Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-m9pkr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-11T21:33:12.284Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Barefoot or Daubert? A cognitive perspective on vetting future dangerousness testimony

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 December 2009

Erica Beecher-Monas
Affiliation:
Wayne State University, Detroit
Get access

Summary

Despite the well-known shakiness of its scientific credentials, expert testimony continues to be prevalent at capital-sentencing hearings. It is difficult to imagine a more critical setting for accurate expert testimony. Yet, because the rules of evidence do not generally apply (and, even where they supposedly apply, they are ignored in practice), future-dangerousness testimony goes unexamined. The reason often given for admitting evidence without regard to evidentiary rules is that the capital jury is charged with making reasoned moral judgments about the fate of the defendant – a policy decision rather than a factual finding. Policy makers as well as factfinders, however, require relevant and reliable information for their task. The dynamics of jury decision making in the context of capital-sentencing decisions demonstrate the importance of recognizing that the relevance requirement is a constitutional concern of fundamental fairness and how that requirement plays out with respect to expert testimony on future dangerousness.

To reach a just decision, jurors are supposed to be provided with “information relevant to the imposition of the sentence and provided with standards to guide its use of the information.” The purpose of testifying experts – that is, witnesses without personal knowledge of the defendant or incident – is the same in capital sentencing as it is at trial: to inform the jury about matters outside their common experience in order to assist the jury in making an accurate and just determination.

Type
Chapter
Information
Evaluating Scientific Evidence
An Interdisciplinary Framework for Intellectual Due Process
, pp. 146 - 154
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×