Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-swr86 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T04:12:06.334Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Models of policy divergence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 May 2010

Alberto Alesina
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Howard Rosenthal
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

According to a widely held view about American politics, the two parties are indistinguishable and both located in the middle of the political spectrum. We emphatically disagree.

The notion of convergence of party platforms emerges from the initial rational choice models of two-party electoral competition in the contributions of Hotelling (1929), Black (1958), and Downs (1957). These seminal works assumed that although voters care about public policy, candidates care only about winning.' In this situation, the candidates propose identical platforms: one should observe complete convergence of policies toward the middle. Which policy is actually chosen by a candidate depends on the specification of the electoral process: the number of issues involved, the dissemination of information within the electorate, the nature of voters' preferences, and the ability of voters to make decisions consistent with their preferences.

The most famous convergence result is the “median voter theorem” (Black (1958)). It implies that, under a certain specification, the candidates converge to the policy most preferred by the median voter. For other specifications, Hinich (1977), Coughlin and Nitzan (1981), Ledyard (1984), and Tovey (1991) analyze cases of convergence not at the median. For our purposes, the important point is not so much “where” the candidates converge (at which particular point of the political “middle”) but the fact that they fully converge.

A different view of party competition holds that political parties, as well as the voters, care about policy outcomes, in addition to winning per se (Wittman (1977, 1983), Calvert (1985), and Roemer (1992)). According to this view, political parties represent the interests and values of different constituencies.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×