Integrity is a shifty, furtive concept. Philosophers have had a
hard time defining the idea because it raises a couple of
recurrent perplexities. First, consider former Speaker Jim
Wright's remark that "integrity is . . . the state or quality of
being complete, undivided, [and] unbroken," or the Oxford
English Dictionary connotation of an "unbroken state" of
"material wholeness." The problem is that integrity, so
understood, seems to leave no room for the possibility of
individuals whose lives display any kind of self-critical revi-
sion, changes in course, or discontinuities over historical
time, or for those who compartmentalize, differentiate, and
assume conflicting roles across social space; in other words,
for all of us. We need, as Amelie Rorty has written ("Integ-
rity: Political, not Psychological," in Alan Montefiore and
David Vines, eds., Integrity in the Public and Private Domains,
1999), a far better account as to how and where "integration
and integrity . . . coincide".