Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-09T21:15:09.363Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant's Demonstration of Free Will, Or, How to Do Things with Concepts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 May 2016

BENJAMIN S. YOST*
Affiliation:
PROVIDENCE COLLEGEbyost1@providence.edu

Abstract:

Kant famously insists that free will is a condition of morality. The difficulty of providing a demonstration of freedom has left him vulnerable to devastating attack: critics charge that Kant's post-Groundwork justification of morality amounts to a dogmatic assertion of morality's authority. My paper rebuts this objection, showing that Kant offers a cogent demonstration of freedom. My central claim is that the demonstration must be understood in practical rather than theoretical terms. A practical demonstration of x works by bringing x into existence, and what the demonstration of freedom brings into existence is a moral will, a will regulated by the moral law and capable of acting in accordance with it. Since to act morally is to act freely, bringing a moral will into existence actualizes our capacity for freedom and demonstrates that we possess it. To confirm the viability of such a demonstration, Kant must establish that agents can regulate their wills by practical principles, and that practical judgments are efficacious of themselves (i.e., that non-Humean motivational internalism is true). Kant, I argue, is successful on both counts.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H. (1989) ‘Justification and Freedom in the Critique of Practical Reason’. In Forster, E. (ed.), Kant's Transcendental Deductions: The Three ‘Critiques’ and the ‘Opus postumum’ (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press), 114–30.Google Scholar
Allison, H. (1990) Kant's Theory of Freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Allison, H. (2013) ‘Kant's Practical Justification of Freedom’. In Baiasu, S. (ed.), Kant on Practical Justification: Interpretive Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 284–99.Google Scholar
Ameriks, K. (2003) Interpreting Kant's Critiques. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Ameriks, K. (2013) ‘Is Practical Justification in Kant Ultimately Dogmatic?’ In Timmons, M. and Baiasu, S. (eds.), Kant on Practical Justification: Interpretive Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, M. W. (1995) Kantian Ethics almost Without Apology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Baxley, A. M. (2003) ‘Autocracy and Autonomy’. Kant Studien, 94, (123.Google Scholar
Bittner, R. (1989) What Reason Demands. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (1993) Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2002a) ‘The Inner Freedom of Virtue’. In Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 289315.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2002b) ‘Kant's Distinction between Theoretical and Practical Knowledge’. Harvard Review of Philosophy, 10, 4963.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2010a) The Form of Practical Knowledge: A Study of the Categorical Imperative. Cambridge, UK: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2010b) ‘Reason, Desire, and the Will’. In Denis, L. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 2850.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2010c) ‘The Triebfeder of Pure Practical Reason’. In Reath, A. and Timmerman, J. (eds.), Kant's Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 90118.Google Scholar
Franks, P. (2005) All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and Skepticism in German Idealism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Frierson, P. (2014) Kant's Empirical Psychology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, P. (2000) Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1994a) ‘The Concept of Moral Insight and Kant's Doctrine of the Fact of Reason’. In Velkley, R., (ed.), The Unity of Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 5588.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1994b) ‘Ethics of Autonomy’. In Velkley, R. (ed.), The Unity of Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 89122.Google Scholar
Herrera, L. (2000) ‘Kant on the Moral Triebfeder’. Kant Studien, 91, 395410.Google Scholar
Hill, T. (1998) ‘Kant's Argument for the Rationality of Moral Conduct’. In Guyer, P. (ed.), Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield), 249–72.Google Scholar
Kain, P. (forthcoming) ‘The Development of Kant's Conception of Divine Freedom’. In Look, B. (ed.), Leibniz and Kant (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kleingeld, P. (2010) ‘Moral Consciousness and the “Fact of Reason”’. In Reath, A. and Timmerman, J. (eds.), Kant's Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 5572.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuehn, M. (2014) ‘Collins: Kant's Proto-critical Position’. In Denis, L. and Sensen, O. (eds.), Kant's Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 5167.Google Scholar
McCarty, R. (2006) ‘Maxims in Kant's Practical Philosophy’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 44, 6583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarty, R. (2009) Kant's Theory of Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Morrisson, I. (2008) Kant and the Role of Pleasure in Moral Action. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1970) The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nauckhoff, J. (2003) ‘Incentives and Interests in Kant's Moral Psychology’. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 20, 4160.Google Scholar
Potter, N. (1994) ‘Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics’. Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik, 2, 95111.Google Scholar
Potter, N. (2002) ‘Duties to Oneself, Motivational Internalism, and Self-Deception in Kant's Ethics’. In Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 371–81.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (2000) Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, A. (2006) Agency and Autonomy in Kant's Moral Theory: Selected Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, A. (2010) ‘Formal Principles and the Form of a Law’. In Reath, A. and Timmerman, J. (eds.), Kant's Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 3154.Google Scholar
Schönecker, D. (2013) ‘Kant's Moral Intuitionism: The Fact of Reason and Moral Predispositions’. Kant Studies Online: 138. Available at: http://www.kantstudiesonline.net/KSO_Recent_files/SchoneckerDieter00213_1.pdfGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (2003) Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Sussman, D. (2008) ‘From Deduction to Deed: Kant's Grounding of the Moral Law’. Kantian Review, 13, 5281.Google Scholar
Timmerman, J. (2010) ‘Kant's Deductions of Freedom and Morality’. In Reath, A. and Timmerman, J. (eds.), Kant's Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 7389.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (1990) ‘How to Argue about Practical Reason’. Mind, 99, 355–85.Google Scholar
Ware, O. (2014) ‘Rethinking Kant's Fact of Reason’. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14, 121.Google Scholar
Wood, A. (2008) Kantian Ethics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zuckert, R. (2002) ‘A New Look at Kant's Theory of Pleasure’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 60, 239–52.Google Scholar