Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gvh9x Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T03:51:43.145Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

15 - Conflicts of Interest and Strategic Ignorance of Harm

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 August 2010

Jason Dana
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University
Don A. Moore
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Daylian M. Cain
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
George Loewenstein
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Max H. Bazerman
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Professionals with conflicts of interest face a choice between acting in accord with their self-interest or their professional responsibility. As this choice nearly always has consequences for others, an understanding of these conflicts necessarily entails a discussion of social preferences. In this discussion, I defend the notion that altruistic behavior often results from a desire not to violate rules of ethical conduct, rather than, as current economic theories suggest, a taste for altruistic outcomes per se. Whereas some situations compel people to sacrifice personal gains in favor of social concerns, these same individuals may prefer to avoid such situations in order to be selfish. For example, one may forgo even costless information about the consequences for others of a desired action, as discovering that the action is harmful could compel one not to take it. As described later, such an agent would be engaging in “strategic ignorance of harm.”

Rather than an intentional violation of ethical or moral rules, professional misconduct is often best described as a circumvention of them. Although this distinction might appear pedantic, it suggests challenges and opportunities for how we deal with the problem. In particular, our tendency to give the benefit of doubt in determining whether one has violated a moral rule provides incentives for strategic ignorance of harm, as ignorance raises a question of intent. I will discuss how conflicts can thus remain problematic even where extensive oversight and punishment are possible.

Type
Chapter
Information
Conflicts of Interest
Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy
, pp. 206 - 223
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm glow giving. The Economic Journal, 100, 464–477CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andreoni, J., Miller, J. (2002). Giving according to GARP: an experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica, 70, 737–753CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodenheimer, T. (2000). Uneasy alliance: Clinical investigators and the pharmaceutical industry. New England Journal of Medicine, 342, 1539–1543CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A. (2000). A theory of equity, reciprocity and competition. American Economic Review, 100, 166–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camerer, C. (2003). Behavioral Game Theory: Experiments on Strategic Interaction. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Carrillo, J. D., & Mariotti, T. (2000). Strategic ignorance as a self-disciplining device. Review of Economic Studies, 67, 529–544CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charness, G., & Rabin, M. (2000). Understanding social preferences with simple tests. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, 817–869CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J., Weber, R., & Kuang, J. X. (2003). Exploiting moral wriggle room: Behavior inconsistent with a preference for fair outcomes. Accessible online: 〈http://ssrn.com/abstract=400900.〉CrossRef
Dana, J., Cain, D., & Dawes, R. (2003). What you don't know won't hurt me: Costly (but quiet) exit in a dictator game. Accessible online: 〈http://ssrn.com/abstract=494422.〉
Driver, J. (1992). The suberogatory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70(3), 286–295CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eichenwald, K., & Kolata, G. (1999a). Drug trials hide conflicts for doctors. New York Times, May 17Google Scholar
Eichenwald, K., & Kolata, G. (1999b). A doctor's drug studies turn into fraud. New York Times, May 17
Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition and co-operation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, 817–868CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, A. J. (2002). Altruistically inclined? The behavioral sciences, evolutionary theory, and the origins of reciprocity. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press
Jennings, M. (1996). Manager's journal: Five warning signs of ethical collapse. Wall Street Journal, November 4Google Scholar
Ley, B. (Host). (12/10/00). Bigger, stronger, faster. [Television series episode]. In B. Leonard (Producer), Outside the lines. Bristol, Conn.: ESPN studios. Transcript available online: http://sports.espn.go.com/page2/tvlistings/show37transcript.html
Loewenstein, G., Issacharoff, S., Camerer, C., & Babcock, L. (1992). Self-serving assessments of fairness and pretrial bargaining. Journal of Legal Studies, 12, 135–159Google Scholar
Messick, D. M., & Sentis, K. P. (1979). Fairness and preference. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 15, 418–434CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Messick, D. M., & Sentis, K. (1983). Fairness, preference, and fairness biases. In D. M. Messick & K. S. Cook (Eds.), Equity theory: Psychological and sociological perspectives (pp. 61–94). New York: Praeger
Rabin, M. (1995). Moral preferences, moral constraints, and self-serving biases. Berkeley Department of Economics Working Paper No. 95–241, August

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×