports that when in performance he looks “down at [the audience] from the stage above, I see them, every time, weeping, casting terrible glances, stricken with amazement at the deeds recounted.” Richard Wagner finds nothing less than salvation in the experience of art.

I believe in God, Mozart and Beethoven . . . I believe in the Holy Spirit and the truth of the one, indivisible Art . . . I believe that through this Art all men are saved, and therefore each may die of hunger for Her . . . I believe . . . that true disciples of high Art will be transfigured in a heavenly veil of sun-drenched fragrance and sweet sound, and united for eternity with the divine fount of all Harmony. May mine be the sentence of grace! Amen!

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Plato, , Ion, trans. Cooper, Lane, in Plato, The Collected Dialogues, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntingdon Cairns (Princeton University Press, 1961), 535e, p. 221Google Scholar
Chua, Daniel K. L., Absolute Music and the Construction of Meaning (Cambridge University Press, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hand, Matthew’s work, “part of his final studies in contemporary art” at Nottingham Trent University in the United Kingdom, is reported in David Cohen, “Pop Art,” Chronicle of Higher Education 47, 41 (June 22, 2001), p. A8.Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart, “Logic and Appreciation,” World Review (October 1952), reprinted in Art and Philosophy, ed. Kennick, W. E., 2nd edn (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1979), p. 652.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin, “The Origin of the Work of Art,” trans. Hofstadter, Albert, in Poetry, Language, Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), p. 36.Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris, Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1991), p. 507.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edn, trans. Anscombe, G. E. M. (New York: Macmillan, 1958), §258, p. 92e; interjection added.Google Scholar
Dutton, Denis, The Art Instinct: Beauty, Pleasure, and Human Evolution (Oxford University Press, 2009)Google Scholar
Davies, Stephen, The Artful Species: Aesthetics, Art, and Evolution (Oxford University Press, 2013).Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Birth of Tragedy and the Case of Wagner, trans. Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Random House, 1967), p. 34.Google Scholar
Hölderlin, Friedrich, “On the Law of Freedom,” in Essays and Letters on Theory, ed. and trans. Pfau, Thomas (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1988), pp. 33–34 at p. 34Google Scholar
Dewey, John, Art as Experience (New York: Penguin Putnam, 1934), p. 25.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor W., Aesthetic Theory, ed. and trans. Hullot-Kentor, Robert (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1997), p. 83.Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, Art and its Objects, 2nd edn (Cambridge University Press, 1980), p. 234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavell, Stanley, This New yet Unapproachable America: Lectures after Emerson after Wittgenstein (Albuquerque, NM: Living Batch Press, 1989), p. 55.Google Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism (University of Chicago Press, 1997)Google Scholar
Gould, Timothy, “The Audience of Originality: Kant and Wordsworth on the Reception of Genius,” in Essays in Kant’s Aesthetics, ed. Cohen, Ted and Guyer, Paul (University of Chicago Press, 1982), pp. 179–93.Google Scholar
Schiller, Friedrich, On the Aesthetic Education of Man, in a Series of Letters, trans. Snell, Reginald (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1954), second letter, p. 27.Google Scholar
Beiser, Frederick has undertaken the most sophisticated effort to reconstruct and defend Schiller’s views about freedom and aesthetic experience in his Schiller as Philosopher: A Re-examination (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), pp. 184–90, 229–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, On History, ed. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1963), pp. 11–26Google Scholar
Schiller, ’s “On Naïve and Sentimental Poetry,” trans. Dahlstrom, Daniel O., in Friedrich Schiller, Essays, ed. Walter Hinderer and Daniel O. Dahlstrom (New York: Continuum, 1993), pp. 179–260, especially pp. 249–50Google Scholar
Hume, David, “Of the Standard of Taste,” in The Philosophy of Art: Readings Ancient and Modern, ed. Neill, Alex and Ridley, Aaron (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1995), pp. 255–68Google Scholar
Dickie, George, Art and the Aesthetic (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1974) and his The Art Circle (New York: Haven Publications, 1984)Google Scholar
Levinson, Jerrold, “Defining Art Historically,” British Journal of Aesthetics 19 (1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beardsley, Monroe C., Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, 2nd edn (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1981), p. xxii.Google Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, The Persistence of Romanticism: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 13–19.Google Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, “Problems and Prospects of Wittgensteinian Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45, 3 (spring 1987), pp. 251–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weitz, Morris, “The Role of Theory in Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 15 (1956)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennick, W. E., “Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake?,” Mind 67, 267 (July 1958); reprinted in Aesthetics Today, ed. M. Philipson and P. J. Gudel (New York: New American Library, 1980), pp. 459–76Google Scholar
Mandelbaum, Maurice, “Family Resemblances and Generalization Concerning the Arts,” American Philosophical Quarterly 2, 3 (1965)Google Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, “Althusser and Ideological Criticism of the Arts,” in Explanation and Value in the Arts, ed. Gaskell, Ivan and Kemal, Salim (Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 190–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huhn, Tom, book review, “The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature by Pierre Bourdieu,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54, 1 (winter 1996), p. 88B.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scruton, Roger, Art and Imagination (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982), p. 248.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×