Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T18:17:41.973Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Zangwill, Moderate Formalism, and Another Look at Kant's Aesthetic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 June 2011

Christopher Dowling
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, York

Extract

In recent years Nick Zangwill has gone a long way in championing a moderate aesthetic formalism in an attempt to accommodate those objects that many of us call beautiful despite their lack of any formal beauty. While there is some dispute in the literature about the extent to which Kant can be interpreted as an aesthetic formalist, the appeal of his famous distinction between free and dependent beauty should present a fairly natural ally for Zangwill's project. Indeed, such an alliance has been expressed by Zangwill, who first reaches for this ‘invaluable but misunderstood and underappreciated distinction’ in his ‘Feasible aesthetic formalism’ (1999: 613). Here, Zangwill claims that this essential distinction can be cut loose from Kant's terminology and views about aesthetic judgement. More recently he expresses more strongly that ‘Kant was also a moderate formalist, who opposes extreme formalism when he distinguished free and dependent beauty in §16 of the Critique of Judgement’ (2005: 186n). Yet, a decade on from the initial suggestion, there has been little further exploration or elucidation of this move, or indeed this potential characterization of Kant's aesthetics. It is the aim of this paper to begin to address that deficiency by identifying the extent to which a moderate formalist position is available in Kant's aesthetic. I will suggest that Kant's account does not require substantial modification in order to cast him as a moderate formalist. Taking the time to isolate the plausible grounds for characterizing Kant's aesthetic in this way, this discussion will enable us to explore some of the rival interpretations of his work such that we may also identify the kind of Kantian the moderate formalist is likely to be.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H. (2001) Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgement (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Budd, M. (1998) ‘Delight in the natural world: Kant on the aesthetic appreciation of nature: Part I: natural beauty’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 38: 118.Google Scholar
Chignell, A. (2006) ‘Beauty as a symbol of natural systematicity’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 46: 406–15.Google Scholar
Crawford, D. (1974) Kant's Aesthetic Theory (Madison: Wisconsin University Press).Google Scholar
Currie, G. (1989) An Ontology of Art (Basingstoke: Macmillan).Google Scholar
Currie, G. (1990) ‘Supervenience, essentialism, and aesthetic properties’, Philosophical Studies, 58: 243–57.Google Scholar
Gotshalk, D. W. (1967) ‘Form and expression in Kant's aesthetics’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 7: 250–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, P. (1978) ‘Interest, nature, and art: a problem in Kant's aesthetics’, Review of Metaphysics, 31: 580603.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (1997a) Kant and the Claims of Taste, 2nd edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (1997b) ‘Formalism and the theory of expression in Kant's aesthetics’, Kant-Studien, 68: 4670.Google Scholar
Janaway, C. (1997) ‘Kant's aesthetics and the empty cognitive stock’, Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 459–76.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1952) Critique of Judgement, trans. Meredith, J. C. (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Mallaband, P. (2002) ‘Understanding Kant's distinction between free and dependent beauty’, Philosophical Quarterly, 52: 6681.Google Scholar
Murray, B. (2007) ‘Kant on genius and art’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 47: 199214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parsons, G. (2004) ‘Moderate formalism as a theory of the aesthetic’, Journal of Aesthetic Education, 38: 1935.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scarre, G. (1981) ‘Kant on free and dependent beauty’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 21: 351–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaper, E. (1979) Studies in Kant's Aesthetics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).Google Scholar
Schaper, E. (1992) ‘Taste, sublimity and genius’, in Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (New York: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Walton, K. (1970) ‘Categories of art’, Philosophical Review, 79: 334–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zangwill, N. (1999) ‘Feasible aesthetic formalism’, Noûs, 33: 610–29.Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2000) ‘In defence of moderate aesthetic formalism’, Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 476–93.Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2001) The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2005) ‘In defense of extreme formalism about inorganic nature: reply to Parsons’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 45: 185–91.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, R. (19621963) ‘Kant: the aesthetic judgement’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 21: 333–44.Google Scholar