Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T05:40:15.853Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fiber functors and reconstruction of Hopf algebras

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 June 2024

Simon Lentner
Affiliation:
Fachbereich Mathematik, Universität Hamburg, Bundesstrassee 55, D20, 146 Hamburg, Deutschland e-mail: simon.lentner@uni-hamburg.de
Martín Mombelli*
Affiliation:
Facultad de Matemática, Astronomía y Física, Universidad Nacional de Córdoba, CIEM – CONICET, Medina Allende s/n, (5000) Ciudad Universitaria, Córdoba, Argentina
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The main objective of the present paper is to present a version of the Tannaka–Krein type reconstruction theorems: if $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is an exact faithful monoidal functor of tensor categories, one would like to realize ${\mathcal B}$ as category of representations of a braided Hopf algebra $H(F)$ in ${\mathcal C}$. We prove that this is the case iff ${\mathcal B}$ has the additional structure of a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$-module category compatible with F, which equivalently means that F admits a monoidal section. For Hopf algebras, this reduces to a version of the Radford projection theorem. The Hopf algebra is constructed through the relative coend for module categories. We expect this basic result to have a wide range of applications, in particular in the absence of fiber functors, and we give some applications. One particular motivation was the logarithmic Kazhdan–Lusztig conjecture.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

1.1 Background

The main objective of the present paper is to present a version of the Tannaka–Krein type reconstruction theorems. It is known that if ${\mathcal B}$ is a $\mathbb {k}$ -linear abelian locally finite category and $F:{\mathcal B}\to \mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ is a fiber functor, that is, an exact faithful functor, then the coend

$$ \begin{align*}C=\int^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes_{\mathbb{k}}} F(B)^*\end{align*} $$

has structure of $\mathbb {k}$ -coalgebra, and the functor F factorizes as

where $f:\mathrm {Comod}(C)\to \mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ is the forgetful functor, and $\widehat {F}$ is a category equivalence. We refer the reader to [Reference Husemöller12, Reference Majid18, Reference Rivano22] and the references therein. If, moreover, ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal rigid category and F is a monoidal functor, then it is possible to endow the coalgebra C with structure of Hopf algebra. Succinctly, monoidality of ${\mathcal B}$ gives C a product, turning it into a bialgebra, and rigidity of ${\mathcal B}$ endows C with an antipode.

Some generalizations of this result appeared in the literature. We only mention some of them. In these more general versions, a fiber functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is considered, where ${\mathcal C}$ is an arbitrary monoidal category. In some versions, the object C is not a Hopf algebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . For example, in [Reference Bruguières and Virelizier5], it is shown that if the functor F has a right adjoint $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ , then the associated monad to this adjunction $T=F\circ G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a bimonad, and there is a commutative diagram

Here, $f: {\mathcal C}^T\to {\mathcal C}$ is the forgetful functor. Beck’s monadicity theorem implies that the functor $\widehat {F}:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}^T$ is a monoidal equivalence. Rigidity of both monoidal categories ${\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C}$ implies that T has a Hopf monad structure. In [Reference Lyubashenko16, Reference Lyubashenko17], Lyubashenko reconstructed the object C as a coend $\int ^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B)\boxtimes F(B)^*$ , belonging to some completion of the Deligne tensor product ${\mathcal C} \boxtimes {\mathcal C}$ , and it turns out to be a squared coalgebra. In the work of Majid [Reference Majid18, Reference Majid19], he started with a monoidal functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , where ${\mathcal C}$ is a braided monoidal category, and he reconstructed a Hopf algebra $C=\int ^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B)^*{\otimes } F(B)$ , and set up a commutative diagram

With this generality, the functor $\widehat {F}$ no longer need to be an equivalence.

1.2 Our approach

The point of view of this paper owes a lot to [Reference Schauenburg23]. However, we shall work only with finite categories. Let $\mathbb {k}$ be an arbitrary field, and let ${\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C}$ be finite $\mathbb {k}$ -linear abelian categories. Assume that both ${\mathcal C}, {\mathcal B}$ are rigid monoidal categories and $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a monoidal functor. If F has a section $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ , that is, $F\circ G\simeq \mathrm { Id\,}_{\mathcal C}$ as monoidal functors, then it is possible to endow ${\mathcal B}$ with an action of ${\mathcal C}$ such that F is a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor. This action behaves well together with the monoidal product of ${\mathcal B}$ , in a sense that we call monoidal module category.

Under these conditions, we aim at constructing a Hopf algebra $H\in {\mathcal C}$ and obtaining a kind of Radford projection theorem in this categorical setting.

The reconstruction of such Hopf algebra is given in some steps, which we describe as follows. If ${\mathcal B}$ is a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is an exact faithful module functor, then we construct a coalgebra $C(F)\in {\mathcal C}$ as

$$ \begin{align*}C(F)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B).\end{align*} $$

Here $\oint $ stands for the relative coend, a new tool, developed in [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4], in the context of module categories. This tool is one of the new features that we incorporate in these reconstruction theorems. The coproduct and counit of $C(F)$ are defined using universal properties of the dinatural transformations associated with the relative coend. See Proposition 7.2. Moreover, we show that the functor F factorizes as

Here, $f:{}^C{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C} $ is the forgetful functor and $\widehat {F}: {\mathcal B}\to {}^C{\mathcal C}$ is an equivalence of ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories. The existence of $\widehat {F}$ is stated in Proposition 7.4, and the proof that it is an equivalence of categories is given in Theorem 7.7.

If, in addition, ${\mathcal C}$ is a braided rigid monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, ${\mathcal B}$ is a rigid monoidal category, and F is a monoidal functor, then we endow the coalgebra $C(F)$ with a product, turning it into a bialgebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . Rigidity of ${\mathcal B}$ allows to define an antipode on $C(F)$ , making it into a braided Hopf algebra. These results are stated in Theorem 7.11 and Corollary 7.19.

The contents of the paper are the following. In Section 3, we give a brief account of some basic facts about tensor categories and module categories that will be used throughout the paper. In Section 4, we review the notion of relative (co)end of a functor in the setting of module categories over a tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ . This tool was developed by the second author in [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4] as generalization of the usual (co)end. Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, ${\mathcal M}$ be a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and ${\mathcal A}$ be some target category. If a functor $S:{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal A}$ has a prebalancing, that is, natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\beta^X_{M,N}: S(M,X\triangleright N)\to S(X^*\triangleright M,N),\end{align*} $$

then the relative coend

$$ \begin{align*}\oint^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta)\end{align*} $$

is an object in $ {\mathcal A}$ equipped with dinatural transformations $\pi _M:S(M,M)\xrightarrow {. .} \oint ^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta )$ , such that it satisfies some extra condition (see, for example, (4.3)), and it is universal with this property. When ${\mathcal C}=\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , the relative (co)end coincides with the usual (co)end.

Since relative (co)ends are objects defined by a universal property, they may not exist in general. Section 4.1 is devoted to prove that all relative coends, used in this work, actually exist. In this section, it is crucial that all categories, the tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ and the module category ${\mathcal M}$ are finite. We also require that the action $ {\mathcal C}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal M}$ is exact in each variable, allowing us to use [Reference Douglas, Schommer-Pries and Snyder9, Theorem 2.24], that says that there is an equivalence of module categories ${\mathcal M}\simeq {\mathcal C}_A$ , for some algebra $A\in {\mathcal C}.$

In Section 5, we review the definition of a Hopf algebra H in a braided tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ and its tensor category of comodules ${^H}{\mathcal C}$ . We also review the definition of H-H-Yetter–Drinfeld modules in this setting, which produces a braided tensor category ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})$ . Then we introduce a notion of a ${\mathcal C}$ -module category ${\mathcal B}$ with a compatible tensor structure in the sense that there is a natural isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}l_{X,B}: X \triangleright B\xrightarrow{\;\simeq\; } (X\triangleright \mathbf{1}_{\mathcal B}){\otimes} B,\end{align*} $$

for all $X\in {\mathcal C},\,B\in {\mathcal B}$ , satisfying certain axioms. Note that there is a second reasonable notion of a monoidal module category, where the action $X\triangleright -$ is a monoidal functor, and this definition is not equivalent. Under the presence of a monoidal functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , compatibility of the monoidal product in ${\mathcal B}$ and the action of ${\mathcal C}$ on ${\mathcal B}$ is equivalent to the existence of a section to F, that is a monoidal functor $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ such that there is a monoidal natural isomorphism $F\circ G\simeq \mathrm {Id\,}.$

2 Preliminaries

Throughout this paper, $\mathbb {k}$ will denote an arbitrary field. We shall denote by $\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ the category of finite-dimensional $\mathbb {k}$ -vector spaces.

A finite category [Reference Etingof and Ostrik10] is an abelian $\mathbb {k}$ -linear category such that it has only a finite number of isomorphism classes of simple objects, Hom spaces are finite-dimensional $\mathbb {k}$ -vector spaces, all objects have finite length, and every simple object has a projective cover. All these conditions are equivalent to requiring that the category is equivalent to the category of finite-dimensional representations of a finite-dimensional $\mathbb {k}$ -algebra.

If ${\mathcal M}, {\mathcal N}$ are categories and $F:{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal N}$ is a functor, we shall denote by $F^{\mathrm {{ra}}}, F^{\mathrm {{la}}}:{\mathcal N}\to {\mathcal M}$ its right and left adjoints, respectively. We shall denote by ${\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}$ the opposite category. If $f:M\to N$ is a morphism in ${\mathcal M}$ , sometimes we shall denote by $f^{\mathrm {{op}}}:N\to M$ the same map but understood as a morphism in ${\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}$ .

Any abelian $\mathbb {k}$ -linear category ${\mathcal M}$ has a canonical action of the category of finite-dimensional $\mathbb {k}$ -vector spaces

(2.1) $$ \begin{align} \bullet: \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}} \times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal M}. \end{align} $$

See, for example, [Reference Schauenburg23, Lemma 2.2.2]. Any additive $\mathbb {k}$ -linear functor $F:{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal N}$ between abelian $\mathbb {k}$ -linear categories respects the action of $\mathrm { vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , that is, there are natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}d_{V,M}:F(V \bullet M)\to V \bullet F(M),\end{align*} $$

$V\in \mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , $M\in {\mathcal M}$ , satisfying certain axioms.

From now on, all categories will be assumed to be finite abelian $\mathbb {k}$ -linear categories, and all functors will be additive $\mathbb {k}$ -linear. Here, $\mathbb {k}$ is an arbitrary field. All our proofs work in the presence of an associator, but for simplicity we assume in the presentation that the categories are strict.

3 Representations of tensor categories

3.1 Finite tensor categories

A finite tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ is a monoidal rigid category, with simple unit object $ \mathbf {1}\in {\mathcal C}$ . We refer to [Reference Etingof and Ostrik10] for more details on finite tensor categories. Without loss of generality, we shall assume that tensor categories in this work are strict.

If ${\mathcal C}, {\mathcal D}$ are monoidal categories, a monoidal functor is a functor $F:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal D}$ equipped with natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\xi_{A,B}:F(A){\otimes} F(B)\to F(A{\otimes} B),\end{align*} $$

such that

(3.1) $$ \begin{align} \xi_{A,B{\otimes} C} (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \xi_{B,C})=\xi_{A{\otimes} B, C} (\xi_{A,B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(C)}). \end{align} $$

If $(F,\xi ), (\widetilde {F}, \widetilde {\xi }):{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal D}$ are two monoidal functors, a monoidal natural transformation between F and $\widetilde {F}$ is a natural transformation $\alpha :F\to \widetilde {F}$ such that

(3.2) $$ \begin{align} \alpha_{A{\otimes} B} \xi_{A,B}=\widetilde{\xi}_{A,B} (\alpha_A{\otimes} \alpha_B), \end{align} $$

for any $A,B\in {\mathcal C}$ .

If ${\mathcal C}$ is a category, for any $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , we shall denote by

$$ \begin{align*}\mbox{ev}_X:X^*{\otimes} X\to \mathbf{1}, \quad \mbox{coev}_X: \mathbf{1}\to X{\otimes} X^*\end{align*} $$

the evaluation and coevaluation. By abuse of notation, we shall also denote by

$$ \begin{align*}\mbox{ev}_X:X{\otimes} {}^*X\to \mathbf{1}, \quad \mbox{coev}_X: \mathbf{1}\to {}^*X{\otimes} X\end{align*} $$

the evaluation and coevaluation for the left duals. We will use the following basic result. If $f:X\to Y$ is an isomorphism in ${\mathcal C}$ , then

(3.3) $$ \begin{align}\begin{aligned} (\mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^*X}{\otimes} f )\mbox{coev}_X&= ({}^*f{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_Y )\mbox{coev}_Y, \\\mbox{ev}_Y (f{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_Y)&=\mbox{ev}_X (\mathrm{id\,}_X{\otimes} {}^*f). \end{aligned}\end{align} $$

It is well known that for any pair of objects $X, Y\in {\mathcal C}$ , there are canonical natural isomorphisms

(3.4) $$ \begin{align} \phi^r_{X,Y}: Y^* {\otimes} X^* \to(X{\otimes} Y)^*, \end{align} $$
(3.5) $$ \begin{align} \phi^l_{X,Y}: {}^*Y {\otimes} {}^*X \to {}^*(X{\otimes} Y). \end{align} $$

These isomorphisms allow us to compute coevaluation and evaluation maps of duals; more precisely, we shall need the following identity:

(3.6) $$ \begin{align} \mbox{ev}_{{}^*V}= {}^*(\mbox{coev}_X) \phi^l_{{}^*X,X}. \end{align} $$

We are going to make use, very often, of the canonical natural isomorphisms

(3.7) $$ \begin{align}\begin{aligned} &\psi^Z_{X,Y}:\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(X{\otimes} {}^*Y,Z)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(X,Z{\otimes} Y),\\&\psi^Z_{X,Y}(f)=(f{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_Y)(\mathrm{id\,}_X{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_Y). \end{aligned}\end{align} $$

And, its inverse

(3.8) $$ \begin{align}\begin{aligned} \bar{\psi}^Z_{X,Y}:\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(X,Z{\otimes} Y)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(X{\otimes} {}^*Y,Z) \\\bar{\psi}^Z_{X,Y}(g)=(\mathrm{id\,}_Z{\otimes}\mbox{ev}_Y)(g{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*Y}). \end{aligned}\end{align} $$

We shall also need the following basic fact.

Lemma 3.1 For any pair $V,W\in {\mathcal C}$ , the evaluation of $V{\otimes } W$ is given by

(3.9) $$ \begin{align} \mbox{ev}_{V{\otimes} W} = \mbox{ev}_V(\mathrm{id\,}_V{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_W{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V})(\mathrm{id\,}_{V{\otimes} W} {\otimes} (\phi^l_{V,W})^{-1}). \end{align} $$

3.2 Module categories over tensor categories

A left module category over ${\mathcal C}$ is a category ${\mathcal M}$ together with a $\mathbb {k}$ -bilinear bifunctor $\rhd : {\mathcal C} \times {\mathcal M} \to {\mathcal M}$ , exact in each variable, endowed with natural associativity and unit isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}m_{X,Y,M}: (X\otimes Y)\triangleright M \to X\triangleright (Y\triangleright M), \ \ \ell_M: \mathbf{1} \triangleright M\to M.\end{align*} $$

These isomorphisms are subject to the following conditions:

(3.10)

for any $X, Y, Z\in {\mathcal C}, M\in {\mathcal M}$ , as well as

(3.11) $$ \begin{align} (\mathrm{id\,}_{X}\triangleright \ell_M)m_{X,\mathbf{1} ,M}=\mathrm{id\,}. \end{align} $$

Sometimes we shall also say that ${\mathcal M}$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module category or a representation of ${\mathcal C}$ .

Let ${\mathcal M}$ and ${\mathcal M}'$ be a pair of ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories. A module functor is a pair $(F,c)$ , where $F:{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal M}'$ is a functor equipped with natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}c_{X,M}: F(X\triangleright M)\to X\triangleright F(M),\end{align*} $$

for $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , $M\in {\mathcal M}$ , such that

(3.12)

for any $X, Y\in {\mathcal C}$ , $M\in {\mathcal M}$ , as well as

(3.13) $$ \begin{align} \ell_{F(M)} \,c_{ \mathbf{1} ,M} &=F(\ell_{M}). \end{align} $$

Module functors are composable, if ${\mathcal M}"$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and $(G,d): {\mathcal M}' \to {\mathcal M}"$ is another module functor, then the composition

(3.14) $$ \begin{align} (G\circ F, e): {\mathcal M} \to {\mathcal M}", \qquad e_{X,M} = d_{X,F(M)}\circ G(c_{X,M}) \end{align} $$

is also a module functor.

A natural module transformation, between module functors $(F,c)$ and $(G,d)$ , is a natural transformation $\theta : F \to G$ such that

(3.15) $$ \begin{align} d_{X,M}\theta_{X\triangleright M} = (\mathrm{id\,}_{X}\triangleright \theta_{M})c_{X,M}, \end{align} $$

for any $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , $M\in {\mathcal M}$ . The vector space of natural module transformations will be denoted by $\mathrm {Nat\,}_{\!m}(F,G)$ . Two module functors $F, G$ are equivalent if there exists a natural module isomorphism $\theta :F \to G$ . We denote by $\operatorname {Fun}_{{\mathcal C}}({\mathcal M}, {\mathcal M}')$ the category whose objects are module functors $(F, c)$ from ${\mathcal M}$ to ${\mathcal M}'$ and arrows module natural transformations.

Two ${\mathcal C}$ -modules ${\mathcal M}$ and ${\mathcal M}'$ are equivalent if there exist module functors $F:{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal M}'$ , $G:{\mathcal M}'\to {\mathcal M}$ , and natural module isomorphisms $\mathrm {Id\,}_{{\mathcal M}'} \to F\circ G$ , $\mathrm {Id\,}_{{\mathcal M}} \to G\circ F$ .

A module category will be called strict if isomorphisms m and l are identities. Any module category is equivalent to a strict one. We will often assume that the module category is strict without further mention.

A right module category over ${\mathcal C}$ is a category ${\mathcal M}$ equipped with an exact bifunctor $\triangleleft : {\mathcal M}\times {\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal M}$ and natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{m}_{M, X,Y}: M\triangleleft (X{\otimes} Y)\to (M\triangleleft X) \triangleleft Y, \quad r_M:M\triangleleft \mathbf{1}\to M\end{align*} $$

such that

(3.16)

as well as

(3.17) $$ \begin{align} (r_M\triangleleft \mathrm{id\,}_X) \widetilde{m}_{M, \mathbf{1}, X}= \mathrm{id\,}. \end{align} $$

If ${\mathcal M}, {\mathcal M}'$ are right ${\mathcal C}$ -modules, a module functor from ${\mathcal M}$ to $ {\mathcal M}'$ is a pair $(T, d)$ where $T:{\mathcal M} \to {\mathcal M}'$ is a functor and $d_{M,X}:T(M\triangleleft X)\to T(M)\triangleleft X$ are natural isomorphisms such that for any $X, Y\in {\mathcal C}$ , $M\in {\mathcal M}$ :

(3.18)

as well as

(3.19) $$ \begin{align} r_{T(M)} \,d_{ M, \mathbf{1}} &=T(r_{M}). \end{align} $$

3.3 The internal Hom

Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category and ${\mathcal M}$ be a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. For any pair of objects $M, N\in {\mathcal M}$ , the internal Hom is an object $\underline {\operatorname {Hom}}(M,N)\in {\mathcal C}$ representing the left exact functor

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal M}}(-\triangleright M,N):{\mathcal C}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\to \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}}.\end{align*} $$

This means that there are natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal C}}(X,\underline{\operatorname{Hom}}_{\mathcal M}(M,N))\simeq \operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal M}}(X\triangleright M,N).\end{align*} $$

The internal Hom for right ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories is defined similarly.

The next technical result will be needed later. Recall natural isomorphisms $\phi ^l$ defined in (3.5).

Lemma 3.2 Let ${\mathcal M}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category with action given by $\triangleleft : {\mathcal M}\times {\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal M}$ . If $(F,c):{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a module functor, then, for any $B\in {\mathcal M}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , the following diagrams commute.

(3.20)
(3.21)

Proof The proof follows by simply checking that morphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\mbox{ev}_{F(B\triangleleft X )} = \mbox{ev}_{F(B)}\big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_X{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,} \big)\big(c_{B,X}{\otimes} ( {}^*c_{B,X}\phi^l_{F(B),X})^{-1}\big),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\mbox{coev}_{F(B\triangleleft X )}= \big( {}^*c_{B,X}\phi^l_{F(B),X} {\otimes} c^{-1}_{B,X}\big)\big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}\big) \mbox{coev}_X\end{align*} $$

satisfy rigidity axioms.

4 The (co)end for module categories

In this section, we recall the notion of relative (co)ends, a tool developed in [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4] in the context of representations of tensor categories, generalizing the well-known notion of (co)ends in category theory.

Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category and ${\mathcal M}$ be a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Assume that ${\mathcal A}$ is a category and $S:{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal A}$ is a functor equipped with natural isomorphisms

(4.1) $$ \begin{align} \beta^X_{M,N}: S(M,X\triangleright N)\to S(X^*\triangleright M,N), \end{align} $$

for any $X\in {\mathcal C}, M,N\in {\mathcal M}$ . We shall say that $\beta $ is a prebalancing of the functor S. Sometimes we shall say that it is a ${\mathcal C}$ -prebalancing to emphasize the dependence on  ${\mathcal C}$ .

Definition 4.1 The relative end of the pair $(S,\beta )$ is an object $E\in {\mathcal A}$ equipped with dinatural transformations $\pi _M: E\xrightarrow {. .} S(M,M)$ such that

(4.2)

for any $X\in {\mathcal C}, M\in {\mathcal M}$ , and is universal with this property. This means that, if $\widetilde {E}\in {\mathcal A}$ is another object with dinatural transformations $\xi _M:\widetilde {E}\xrightarrow {. .} S(M,M)$ , such that they fulfill (4.2), there exists a unique morphism $h:\widetilde {E}\to E$ such that $\xi _M= \pi _M\circ h $ .

The relative end depends on the choice of the prebalancing. We will denote the relative end as $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta )$ , or sometimes simply as $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} S$ , when the prebalancing $\beta $ is understood from the context.

The relative coend of the pair $(S,\beta )$ is defined dually. This is an object $C\in {\mathcal A}$ equipped with dinatural transformations $\pi _M:S(M,M)\xrightarrow {. .} C$ such that

(4.3)

for any $X\in {\mathcal C}, M\in {\mathcal M}$ , universal with this property. This means that, if $\widetilde {C}\in {\mathcal A}$ is another object with dinatural transformations $\lambda _M: S(M,M) \xrightarrow {. .} \widetilde {C}$ such that they satisfy (4.3), there exists a unique morphism $g:C\to \widetilde {C}$ such that $g \circ \pi _M=\lambda _M$ . The relative coend will be denoted $\oint ^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta )$ , or simply as $\oint ^{M\in {\mathcal M}} S$ .

A similar definition can be made for right ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories. Let ${\mathcal A}$ be a category, and let ${\mathcal N}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category endowed with a functor $S:{\mathcal N}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal N}\to {\mathcal A}$ with a prebalancing

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{M,N}: S(M\triangleleft X, N)\to S(M, N\triangleleft {}^* X),\end{align*} $$

for any $M,N\in {\mathcal N}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ .

Definition 4.2 The relative end for S is an object $E\in {\mathcal A}$ equipped with dinatural transformations $\lambda _N:E\xrightarrow { .. } S(N,N)$ such that

(4.4)

for any $N\in {\mathcal N}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ . We shall also denote this relative end by $\oint _{N\in {\mathcal N}} (S, \gamma )$ .

Similarly, the relative coend is an object $C\in {\mathcal B}$ with dinatural transformations $\lambda _N: S(N,N)\xrightarrow { .. } C$ such that

(4.5)

for any $N\in {\mathcal N}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ . We shall also denote this relative coend by $\oint ^{N\in {\mathcal N}} (S, \gamma )$ .

In the next proposition, we collect some results about the relative (co)end that will be useful. The reader is referred to [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4, Proposition 3.3] and [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4, Proposition 4.2].

Proposition 4.3 Assume that ${\mathcal M}, {\mathcal N}$ are left ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories and that $S, \widetilde {S}:{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal A}$ are functors equipped with ${\mathcal C}$ -prebalancings

$$ \begin{align*}\beta^X_{M,N}: S(M,X\triangleright N)\to S(X^*\triangleright M,N),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\beta}^X_{M,N}: \widetilde{S}(M,X\triangleright N)\to \widetilde{S}(X^*\triangleright M,N),\end{align*} $$

$X\in {\mathcal C}, M,N\in {\mathcal M}$ . The following assertions holds:

  1. (i) Assume that the module ends $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta ), \oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} (\widetilde {S},\widetilde {\beta })$ exist and have dinatural transformations $\pi , \widetilde {\pi }$ , respectively. If $\gamma :S\to \widetilde {S}$ is a natural transformation such that

    (4.6) $$ \begin{align} \widetilde{\beta}^X_{M,N} \gamma_{(M,X\triangleright N)}=\gamma_{(X^*\triangleright M,N)} \beta^X_{M,N}, \end{align} $$
    then there exists a unique map $\widehat {\gamma }: \oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\beta )\to \oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} (\widetilde {S},\widetilde {\beta })$ such that
    $$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\pi}_M \widehat{\gamma}= \gamma_{(M,M)} \pi_M\end{align*} $$
    for any $M\in {\mathcal M}$ . If $\gamma $ is a natural isomorphism, then $\widehat {\gamma }$ is an isomorphism.
  2. (ii) For any pair of ${\mathcal C}$ -module functors $(F, c), (G, d):{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal N},$ the functor

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal N}}(F(-), G(-)): {\mathcal M}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}}\end{align*} $$
    has a canonical prebalancing given by
    (4.7) $$ \begin{align} \beta^X_{M,N}: \operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal N}}(F(M), G(X\triangleright N))\to \operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal N}}(F(X^*\triangleright M), G(N)) \end{align} $$
    $$ \begin{align*}\beta^X_{M,N}(\alpha)= (ev_X\triangleright \mathrm{id\,}_{G(N)}) m^{-1}_{X^*,X,G(N)} (\mathrm{id\,}_{X^*}\triangleright d_{X,N}\alpha)c_{X^*,M},\end{align*} $$
    for any $X\in {\mathcal C}, M, N\in {\mathcal M}$ . There is an isomorphism
    $$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{Nat\,}_{\!m}(F,G)\simeq \oint_{M\in {\mathcal M}} (\operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal N}}(F(-), G(-)), \beta).\end{align*} $$

The next result will be needed later. It follows from a combination of [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4, Proposition 3.3] (ii) and [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4, Lemma 3.6]. Let ${\mathcal M}$ be a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, then ${\mathcal N}={\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}$ is a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category with right action given by

$$ \begin{align*}M \triangleleft X= X^*\triangleright M.\end{align*} $$

Assume that ${\mathcal A}$ is a category equipped with a functor

$$ \begin{align*}S:{\mathcal N}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal N}\to {\mathcal A}\end{align*} $$

together with a prebalancing

$$ \begin{align*}\beta^X_{M,N}: S(M \triangleleft X, N)\to S(M,N \triangleleft {}^*X).\end{align*} $$

The functor

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal A}(S(-,-), U):{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}}\end{align*} $$

has a natural prebalancing

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{M,N}:\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal A}(S(M, N\triangleleft {}^* X), U)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal A}( S(M\triangleleft X, N),U),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{M,N}(f)=f\circ \beta^X_{M,N}.\end{align*} $$

The proof of the next statement is similar to the proof of [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4, Proposition 3.3(ii)].

Proposition 4.4 If the coend $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal N}} (S,\beta )$ exists, then for any object $U\in {\mathcal A}$ , the end $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} \operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal A}( S( -, -), U)$ exists, and there is an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\oint_{M\in {\mathcal M}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal A}(S( -, -),U)\simeq \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal A}( \oint^{M\in {\mathcal N}} (S,\beta), U).\end{align*} $$

Moreover, if $\oint _{M\in {\mathcal M}} \operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal A}(S( -, -),U)$ exists for any $U\in {\mathcal A}$ , then the coend $\oint ^{M\in {\mathcal N}} (S,\beta )$ exists.

The proof of the next result is completely analogous to the proof in the case of usual coend.

Lemma 4.5 Let ${\mathcal M}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, $S:{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal A}$ a functor equipped with a prebalancing $\gamma $ . If $F:{\mathcal A}\to {\mathcal A}'$ is a right exact functor, then there is an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}F(\oint^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S,\gamma))\simeq \oint^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (F\circ S,F(\gamma)).\end{align*} $$

We shall also need the next result.

Lemma 4.6 Let ${\mathcal M}, {\mathcal N}$ be right ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories, and let $(J,c):{\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal N}$ be an equivalence of ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories. Assume that $S:{\mathcal N}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal N}\to {\mathcal A}$ is a functor equipped with a prebalancing $\beta $ . The functor $S(J(-), J(-)):{\mathcal M}^{\mathrm {{op}}}\times {\mathcal M}\to {\mathcal A}$ has a prebalancing $\gamma $ given by

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^V_{M,N}=S(\mathrm{id\,}_{J(M)},c_{N,{}^*V})\beta^V_{J(M),J(N)}S(c^{-1}_{M,V},\mathrm{id\,}_{J(N)})\end{align*} $$

for any $M,N\in {\mathcal M}$ . There is an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\oint^{M\in {\mathcal M}} (S(J(-), J(-)),\gamma)\simeq \oint^{N\in {\mathcal N}} (S,\beta).\end{align*} $$

Proof We only sketch the proof. Let $\lambda _N:S(N,N)\to \oint ^{N\in {\mathcal N}} (S,\beta )$ be the associated dinatural transformations. If we define $\pi _M=\lambda _{J(M)}$ , for any $M\in {\mathcal M}$ , one can verify that these are dinatural transformations and they satisfy (4.5). Universality of $\pi $ follows from the universality of $\lambda $ and the fact that J is an equivalence of categories.

4.1 Existence of (co)ends

In this section, we shall prove that certain (co)ends exists. All these (co)ends will be used in subsequent sections. We shall use ideas from [Reference Shimizu24, Reference Shimizu25].

Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Since our definition of module category includes that the action is right exact in each variable, the hypothesis of [Reference Douglas, Schommer-Pries and Snyder9, Theorem 2.24] are fulfilled. This means that there exists an algebra $A\in {\mathcal C}$ such that

(4.8) $$ \begin{align} {\mathcal B}\simeq {}_{A}{\mathcal C} \end{align} $$

as module categories. Consider ${\mathcal C}$ as a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category with the regular action. We shall denote by $\mathrm {Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C})$ the category of right exact ${\mathcal C}$ -module functors. The functor

$$ \begin{align*}\Phi:{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}} \to \mathrm{Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C}),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\Phi(B)(D)= \underline{\operatorname{Hom}}(D,B)^*\end{align*} $$

is an equivalence of categories, since, under identification (4.8), the functor $\Phi $ is the composition of equivalences

$$ \begin{align*}({}_A{\mathcal C})^{\mathrm{{op}}} \xrightarrow{( -)^*} {\mathcal C}_A\xrightarrow{\, R \,} \mathrm{Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({}_{A}{\mathcal C},{\mathcal C}).\end{align*} $$

Here, $R: {\mathcal C}_{A} \to \mathrm {Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({}_A{\mathcal C},{\mathcal C})$ is the functor given by $R(V)(W)=V{\otimes }_{A} W.$ Let be $(F,c)\in \mathrm {Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C})$ . In particular, we have natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}c_{B,X}: F(B \triangleleft X)\to F(B) {\otimes} X,\end{align*} $$

for $B\in {\mathcal B}, X\in {\mathcal C}$ . Consider the functor

$$ \begin{align*}{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B},\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}(D, B)\mapsto D \triangleleft {}^*F(B).\end{align*} $$

This functor possesses a ${\mathcal C}$ -prebalancing

(4.9) $$ \begin{align} \gamma^V_{B,D}: D\triangleleft {}^*F(B \triangleleft V) \to D\triangleleft {}^*V{\otimes}{}^*F(B ), \end{align} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^V_{B,D}=\mathrm{id\,}_{D}\triangleleft (\phi^l_{F(B),V})^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Proposition 4.7 Let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. For any right exact ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , the coend

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{C}(F,c)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} (B \triangleleft {}^*F(B), \gamma)\in {\mathcal B},\end{align*} $$

exists. Moreover, the functor $(F,c)\mapsto \widetilde {C}(F,c)$ is a quasi-inverse of $\Phi $ .

Proof For any $D\in {\mathcal B}$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(\Phi(D), F)& \simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(\Phi(D)(B), F(B))\\ &\simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(\underline{\operatorname{Hom}}_{{\mathcal B}}(B,D)^*, F(B))\\ &\simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}( {}^*F(B), \underline{\operatorname{Hom}}_{{\mathcal B}}(B,D))\\ &\simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(B \triangleleft {}^*F(B), D)\\ &\simeq \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}( \oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} B \triangleleft {}^*F(B), D)\\ &=\operatorname{Hom}_{{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}}}(D, \oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} B \triangleleft {}^*F(B)). \end{align*} $$

The first isomorphism is Proposition 4.3(ii), and the fifth isomorphism is Proposition 4.4. Observe that, to prove the existence of the fourth isomorphism, one has to check that the natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}( {}^*F(B), \underline{\operatorname{Hom}}_{{\mathcal B}}(B,D)\simeq \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(B \triangleleft {}^*F(B), D)\end{align*} $$

commute with the respective prebalancings and then use Proposition 4.3(i). This calculation is left to the reader. This proves both that the coend $\widetilde {C}(F,c)$ exists and that the quasi-inverse of $\Phi $ is given by

$$ \begin{align*}\bar{\Phi}: \mathrm{Rex\,}_{\mathcal C}({\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C}) \to{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}},\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\bar{\Phi}(F,c)= \oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} (B \triangleleft {}^*F(B), \gamma).\\[-37pt] \end{align*} $$

For a pair of module functors $(F,c), (\widetilde F, \tilde c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , the functor

$$ \begin{align*}{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C},\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}(A,B)\mapsto \widetilde{F}(B){\otimes} {}^*F(A)\end{align*} $$

has a canonical prebalancing, given by

(4.10) $$ \begin{align}\begin{aligned} \beta^X_{A,B}& : \widetilde{F}(B){\otimes} {}^*F(A \triangleleft X) \to \widetilde{F}(B \triangleleft {}^*X){\otimes} {}^*F(A), \\\beta^X_{A,B}& =(\tilde{c}^{-1}_{B, {}^*X}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}_{\widetilde F(B)}{\otimes} (\phi^l_{F(A),X})^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{A,X})). \end{aligned}\end{align} $$

As a consequence of Lemma 4.5, one can apply $\widetilde F $ to the coend in Proposition 4.7. Thus, we get the next result.

Corollary 4.8 For any pair of right exact ${\mathcal C}$ -module functors $F, \widetilde F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , the coend

$$ \begin{align*}\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} (\widetilde F(B) {\otimes} {}^*F(B), \beta)\in {\mathcal B}\end{align*} $$

exists.

5 Hopf algebras in braided tensor categories

5.1 Hopf algebras in braided tensor categories

Let us briefly recall the notion of Hopf algebras in braided tensor categories, and how their corepresentation categories are again tensor categories. For more details, the reader is referred to [Reference Majid19, Reference Majid20, Reference Takeuchi26] and the references therein.

A braided tensor category is a pair $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ where ${\mathcal C}$ is a tensor category and $\sigma _{V,W}:V{\otimes } W\to W{\otimes } V$ is a braiding, that is, a family of natural isomorphisms satisfying

(5.1) $$ \begin{align} &\sigma_{V,U{\otimes} W}=(\mathrm{id\,}_U{\otimes} \sigma_{V,W})(\sigma_{V,U}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_W), \nonumber\\ &\sigma_{V{\otimes} U, W}=(\sigma_{V,W}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_U) (\mathrm{id\,}_V{\otimes} \sigma_{U,W}). \end{align} $$

Remark 5.1 Note that in the above axioms we are assuming that ${\mathcal C}$ is a strict tensor category.

The braiding fulfills the braid relation, whence the name. We illustrate this identity in terms of string diagrams, which we read bottom to top.

Definition 5.2 A bialgebra in ${\mathcal C}$ is a collection $(H,m,u,\Delta ,\varepsilon )$ , where $(H,m,u)$ is an algebra, $(H,\Delta ,\varepsilon )$ is a coalgebra, and $\Delta , \varepsilon $ are algebra morphisms. That is,

(5.2) $$ \begin{align} \Delta\circ m&=(m{\otimes} m) ({\mathrm{id\,}}{\otimes} \sigma_{H,H}{\otimes} {\mathrm{id\,}}) (\Delta{\otimes} \Delta),\end{align} $$
(5.3) $$ \begin{align} \Delta\circ u&= (u{\otimes} u), \end{align} $$
(5.4) $$ \begin{align} \varepsilon \circ m &= (\varepsilon{\otimes}\varepsilon), \end{align} $$
(5.5) $$ \begin{align} \varepsilon \circ u &= {\mathrm{id\,}}_ {\mathbf{1}}. \end{align} $$

We illustrate the first identity:

If H is a bialgebra, then the space $\operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal C}(H,H)$ has a convolution product with unit given by $u\circ \varepsilon $ . If the identity $\mathrm {id\,}_H$ has an inverse S under the convolution product, then H is a Hopf algebra, and S is called the antipode. The next theorem is well known (see, for example, [Reference Majid19]).

Theorem 5.3 If H is a Hopf algebra in a braided tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ , then the category of left H-comodules ${}^H{\mathcal C}$ is a tensor category. Moreover, if ${\mathcal C}$ is a finite tensor category, then ${}^H{\mathcal C}$ is also a finite tensor category, and the forgetful functor $f:{}^H{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ is an exact faithful monoidal functor.

The tensor product of two left H-comodules is given as follows: if $(V,\rho _V)$ , $(W, \rho _W)$ are objects in ${}^H{\mathcal C}$ , then the tensor product $V{\otimes } W$ in ${\mathcal C}$ has a left H-comodule structure given by

(5.6) $$ \begin{align}\rho_{V{\otimes} W}= (m{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{V{\otimes} W})(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} \sigma_{V,H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_W)(\rho_V{\otimes} \rho_W). \end{align} $$

If $(V, \rho _V)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ , then ${}^*V\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ . The coaction is given by

(5.7) $$ \begin{align} \rho_{{}^*V}=\big((S{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\sigma_{{}^*V,H}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_V\big)\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} \rho_V{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}\big)\big(\mbox{coev}_V{\otimes}\mathrm{ id\,}_{{}^*V}\big). \end{align} $$

The coaction of the right dual $V^*$ is defined similarly.

For any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , we can endow V with a trivial H-comodule structure given by

$$ \begin{align*}\rho^t_V:V\to H{\otimes} V, \quad \rho^t_V=u{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V.\end{align*} $$

5.2 Yetter–Drinfeld modules

Let H be a finite-dimensional Hopf algebra in $\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ . Then we shall denote by ${}^H_H{\mathcal YD}$ the category of finite-dimensional Yetter–Drinfeld modules. An object $V\in {}^H_H{\mathcal YD}(\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}})$ is a left H-module $\cdot :H{\otimes _{\mathbb {k}}} V\to V$ and a left H-comodule $\lambda :V\to H{\otimes _{\mathbb {k}}} V$ such that

(5.8) $$ \begin{align} \lambda(h\cdot v)=h_{\left( 1 \right)} v_{\left( -1 \right)} {\mathcal S}(h_{\left( 3 \right)}){\otimes} h_{\left( 2 \right)}\cdot v_{\left( 0 \right)}, \end{align} $$

for any $h\in H, v\in V$ . If $V\in {}^H_H{\mathcal YD}(\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}})$ , the map $\sigma _X: V{\otimes _{\mathbb {k}}} X\to X{\otimes _{\mathbb {k}}} V$ , given by $\sigma _X(v{\otimes } x)=v_{\left ( -1 \right )}\cdot x{\otimes } v_{\left ( 0 \right )}$ , is a half-braiding for V.

This notion had been generalized in [Reference Bespalov3] to Hopf algebras H inside a braided tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ :

Definition 5.4 Let H be a Hopf algebra in a braided tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ . Then an H-H-Yetter–Drinfeld module V is an object $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , together with a structure of H-module $m:H\otimes V\to V$ and structure of H-comodule in $\rho :V\to H\otimes V$ in the tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ , compatible in the following way:

The category ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})$ consists of Yetter–Drinfeld modules and of H-linear and H-colinear morphisms. It becomes a tensor category with the usual tensor product of H-modules and H-comodules $V\otimes W$ . An useful feature of this tensor category is that it admits, by construction, a braiding

$$ \begin{align*} c_{(V, m_V, \rho_V), (W, m_W, \rho_W)} &: V \otimes W \rightarrow W \otimes V \end{align*} $$

which is given on objects $(V, m_V, \rho _V)$ and $(W, m_W, \rho _W)$ by

$$ \begin{align*} c_{(V, m_V, \rho_V), (W, m_W, \rho_W)} &:= (\rho_W \otimes \mathrm{id\,}_V ) \circ (\mathrm{id\,}_H \otimes c_{V,W} ) \circ (\rho_V \otimes \mathrm{id\,}_W ) \end{align*} $$

and is invertible if H has a bijective antipode

$$ \begin{align*} (c_{(V, m_V, \rho_V), (W, m_W, \rho_W)} )^{-1} &:= c^{-1}_{V,W} \circ (m_W \otimes \mathrm{id\,}_V ) \circ (c^{-1}_{H,W} \otimes \mathrm{id\,}_V ) \\ &\circ (\mathrm{id\,}_W \otimes S^{-1} \otimes \mathrm{id\,}_V ) \circ (\mathrm{id\,}_W \otimes \rho_V ). \end{align*} $$

If ${\mathcal C}$ is rigid, then the dual object in ${\mathcal C}$ with the standard dual action and coaction gives a dual object in ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})$ . The structure is summarized in the following statement proven in [Reference Bespalov3].

Theorem 5.5 Let H be a Hopf algebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . The Yetter–Drinfeld modules over H in ${\mathcal C}$ have a natural structure of a braided tensor category ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})$ . If ${\mathcal C}$ is rigid, then so is ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})$ .

Recall that the Drinfeld center $\mathcal {Z}(\mathcal {B})$ is a braided tensor category associated with any tensor category $\mathcal {B}$ . The construction of Yetter–Drinfeld modules gives a realization of a special case of the construction of a relative Drinfeld center $\mathcal {Z}_{\mathcal C}(\mathcal {B})$ , a braided tensor category associated with any tensor category $\mathcal {B}$ with a braided subcategory ${\mathcal C}\hookrightarrow \mathcal {Z}(\mathcal {B})$ . More precisely, we have

$$ \begin{align*}{^H_H}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C})=\mathcal{Z}_{\mathcal C}({^H}{\mathcal C}).\end{align*} $$

6 Monoidal module categories

Assume that ${\mathcal C}$ , ${\mathcal B}$ tensor categories. We shall define what means that a tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ acts on ${\mathcal B}$ .

Definition 6.1 We call ${\mathcal B}$ a monoidal left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category if ${\mathcal B}$ is a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, with action given by $\triangleright :{\mathcal C}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B}, $ such that $ \mathbf {1}\triangleright \mathbf {1}\simeq \mathbf {1},$ and there are natural isomorphisms $l_{X,B}: X \triangleright B\xrightarrow {\;\simeq \; } (X\triangleright \mathbf {1}){\otimes } B,$ for any $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , such that

(6.1) $$ \begin{align} l_{ \mathbf{1}, B}=\mathrm{id\,}_B, \quad l_{X, \mathbf{1}}=\mathrm{id\,}_{X\triangleright \mathbf{1}}, \end{align} $$
(6.2)

for any $X, Y\in {\mathcal C}$ , $B\in {\mathcal B}$ . Similarly, we shall say that ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, with action $\triangleleft :{\mathcal B}\times {\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}, $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\mathbf{1}\triangleleft \mathbf{1}\simeq \mathbf{1},\end{align*} $$

and there are natural isomorphisms $l_{B,X}: B \triangleleft X\to B{\otimes } ( \mathbf {1} \triangleleft X),$ such that for any $X, Y\in {\mathcal C}$ , $B\in {\mathcal B}$ ,

(6.3) $$ \begin{align} l_{ B, \mathbf{1}}=\mathrm{id\,}_B, \quad l_{ \mathbf{1}, X}=\mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft X }, \end{align} $$
(6.4)

Example 6.2

  1. (i) Any tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ is a monoidal $\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ -module category, with the canonical action

    $$ \begin{align*} \bullet: \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}} \times {\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}. \end{align*} $$
  2. (ii) Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category. Any tensor subcategory ${\mathcal D}$ acts on ${\mathcal C}$ by

    $$ \begin{align*}X \triangleright Y=X{\otimes} Y.\end{align*} $$
    In particular, any tensor category acts on itself.
  3. (iii) Let $({\mathcal C}, \sigma )$ be a braided tensor category and ${\mathcal D}\subseteq {\mathcal C}$ be a tensor subcategory. Then ${\mathcal D}^{\mathrm {{rev}}}$ acts on ${\mathcal C}$ as

    $$ \begin{align*}X \triangleright Y=Y{\otimes} X.\end{align*} $$
    In this case, $l_{X,B}=\sigma _{B,X}$ .
  4. (iv) Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category and $C\in {\mathcal C}$ be a coalgebra. Then the category ${}^C{\mathcal C}$ , of left C-comodules in ${\mathcal C}$ , is a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. The action is given as follows. If $(W,\rho )\in {}^C{\mathcal C}$ , then $W \triangleleft Y=W{\otimes } Y$ , where the coaction on $W{\otimes } Y$ is given by $\rho {\otimes } \mathrm {id\,}_Y.$

Definition 6.3 If ${\mathcal B}$ , ${\mathcal B}'$ are right monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories, a monoidal module functor is a collection $(F,c,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B}'$ where $(F,c)$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor, $(F, \xi )$ is a monoidal functor, and equation

(6.5) $$ \begin{align} l_{F(B),V}\, c_{B,V}= (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}) \xi^{-1}_{B, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V} F(l_{B,V}) \end{align} $$

is fulfilled for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ .

6.1 Sections of monoidal functors

Definition 6.4 Let ${\mathcal C}, {\mathcal B}$ be tensor categories. If $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a tensor functor, a section to F is a right exact tensor functor $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ such that $F\circ G\simeq \mathrm {Id\,}_{\mathcal C}$ as monoidal functors.

Example 6.5

  1. (1) Any (linear) tensor functor $F:{\mathcal B} \to \mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ has a canonical section given by

    $$ \begin{align*}G:\mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}} \to {\mathcal B},\end{align*} $$
    $$ \begin{align*}G(V)= V \bullet \mathbf{1}.\end{align*} $$

    Here, the action $\bullet :\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B}$ is the one presented in (2.1).

  2. (2) The previous example can be generalized to other kinds of fiber functors. If ${\mathcal C}$ is a tensor category that acts on another tensor category ${\mathcal B}$ , then any monoidal functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ that is also a ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor has a section given by $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ , $G(V)=V\triangleright \mathbf {1}$ . See Proposition 6.6 below.

  3. (3) If $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ is a braided tensor category and $H\in {\mathcal C}$ is a Hopf algebra with unit given by $u: \mathbf {1}\to H$ , then the forgetful functor $f: {}^H{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ has a section given by $G:{\mathcal C}\to {}^H{\mathcal C}$ , $G(V)=(V,\rho ^t_V)$ . Here, $\rho ^t_V=u{\otimes } \mathrm {id\,}_V$ is the trivial comodule structure.

  4. (4) Let H be a Hopf algebra and R be a Hopf algebra in the category of Yetter–Drinfeld modules ${}^H_H{\mathcal YD}$ . Consider the corresponding Hopf algebra obtained by bosonization $R\# H$ . Let us consider the functor

    $$ \begin{align*}F:\operatorname{Rep}(R\# H)\to \operatorname{Rep}(H), \quad F(V)=V.\end{align*} $$
    The action of H on V is given by $h\cdot v= (1\# h)\cdot v$ . The functor F has a section given by $G:\operatorname {Rep}(H)\to \operatorname {Rep}(R\# H)$ given by $G(V)=V$ , where the action of $R\# H$ on V is given by
    $$ \begin{align*}(r\# h)\cdot v=\varepsilon(r) h\cdot v.\end{align*} $$
  5. (5) Let $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ be a braided tensor category. The forgetful functor from the center of ${\mathcal C}$ , $f :Z({\mathcal C})\to {\mathcal C}$ , has a section given by the inclusion ${\mathcal C} \hookrightarrow Z({\mathcal C})$ , $V\mapsto (V,\sigma )$ .

Proposition 6.6 Let ${\mathcal B}, {\mathcal C}$ be tensor categories, and let $(F,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be a monoidal functor. The following notions are equivalent:

  1. (i) The functor F has a section.

  2. (ii) ${\mathcal B}$ is a right monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category (in the sense of Definition 6.1) and F is a monoidal module functor.

Proof Let us only give a sketch of the proof. (i) implies (ii): assume that $(G, \zeta ):{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal section to F. Let $\alpha :F\circ G\to \mathrm {Id\,}$ be a natural monoidal isomorphism. Define the right action of ${\mathcal C}$ on ${\mathcal B}$ as

$$ \begin{align*}B \triangleleft V:= B{\otimes} G(V),\end{align*} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . The associativity of this action is given by

$$ \begin{align*}m_{B,V,W}: B \triangleleft (V{\otimes} W)\to (B \triangleleft V) \triangleleft W,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}m_{B,V,W}= \mathrm{id\,}_B{\otimes} \zeta^{-1}_{V,W},\end{align*} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V, W\in {\mathcal C}$ . Turns out that ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal module category with isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}l_{B,V}: B \triangleleft V\to B{\otimes} ( \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}l_{B,V}=\mathrm{id\,}_{B{\otimes} G(V)}.\end{align*} $$

With this action, F is a module functor. The module structure of the functor F is given by

$$ \begin{align*}c_{B,V}:F(B \triangleleft V)\to F(B){\otimes} V,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}c_{B,V}= (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \alpha_V) \xi^{-1}_{B,G(V)} F(l_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Since $c_{ \mathbf {1},V}=\alpha _V$ , then it follows that equation (6.5) is fulfilled, that is, $(F,\xi , c)$ is a monoidal module functor.

Let us prove now that (ii) implies (i): assume that $(F,\xi , c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor. Define $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ , $G(V)= \mathbf {1} \triangleleft V $ . Axiom (6.4) implies that isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}l^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1}\triangleleft V, W }: G(V){\otimes} G(W) \to G(V{\otimes} W)\end{align*} $$

endow G with the structure of monoidal functor. Define natural isomorphisms $\alpha _V:F(G(V))=F( \mathbf {1} \triangleleft V)\to V$ , $\alpha _V=c_{ \mathbf {1}, V}$ . Let us check that they are monoidal natural isomorphisms. For this, we need to verify that equation

(6.6) $$ \begin{align} (c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, W})= c_{ \mathbf{1}, V{\otimes} W} F(l^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}) \xi_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W} \end{align} $$

is satisfied. Using that c satisfies diagram (3.18), it follows that the right-hand side of equation (6.6) is equal to

$$ \begin{align*} &=(c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_W) c_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V, W} F(l^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}) \xi_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}\\ &=(c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_W) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F( \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V)}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, W} ) \xi^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W} F(l_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}) F(l^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}) \xi_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}\\ &=(c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, W}). \end{align*} $$

The second equation follows from (6.5)

Remark 6.7 Constructions in Proposition 6.6 are reciprocal in the following sense. If ${\mathcal B}$ is a right monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ is the monoidal functor $G(V)= \mathbf {1}\triangleleft V$ , then one can endow ${\mathcal B}$ with a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module structure

$$ \begin{align*}B\blacktriangleleft V= B{\otimes} G(V),\end{align*} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Turns out, that the identity functor $\mathrm {Id\,}: ({\mathcal B}, \triangleleft )\to ({\mathcal B}, \blacktriangleleft )$ is an equivalence of module categories.

6.2 Some natural module transformations

It is known that natural transformations between additive functors are additive. For example, if $(F,\xi )$ is an additive monoidal functor, then natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\xi_{A,B}:F(A){\otimes} F(B)\to F(A{\otimes} B)\end{align*} $$

are additive in each variable. In this section, we shall study what happens when F is a monoidal module functor. We aim at proving that $\xi $ is a module natural transformation in the second variable.

Lemma 6.8 If ${\mathcal B}$ is a right monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, then for any $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , the functor $L_A:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B}$ , $L_A(B)=A{\otimes } B$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor.

Proof For any $B\in {\mathcal B}, V\in {\mathcal C}$ , the module structure of the functor $L_A$ is given by

$$ \begin{align*}\eta_{B,V}: A{\otimes} (B \triangleleft V)\to (A{\otimes} B) \triangleleft V,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\eta_{B,V}= l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Let us prove that $\eta $ satisfies (3.18). Using that isomorphisms l satisfy diagram (6.4), it follows that for any $C\in {\mathcal B}$ and any $V, W\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have that

(6.7) $$ \begin{align} l^{-1}_{C, V{\otimes} W}= l^{-1}_{C\triangleleft V, W}(l^{-1}_{C,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W})(\mathrm{id\,}_C{\otimes} l_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}). \end{align} $$

On one hand, we have that

$$ \begin{align*} \eta_{B,V{\otimes} W}& = l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V{\otimes} W}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V{\otimes} W})\\ &= l^{-1}_{(A{\otimes} B)\triangleleft V, W}(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W})(\mathrm{id\,}_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes} l_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W}) (\mathrm{ id\,}_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes} l^{-1}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V,W})\\ &\quad (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W})(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B\triangleleft V,W})\\ & = l^{-1}_{(A{\otimes} B)\triangleleft V, W}(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}) (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W})(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B\triangleleft V,W}). \end{align*} $$

The second equation follows from using (6.7). On the other hand,

$$ \begin{align*}(\eta_{B,V}\triangleleft \mathrm{id\,}_W) \eta_{B\triangleleft V, W}\end{align*} $$

is equal to

$$ \begin{align*} &=(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V} \triangleleft\mathrm{id\,}_W)(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}) l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} (B \triangleleft V), W} (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B \triangleleft V, W})\\ &=(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V} \triangleleft\mathrm{id\,}_W) l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B {\otimes} ( \mathbf{1}\triangleleft V), W} (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}) (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B \triangleleft V, W})\\ & =l^{-1}_{(A{\otimes} B)\triangleleft V, W}(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W}) (\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ \mathbf{1} \triangleleft W})(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B\triangleleft V,W}). \end{align*} $$

The second and third equalities follow from the naturality of l.

Proposition 6.9 Assume that ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and that $(F, c, \xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ a monoidal module functor. The following assertions hold.

  1. (i) The category ${\mathcal B}$ has structure of ${\mathcal C}$ -bimodule category.

  2. (ii) There are ${\mathcal C}$ -module functors

    $$ \begin{align*}H, \widetilde{H}:{\mathcal B}\boxtimes_{\mathcal C} {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}\end{align*} $$
    such that
    $$ \begin{align*}H(A\boxtimes B)=F(A{\otimes} B), \quad \widetilde{H}(A\boxtimes B)=F(A){\otimes} F(B),\end{align*} $$
    for any $A, B\in {\mathcal B}$ .
  3. (iii) The monoidal structure of the functor F defines a natural module isomorphism $\xi :\widetilde {H} \to H$ .

Proof (i). From Proposition 6.6, there is a section $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ of the functor F. Define the left action $\triangleright :{\mathcal C}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal B}$ as $V\triangleright B=G(V){\otimes } B$ . With this action, ${\mathcal B}$ becomes a ${\mathcal C}$ -bimodule category. Thus, we can consider the Deligne tensor product over ${\mathcal C}$ , ${\mathcal B}\boxtimes _{\mathcal C} {\mathcal B}$ . This category has an obvious right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category structure.

One can prove that functors ${\mathcal B}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ given by

$$ \begin{align*}(A,B)\mapsto F(A{\otimes} B), \quad (A,B)\mapsto F(A){\otimes} F(B)\end{align*} $$

are ${\mathcal C}$ -balanced, thus defining functors H and $\widetilde {H}$ . The (right) ${\mathcal C}$ -module structure of the functor $\widetilde {H}$ is the one inherited from the functor F. The module structure of the functor H is more involved. One can prove that natural transformations

$$ \begin{align*}e_{A,B,V}: F(A{\otimes} (B\triangleleft V))\to F(A{\otimes} B) {\otimes} V,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}e_{A,B,V}= c_{A{\otimes} B, V} F(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}))\end{align*} $$

are ${\mathcal C}$ -balanced, thus defining natural transformations

$$ \begin{align*}e_{X,V}: H(X\triangleleft V)\to H(X)\triangleleft V,\end{align*} $$

for any $X\in {\mathcal B}\boxtimes _{\mathcal C} {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . One can prove also that $(H,e)$ is a module functor. Note that e is the module structure resulting from the composition of module structures of F and the functor $L_A$ , presented in Lemma 6.8. This proves (ii).

(iii). To prove that $\xi $ is a natural module transformation in the second variable, we need to verify that the diagram

(6.8)

is commutative for any $A, B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Here,

$$ \begin{align*}e_{A,B,V}= c_{A{\otimes} B, V} F(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V})).\end{align*} $$

We have

$$ \begin{align*} e_{A,B,V} &\xi_{A,B\triangleleft V}= c_{A{\otimes} B, V} F(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}))\xi_{A,B\triangleleft V}\\ &=(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}) \xi^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, \mathbf{1}\triangleleft V} F(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}) \xi_{A,B\triangleleft V}\\ &=(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}) \xi^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, \mathbf{1}\triangleleft V} \xi_{A,B{\otimes} ( \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V)}(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} F(l_{B,V}))\\ &=(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, V}) (\xi_{A,B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F( \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \xi^{-1}_{B, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V}) (\mathrm{ id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} F(l_{B,V}))\\ &=(\xi_{A,B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ V}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} c_{ \mathbf{1}, V})\xi^{-1}_{B, \mathbf{1} \triangleleft V} F(l_{B,V})) \\ &=(\xi_{A,B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ V}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} c_{B, V}). \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from (6.5), the third equality follows from the naturality of $\xi $ , and the fourth one follows from (3.1). The last equality follows from (6.5).

7 Fiber functors and reconstruction results

It is a classical result that, out of a fiber functor, which is a monoidal, exact, and faithful functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to \mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , one can reconstruct a (usual) Hopf algebra H such that ${\mathcal B}$ is monoidally equivalent to the category of left H-comodules. We shall generalize these reconstruction theorems for a fiber functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , where ${\mathcal C}$ is an arbitrary braided tensor category acting monoidally on ${\mathcal B}$ . The reconstruction of the Hopf algebra from these data will be described in a similar way as the case ${\mathcal C}=\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ . See, for example, [Reference Majid19, Reference Schauenburg23]. The main new ingredient will be the use of the relative coend, introduced in [Reference Bortolussi and Mombelli4], and the splitting condition, that is, the existence of a section $G:{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal B}$ of F. While dealing with the relative (co)end, the primary new challenge will be demonstrated that some dinatural transformations satisfy equation (4.5).

7.1 Coalgebras constructed from a coend

Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. For the rest of this section, $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ will denote a right exact module functor.

Consider the functor

$$ \begin{align*}S^F:{\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\times {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C},\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}S^F(A,B)=F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(A).\end{align*} $$

This functor has a canonical prebalancing given by

(7.1) $$ \begin{align} &\beta^X_{A,B}: F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(A \triangleleft X) \to F(B \triangleleft {}^*X){\otimes} {}^*F(A), \nonumber\\ &\beta^X_{A,B}=(c^{-1}_{B, {}^*X}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(A)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} (\phi^l_{F(A),X})^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{A,X})). \end{align} $$

We define

$$ \begin{align*}C(F,c)=C(F)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} (S^F,\beta)= \oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B).\end{align*} $$

Let $\pi _B:F(B){\otimes } {}^*F(B)\to C(F)$ be the associated dinatural transformations. Existence of this coend follows from Corollary 4.8. The following lemma is a generalization of [Reference Schauenburg23, Lemma 2.1.9]. Recall that for any $M, N\in {\mathcal B}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have natural isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}\psi^V_{F(M),F(N)}:\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(M){\otimes} {}^*F(N),V)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(M),V{\otimes} F(N))\end{align*} $$

described in (3.7).

Lemma 7.1 The functor $V\mapsto \mathrm {Nat\,}_{\! m}(F, V{\otimes } F)$ is represented by $C(F)$ . That is, for any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , there are natural isomorphisms

(7.2) $$ \begin{align} &\omega: \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(C(F),V)\to \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(F, V{\otimes} F), \nonumber\\ &\omega(g)_B= (g{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)})\psi^{C(F)}_{F(B),F(B)}(\pi_B). \end{align} $$

Proof Fix some object $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . The functor $V{\otimes } F$ is a right module functor, then we can consider the prebalancing of the functor

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F( -),V{\otimes} F(- )): {\mathcal B}\times {\mathcal B}^{\mathrm{{op}}}\to \mathrm{vect\,}_{\mathbb{k}},\end{align*} $$

given by

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{B,N} :\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(N\triangleleft {}^*X),V{\otimes} F(B ))\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(N ),V{\otimes} F(B\triangleleft X)),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{N,B}(f)=(\mathrm{id\,}_V{\otimes} c_{B, X})(f{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_X) (c^{-1}_{N, {}^*X}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_X)(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(N)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_X).\end{align*} $$

Note that here we are considering ${\mathcal B}^{\mathrm {{op}}}$ as a left ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, with action $X\triangleright B:=B\triangleleft {}^*X$ . Proposition 4.3(ii) tells us that there is an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} (\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B),V{\otimes} F(B)), \gamma) \simeq \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(F, V{\otimes} F).\end{align*} $$

From the proof of Proposition 4.4, one can see that the dinatural transformations of the end $\oint _{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes } {}^*F(B),V)$ are given by

$$ \begin{align*}\widehat{\pi}_B:\oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\widehat{\pi}_B(g)= g\circ \pi_B.\end{align*} $$

Here, we are using identification

$$ \begin{align*}\oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V)= \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V).\end{align*} $$

It follows by a straightforward computation that

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^X_{M,N} (\psi^V_{F(M\triangleleft {}^*X ),F(N )}(f))=\psi^V_{F(M ),F(N\triangleleft X)}(f\circ \beta^X_{N,M} ),\end{align*} $$

for any $M, N\in {\mathcal B}$ and any $f\in \operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal B}(F(M \triangleleft {}^*X){\otimes } {}^*F(N ),V)$ . This implies, using Proposition 4.3(i) that, for any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , there exists an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\widehat{\psi}^V:\oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V)\to \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B),V{\otimes} F(B)),\end{align*} $$

such that $\mu _B\circ \widehat {\psi }^V= \psi ^V_{F(B),F(B)}\circ \widehat {\pi }_B.$ For any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have that

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(C(F),V)&\simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B),V)\\ &\simeq \oint_{B\in {\mathcal B}} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(F(B),V{\otimes} F(B))\\ &\simeq \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(F, V{\otimes} F). \end{align*} $$

The first isomorphism is Proposition 4.4. Tracing this chain of isomorphisms, one can see that the composition coincides with $\omega $ defined by equation (7.2).

Proposition 7.2 Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Let $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be a right exact module functor. The object $C(F)\in {\mathcal C}$ has a coalgebra structure $\Delta :C(F)\to C(F){\otimes } C(F)$ , $\varepsilon :C(F)\to \mathbf {1}$ determined by diagrams

(7.3)
(7.4)

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ .

Proof It follows by a straightforward computation that the maps

$$ \begin{align*}\mbox{ev}_{F(B)}:F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)\to \mathbf{1},\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}(\pi_B{\otimes} \pi_B )(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)} {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}): F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)\to C(F){\otimes} C(F)\end{align*} $$

are dinatural maps. It follows from diagram (3.20) that $ \mbox {ev}_{F(B)}$ satisfies (4.5). It follows from diagram (3.21) and the fact that $\pi $ satisfies (4.5) that $(\pi _B{\otimes } \pi _B )(\mathrm {id\,}{\otimes } \mbox {coev}_{F(B)} {\otimes }\mathrm {id\,})$ also satisfies equation (4.5). Whence, the existence of $\Delta $ and $\varepsilon $ follows from the universal property of the relative coend.

The proof that $(C(F),\Delta , \varepsilon )$ is a coalgebra is standard, and it follows from diagrams (7.3) and (7.4).

Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let $C\in {\mathcal C}$ be a coalgebra. The category ${}^C{\mathcal C}$ , of left C-comodules in ${\mathcal C}$ , is a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. The action is given as follows. If $(W,\rho )\in {}^C{\mathcal C}$ , then $W \triangleleft Y=W{\otimes } Y$ , where the coaction on $W{\otimes } Y$ is given by $\rho {\otimes } \mathrm {id\,}_Y.$ The forgetful functor $f:{}^C{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor. The next result says that the coalgebra reconstructed from the forgetful functor f coincides with C.

In this case, the functor $S^f$ has a prebalancing given by

$$ \begin{align*}\beta^X_{A,B}=\mathrm{id\,}_B{\otimes} (\phi^l_{A,X})^{-1},\end{align*} $$

for any $A, B\in {}^C{\mathcal C}$ , $X\in {\mathcal C}$ .

Lemma 7.3 There exists an isomorphism of coalgebras $C(f)\simeq C$ in ${\mathcal C}$ .

Proof In this particular case, if $T\in {\mathcal C}$ is an object, and $\lambda _W:W{\otimes } {}^*W\to T$ is a dinatural transformation, equation (4.5) writes as

(7.5) $$ \begin{align} \lambda_{W{\otimes} {}^*V}(\mathrm{id\,}_W{\otimes} (\phi^l_{W{\otimes} {}^*V,V})^{-1}) =\lambda_W (\mathrm{id\,}_W{\otimes} {}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_W{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_V)), \end{align} $$

for any $W\in {}^C{\mathcal C}, V\in {\mathcal C}.$

If $W\in {}^C{\mathcal C}$ has comodule structure given by $\rho _W\to C{\otimes } W$ , then we define $\pi _W:W{\otimes } {}^*W\to C,$ the morphisms given by $\pi _W=\bar {\psi }^C_{W,W}(\rho )$ . Recall that natural isomorphisms $\bar {\psi }$ were defined in (3.8). Maps $\pi _W$ are dinatural transformations, and they satisfy equation (7.5).

Let $A\in {\mathcal C}$ be another object, equipped with dinatural transformations $\lambda _W:W{\otimes } {}^*W\to A$ such that they satisfy equation (7.5). Define h as the composition

$$ \begin{align*}h: C\xrightarrow{\mathrm{id\,}_C{\otimes} {}^*\varepsilon}C{\otimes} {}^*C \xrightarrow{\lambda_C} A.\end{align*} $$

Since $\lambda $ is dinatural, and it satisfies (7.5), one can see that $h\circ \pi _W= \lambda _W$ . This proves that, indeed, $C(f)\simeq C$ .

Proposition 7.4 Let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and let $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be a right exact module functor. Set $C=C(F)$ the coalgebra defined in Proposition 7.2.

  1. 1. The functor $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ factorizes as

    (7.6)
    Here, $f:{}^C{\mathcal C} \to {\mathcal C}$ is the forgetful functor, and the functor $\widehat {F}$ is a ${\mathcal C}$ -module functor.
  2. 2. If F is exact (resp. faithful), then $\widehat {F}$ is exact (resp. faithful).

Proof 1. For any $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , define $\widehat {F}(A)=(F(A),\rho _A),$ where

$$ \begin{align*}\rho_A=\psi^C_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi_A):F(A)\to C{\otimes} F(A).\end{align*} $$

Using diagrams (7.3) and (7.4), one can prove that

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathrm{id\,}_C{\otimes} \rho_A)\rho_A=(\Delta{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\rho_A,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}(\varepsilon{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,})\rho_A=\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}.\end{align*} $$

2. Clearly, if F is faithful, then $\widehat {F}$ is faithful. Assume that F is left exact. Let $f:A\to B$ be a morphism in ${\mathcal B}$ with kernel $k=\ker f: K\to A$ . Since F is left exact, then $F(k)=\ker F(f)$ . We only need to prove that the morphism $F(k):F(K)\to F(A)$ is a map of C-comodules. That is, we need to prove the equality

(7.7) $$ \begin{align} (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} F(k)) \psi^C_{F(K),F(K)}(\pi_K)= \psi^C_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi_A) F(k). \end{align} $$

Using the naturality of $\psi $ , it follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \psi^C_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi_A) F(k)&= \psi^C_{F(K),F(A)}(\pi_A (F(k){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}))\\ &=\psi^C_{F(K),F(A)}(\pi_K (\mathrm{id\,} {\otimes} {}^*F(k)))\\ &=(\mathrm{id\,} {\otimes} F(k)) \psi^C_{F(K),F(K)}(\pi_K ). \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from the dinaturality of $\pi $ , and the third equality follows again by the naturality of $\psi $ . The proof that if F is right exact then $\widehat {F}$ is right exact follows similarly.

7.2 Some auxiliary results

In this section, we shall present some technical results that will be used later. In particular, these results will be used in the proof of our main result Theorem 7.7.

Let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be a module functor. To make calculations easier, we shall assume that the associativity of the ${\mathcal C}$ -module category ${\mathcal B}$ is trivial. Recall the relative coend

(7.8) $$ \begin{align} \widetilde{C}(F,c)=\widetilde{C}=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} B \triangleleft {}^*F(B)\in {\mathcal B} \end{align} $$

presented in Proposition 4.7. Let us denote by

$$ \begin{align*}\lambda_B:B \triangleleft {}^*F(B) \to \widetilde{C}(F,c)\end{align*} $$

the associated dinatural transformations. Analogous to the definition of $\Delta $ , given in (7.3), we shall define a map

(7.9) $$ \begin{align}\delta: \widetilde{C}(F,c)\to \widetilde{C}(F,c)\triangleleft C(F,c).\end{align} $$

Lemma 7.5 There exists a unique morphism $\delta : \widetilde {C}(F,c)\to \widetilde {C}(F,c)\triangleleft C(F,c)$ such that

(7.10)

Proof Let us denote $ d_{B,V}$ the following natural isomorphism:

$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}:{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)\to {}^*V{\otimes}{}^*F(B) ,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}= \big(\phi^l_{F(B), V} \big)^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Recall from equation (4.9) that the prebalancing used in the coend $\widetilde {C}(F,c)$ is given by

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^V_{B,D}: D\triangleleft {}^*F(B \triangleleft V) \to D\triangleleft {}^*V{\otimes}{}^*F(B ),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\gamma^V_{B,D}=\mathrm{id\,}_{D}\triangleleft d_{B,V}.\end{align*} $$

Using that c satisfies (3.18), it is not difficult to prove that

(7.11) $$ \begin{align} d_{B,{}^*V{\otimes} V }=(\phi^l_{{}^*V,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} d_{B,{}^*V}) d_{B\triangleleft {}^*V, V }, \end{align} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . The naturality of $\phi ^l$ and c implies that

(7.12) $$ \begin{align} F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V ))=({}^*(\mbox{coev}_V){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B)}) d_{B,{}^*V{\otimes} V }, \end{align} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Whence, using (3.6), it follows that

(7.13) $$ \begin{align} F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V )) d^{-1}_{B\triangleleft {}^*V, V }= (\mbox{ev}_{{}^*V}){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B)}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} d_{B,{}^*V}). \end{align} $$

In this case, if $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , a dinatural transformation $\nu _B: B\triangleleft {}^*F(B)\to A$ satisfies equation (4.5) if and only if

(7.14) $$ \begin{align} \nu_B \big( \mathrm{id\,}_B \triangleleft F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V )\big)= \nu_{B \triangleleft {}^*V} \gamma^V_{B\triangleleft {}^*V,B}. \end{align} $$

Using that dinatural transformations $\lambda $ and $\pi $ both satisfy (4.5) and using (7.13), it follows that dinatural transformation

$$ \begin{align*}(\lambda_B\triangleleft\,\pi_B) (\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft(\mbox{coev}_{F(B)} {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B)})\end{align*} $$

also satisfies (7.14). Now, existence of the map $\delta : \widetilde {C}(F,c)\to \widetilde {C}(F,c)\triangleleft C(F,c)$ satisfying (7.10) follows from the universal property of the relative coend.

For any $A, B\in {\mathcal B}$ and $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , define

(7.15) $$ \begin{align} &\widetilde{\psi}^V_{B,A}:\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(B\triangleleft {}^*V,A)\to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal B}(B,A \triangleleft V), \nonumber\\ &\widetilde{\psi}^V_{B,A}(f)=(f\triangleleft \mathrm{id\,}_V)(\mathrm{id\,}_B \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V). \end{align} $$

Compare with natural isomorphisms given in (3.7). For any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , define also

(7.16) $$ \begin{align} \widetilde{\rho}_B= \widetilde{\psi}^{F(B)}_{B,\widetilde{C}}(\lambda_B):B\to \widetilde{C} \triangleleft F(B). \end{align} $$

One could check that, using Lemma 4.5, whenever F is right exact, $F(\widetilde {C})=C$ . The dinatural transformations of $F(\widetilde {C})$ is given by $F(\lambda _B)$ . In particular, this implies that

(7.17) $$ \begin{align} c_{\widetilde{C},F(B)}F(\widetilde{\rho}_B)=\rho_B, \end{align} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ . Using definition of $\Delta :C\to C{\otimes } C$ given by diagram (7.2), one can see that

(7.18) $$ \begin{align} c_{\widetilde{C}, C} F(\delta)=F(\Delta). \end{align} $$

If $h_1, h_2:C{\otimes } F(B)\to C{\otimes } C{\otimes } F(B)$ are defined as

$$ \begin{align*}h_1=\mathrm{id\,}_C{\otimes} \rho_B, \quad h_2=\Delta{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)},\end{align*} $$

then it is a standard result that the kernel of the difference $h_1-h_2$ is $\rho _B$ . Using the above, we have the following.

Proposition 7.6 Assume that the module functor $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is faithful and exact. The map $\widetilde {\rho }_B:B\to \widetilde {C} \triangleleft F(B)$ is the kernel of the difference of morphisms

where $\widetilde {h}_1= \mathrm {id\,}_{\widetilde {C} } \triangleleft \rho _B$ and $\widetilde {h}_2= \delta \triangleleft \mathrm {id\,}_{F(B)}.$

Proof Note that we are using that F is right exact so that $F(\widetilde {C})=C$ . See Lemma 4.5. Using (7.17), (7.18), and the naturality of c, one can prove that

$$ \begin{align*}c_{\widetilde{C}, C{\otimes} F(B)} F(\widetilde{h}_1-\widetilde{h}_2)= (h_1-h_2) c_{\widetilde{C}, F(B)}.\end{align*} $$

This implies that $F (\widetilde {\rho }_B)=\ker F(\widetilde {h}_1-\widetilde {h}_2)=F(\ker \widetilde {h}_1-\widetilde {h}_2)$ , since F is also left exact. The result follows, since F is faithful.

7.3 Reconstruction results

The following theorem is one of our main results and is a generalization of [Reference Schauenburg23, Theorem 2.2.8].

Theorem 7.7 Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Let $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be an exact and faithful module functor. Let $C=\oint ^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes } {}^*F(B)\in {\mathcal C}$ be the relative coend coalgebra introduced in Proposition 7.2 and consider its category of comodules ${}^C{\mathcal C}$ . Then the functor F factorizes into an equivalence of ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories $\widehat {F}: {\mathcal B}\stackrel {\sim }{\longrightarrow } {}^C{\mathcal C}$ and the forgetful functor $f:{}^C{\mathcal C} \to {\mathcal C}$ :

(7.19)

Proof Recall that we denote by

$$ \begin{align*}\pi_A:F(A){\otimes} {}^*F(A)\to \oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)\end{align*} $$

the dinatural transformations of the relative coend $C(F)$ . The definition of the functor $\widehat {F}:{\mathcal B}\to {}^C{\mathcal C}$ was given in Proposition 7.4. Since F is faithful, $\widehat {F}$ is also faithful. We need to prove that $\widehat {F}$ is essentially surjective and full.

Let us prove first that $\widehat {F}$ is essentially surjective. Take $(M,\rho )\in {}^C{\mathcal C}$ . We endowed $C{\otimes } M$ structure of left C-comodule via $\Delta $ , then $\rho :M\to C{\otimes } M$ is actually a morphism in ${}^C{\mathcal C}$ . We begin with the observation that $(M,\rho )$ is the kernel (in ${}^C{\mathcal C}$ ) of the difference of morphisms

Recall from Proposition 7.4 that for any $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , the object $F(A)$ has a left H-comodule structure given by $\rho _A=\psi ^C_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi _A).$ Hence, for any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , the object $F(A){\otimes } V$ has a left comodule structure given by $\rho _A{\otimes }\mathrm {id\,}_V$ . The next claim will be crucial for the proof. To prove this claim, it is essential that the dinatural maps $\pi $ satisfy equation (4.5).

Claim 7.1 For any $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C},$ morphisms $c_{A,V}:F(A\triangleleft V)\to F(A){\otimes } V$ are C-comodule maps.

Proof of Claim

We need to prove that

$$ \begin{align*} (\psi^H_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi_A){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V)c_{A,V}=(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} c_{A,V}) \psi^H_{F(A\triangleleft V),F(A\triangleleft V)}(\pi_{A\triangleleft V}). \end{align*} $$

This equation is equivalent to

(7.20) $$ \begin{align} (\pi_A{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V}) (\mathrm{id\,} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V) c_{A,V}= (\pi_{A\triangleleft V}{\otimes} c_{A,V})(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A\triangleleft V)} ). \end{align} $$

Since $\pi $ satisfies equation (4.5), it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\pi_{A\triangleleft V}= \pi_A (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(F(\mathrm{id\,}_A \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_{V^*})) ) \big(\beta^{V^*}_{A\triangleleft V, A} \big)^{-1}.\end{align*} $$

Using the description of the prebalancing $\beta $ given in (4.10), we obtain that

(7.21) $$ \begin{align} \pi_{A\triangleleft V}& = \pi_A (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(c_{A\triangleleft V, V^*} F(\mathrm{id\,}_A \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_{V^*})) ) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \phi^l_{F(A\triangleleft V),V^*}) \nonumber\\ &\quad (c_{A,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(A\triangleleft V)}). \end{align} $$

It follows from the naturality of c that

$$ \begin{align*}c_{A, V{\otimes} V^*} F(\mathrm{id\,}_A \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_{V^*})=(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*}).\end{align*} $$

Using equation (3.18), it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}c_{A\triangleleft V, V^*} F(\mathrm{id\,}_A \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_{V^*})= (c^{-1}_{A,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{V^*} )(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*}).\end{align*} $$

Whence

(7.22) $$ \begin{align} \pi_{A\triangleleft V}&=\pi_A (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*})) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(c^{-1}_{A,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{V^*} ) ) \nonumber\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \phi^l_{F(A\triangleleft V),V^*})(c_{A,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(A\triangleleft V)})\\ &=\pi_A (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*})) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \phi^l_{V^*,F(A){\otimes} V} )\nonumber\\ & ( c_{A,V}{\otimes} {}^*(c^{-1}_{A,V}) ).\nonumber \end{align} $$

The second equality follows from the naturality of $\phi ^l$ . It follows by a tedious, but straightforward, computation that

(7.23) $$ \begin{align} \big({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_{V^*}){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big)&\big( \phi^l_{V^*,F(A){\otimes} V}{\otimes}\mathrm{ id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V}\big) \nonumber\\ &\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{V}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_{F(A){\otimes} V}\big)= \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{V}. \end{align} $$

Let us prove now equation (7.20). The right-hand side of (7.20) is equal to

$$ \begin{align*} &=(\pi_{A\triangleleft V} {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} ) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{A,V}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A\triangleleft V)}) \\ &= \big(\pi_A {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big) \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*}){\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V}\big)\\ & \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \phi^l_{V^*,F(A){\otimes} V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big) \big( c_{A,V} {\otimes} {}^*(c^{-1}_{A,V}){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big)\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{A,V}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A\triangleleft V)} {\otimes}\mbox{coev}_{F(A\triangleleft V)}) \\ &=\big(\pi_A {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big) \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} {}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{V^*}){\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V}\big)\\ & \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \phi^l_{V^*,F(A){\otimes} V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big) \big( c_{A,V}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A){\otimes} V} \big)\\ &=(\pi_A{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} V}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V) c_{A,V}. \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from equation (7.22), the third equality follows from (3.3), and the last equality follows from (7.23). This finishes the proof of the claim.

It follows from Claim that natural isomorphisms c endow the functor $\widehat {F}$ with structure of module functor. Let

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{C}=\widetilde{C}(F,c)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} B \triangleleft {}^*F(B)\in {\mathcal B}\end{align*} $$

be the object defined in Proposition 4.7, together with the map

$$ \begin{align*}\delta:\widetilde{C}\to \widetilde{C} \triangleleft C,\end{align*} $$

presented in diagram (7.10). Since $F(\widetilde {C})=C$ , it also follows from Claim 7.1 that there are C-comodule isomorphisms

$$ \begin{align*}F(\widetilde{C} \triangleleft M )\simeq C {\otimes} M,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}F(\widetilde{C} \triangleleft (C{\otimes} M) )\simeq C{\otimes} C {\otimes} M.\end{align*} $$

Hence, $(M,\rho )$ is the kernel of the difference of morphisms

where $h_1= \delta \triangleleft \mathrm {id\,}_M, h_2=\mathrm {id\,}_{\widetilde {C}} \triangleleft \rho $ . Since F is left exact, $(M,\rho )\simeq F( \ker (h_1-h_2))$ . This proves that $\widehat {F}$ is essentially surjective.

Let us prove now that $\widehat {F}$ is full. Take $A, B\in {\mathcal B}$ and $f:F(A)\to F(B)$ a C-comodule morphism. We have a commutative diagram

(7.24)

This implies that we have a commutative diagram

(7.25)

Where $h^A_1= \mathrm {id\,}_H{\otimes } \rho _A, h^A_2=\Delta {\otimes } \mathrm {id\,}_{F(A)}.$ Note that, by the universal property of the kernel, the map $f:F(A)\to F(B)$ is the unique morphism fitting in this diagram. Define

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{C}=\widetilde{C}(F,c)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} B \triangleleft {}^*F(B)\in {\mathcal B}.\end{align*} $$

See Proposition 4.7 for the definition of this coend. Using Proposition 7.6, for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , we have an exact sequence

$$ \begin{align*}0\to B\xrightarrow{\quad\widetilde{\rho}_B} \widetilde{C} \triangleleft F(B ) \xrightarrow{\quad \widetilde{h}\quad } \widetilde{C} \triangleleft (C{\otimes} F(B ) ), \end{align*} $$

where $\widetilde {h}_B=\mathrm {id\,}_{\widetilde {C} } \triangleleft \rho _B- \delta \triangleleft \mathrm {id\,}_{F(B)}.$ For the definition of $\delta $ and $ \widetilde {\rho }_B$ , see (7.9) and (7.10). Since f is a comodule morphism, by the universal property of the kernel, there exists a unique morphism $\eta $ that fits into the diagram

(7.26)

Applying F to this diagram, we obtain diagram (7.25). By the uniqueness of f, we get that $F(\eta )=f$ , proving that $\widehat {F}$ is full.

7.4 Hopf algebras in ${\mathcal C}$ constructed from a coend

In the case ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and the functor $(F,c,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is a monoidal module functor, one can endow the coalgebra $C=C(F)$ with a Hopf algebra structure. In this section, we shall explain the construction of the product and antipode on $C(F).$ The new hypothesis needed to construct such Hopf algebra is that ${\mathcal C}$ possesses a braiding.

To construct the product $m:C(F){\otimes } C(F)\to C(F)$ , we shall use ideas from [Reference Majid19]. In few words, we shall construct some natural module transformation $F{\otimes } F\to C(F){\otimes } F{\otimes } F$ and use Lemma 7.1 to find $m:C(F){\otimes } C(F)\to C(F)$ .

Lemma 7.8 Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a braided tensor category, ${\mathcal B}$ be a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and a monoidal module functor $(F,c,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ . Let us denote $ d_{B,V}$ the following natural isomorphism:

$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}:{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)\to {}^*V{\otimes}{}^*F(B) ,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}= \big(\phi^l_{F(B), V} \big)^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Then, for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have

(7.27) $$ \begin{align} d_{B,{}^*V{\otimes} V }=(\phi^l_{{}^*V,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} d_{B,{}^*V}) d_{B\triangleleft {}^*V, V }, \end{align} $$

Proof It follows by a straightforward calculation using (3.18).

Recall, from Proposition 6.9, the functors

$$ \begin{align*}H, \widetilde{H}:{\mathcal B}\boxtimes_{\mathcal C} {\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C},\end{align*} $$

determined by

$$ \begin{align*}H(A\boxtimes B)=F(A{\otimes} B), \quad \widetilde{H}(A\boxtimes B)=F(A){\otimes} F(B),\end{align*} $$

for any $A, B\in {\mathcal B}$ . Recall also that we are denoting by $\pi _B:F(B){\otimes } {}^*F(B)\to C(F)$ the dinatural transformations and the associated left $C(F)$ -coaction $\rho _B=\psi ^C_{F(B),F(B)}(\pi _B).$

Remark 7.9 In the case ${\mathcal C}=\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , the following proposition is trivial, since it only says that some natural transformation is additive. In the general case, where ${\mathcal C}$ is arbitrary, it is far from obvious, and it is a crucial step toward the reconstruction of the product in $C(F)$ . Its proof will highlight the importance of all required axioms.

For later use, $\pi $ has to satisfy equation (4.5), using prebalancing (7.1). This means that

(7.28) $$ \begin{align} \pi_{B\triangleleft V}=\pi_B \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} {}^*F(\mathrm{id\,}_B \triangleleft \mbox{coev}_{V^*}) \big)\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{B\triangleleft V,V^* }\big)\big(c_{B, V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)}\big). \end{align} $$

Proposition 7.10 Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a braided tensor category, ${\mathcal B}$ be a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and $(F,c,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be a monoidal module functor. The natural transformation $\mu : \widetilde {H} \to C(F){\otimes } \widetilde {H}$ determined by the composition

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{H}(A,B)\xrightarrow{ \xi_{A,B}} H(A, B)\xrightarrow{\rho_{A{\otimes} B } } C(F){\otimes} H(A, B)\xrightarrow{\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \xi^{-1}_{A,B}} C(F){\otimes} \widetilde{H}(A,B)\end{align*} $$

is a natural module transformation. That is, $\mu \in \mathrm {Nat\,}_{\! m}( \widetilde {H}, C(F){\otimes } \widetilde {H})$ .

Proof It follows from Proposition 6.9 that $\xi $ is a natural module transformation. Once it has been established that the diagram

(7.29)

is commutative, the proof will follow. Recall, from the proof of Proposition 6.9, that

$$ \begin{align*}e_{A,B,V}: F(A{\otimes} (B\triangleleft V))\to F(A{\otimes} B) {\otimes} V,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}e_{A,B,V}= c_{A{\otimes} B, V} F(l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V})).\end{align*} $$

We shall also keep the notation

$$ \begin{align*}\eta_{A,B,V}: A{\otimes} (B \triangleleft V)\to (A{\otimes} B) \triangleleft V,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\eta_{A,B,V}= l^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B, V}(\mathrm{id\,}_A{\otimes} l_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Using the definition of $\rho _A$ , one can see that diagram (7.29) amounts to

(7.30) $$ \begin{align} \begin{split} &(\mathrm{id\,}_{C(F)}{\otimes} e_{A,B,V})(\pi_{A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V)}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_{F(A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V)} )=\\ &=(\pi_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{_{F(A{\otimes} B)}{\otimes} V})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A{\otimes} B) }{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V)e_{A,B,V}. \end{split} \end{align} $$

Using the dinaturality of $\pi $ , one can see that the left-hand side of (7.30) is equal to

$$ \begin{align*}&=\big(\pi_{(A{\otimes} B )\triangleleft V} (F(\eta_{B,V}){\otimes} {}^*F(\eta^{-1}_{A,B,V})){\otimes} e_{A,B,V}\big)(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V)}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_{F(A{\otimes} B \triangleleft V)} )\\ &=\big(\pi_{(A{\otimes} B )\triangleleft V} {\otimes} c_{A{\otimes} B,V}\big) \big(F(\eta_{A,B,V}) {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F((A{\otimes} B) \triangleleft V)}\big)\\ &=\big(\pi_{(A{\otimes} B )\triangleleft V} {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}\big) \big(F(\eta_{A,B,V}) {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{A{\otimes} B,V}\big) \big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F((A{\otimes} B) \triangleleft V)}\big)\\ &=\big(\pi_{(A{\otimes} B )\triangleleft V} {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}\big) \big(F(\eta_{A,B,V}) {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} c_{A{\otimes} B,V}\big) \big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}{\otimes} c^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}\big)\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B\triangleleft V){\otimes} {}^*V{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V }) ( \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_V)\\ &=\big(\pi_{(A{\otimes} B )\triangleleft V} {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}\big) \big(F(\eta_{A,B,V}) {\otimes} d^{-1}_{A{\otimes} B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B){\otimes} V}\big)\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B\triangleleft V){\otimes} {}^*V}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_V ) ( \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes}\mbox{coev}_V)\\ &=(\pi_{A{\otimes} B}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{_{F(A{\otimes} B)}{\otimes} V})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A{\otimes} B)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A{\otimes} B) }{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V)e_{A,B,V}. \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from the definition of $e_{A,B,V}$ and (3.3), and the fourth follows from (3.21). The last equation follows by using (7.28) and (7.27).

Theorem 7.11 Assume that $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ is a braided tensor category, ${\mathcal B}$ is a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category, and $(F,c,\xi ):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ is an exact and faithful monoidal module functor with monoidal structure

$$ \begin{align*}\xi_{A,B}:F(A){\otimes} F(B)\to F(A{\otimes} B).\end{align*} $$

The relative coend coalgebra $C(F)$ from Theorem 7.7 has an algebra structure, with unit $u=\pi _{\mathbf {1}}$ and product $m:C(F){\otimes } C(F)\to C(F)$ determined by

(7.31) $$ \begin{align} \begin{split}&(m{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\pi_A{\otimes} \pi_B{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A){\otimes} F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \sigma_{F(A), F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)})\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)})=(\mathrm{id\,}_{C(F)}{\otimes} \xi^{-1}_{A,B})\rho_{A{\otimes} B} \xi_{A,B}, \end{split} \end{align} $$

for any $A,B\in {\mathcal B}$ . The object $C(F)$ becomes a bialgebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . Moreover, the equivalence of ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories $\widehat {F}:{\mathcal B}\to {}^{C(F)}{\mathcal C}$ is an equivalence of tensor categories.

Proof Recall from Lemma 7.3 that, if $f:{}^{C{\otimes } C}{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ is the forgetful functor, then $C(f)= C{\otimes } C$ and the dinatural transformations of this coend are given by

$$ \begin{align*}\lambda_{(W,\rho)}:W{\otimes} {}^*W\to C{\otimes} C,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\lambda_{(W,\rho)}= \bar{\psi}^{C{\otimes} C}_{W,W}(\rho).\end{align*} $$

Since the functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ factorizes as $F=f\circ \widehat {F}$ , then the functor $\widetilde {H}={\otimes }\circ (F\boxtimes F): {\mathcal B}\boxtimes _{\mathcal C}{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ factorizes as

Using Lemma 4.6, since $\widehat {F}$ is an equivalence of right ${\mathcal C}$ -module categories, it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}C( \widetilde{H})=\oint^{X\in {\mathcal B}\boxtimes_{\mathcal C}{\mathcal B}} \widetilde{H}(X){\otimes} {}^*\widetilde{H}(X)=C(F){\otimes} C(F).\end{align*} $$

Lemma 4.6 also explains how to compute dinatural transformations of this coend. If $\pi _X: \widetilde {H}(X){\otimes } {}^*\widetilde {H}(X)\to C(F){\otimes } C(F)$ , $X\in {\mathcal B}\boxtimes _{\mathcal C}{\mathcal B}$ , are the dinatural transformations associated with this coend, then

$$ \begin{align*}\pi_{A\boxtimes B}&=\lambda_{(F(A){\otimes} F(B),\rho)}=\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{C(F){\otimes} C(F)}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_D\big)\big(\mathrm{id\,}_C{\otimes}\sigma_{F(A),C}{\otimes} \mathrm{ id\,}_{F(B){\otimes} {}^*D}\big)\\ & \big(\pi_A{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \pi_B{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}\big) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*D}), \end{align*} $$

for any $A,B\in {\mathcal B}$ . Here, $D=F(A){\otimes } F(B)$ . Here, $\rho :F(A){\otimes } F(B)\to C(F){\otimes } F(A){\otimes } F(B) $ is the comodule structure of the tensor product according to formula (5.6). It follows from Lemma 7.1 that there is an isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \omega: \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(C(F){\otimes} C(F),C(F))\to \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(\widetilde{H}, C(F){\otimes} \widetilde{H}),\\ \omega(g)_X= (g{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{\widetilde{H}(X)})\psi^{C(F){\otimes} C(F)}_{\widetilde{H}(X),\widetilde{H}(X)}(\pi_X). \end{split} \end{align*} $$

Since, by Proposition 7.10, $(\mathrm {id\,}_{C(F)}{\otimes } \xi ^{-1}_{A,B}) \rho _{A{\otimes } B} \xi _{A,B}$ is a natural module transformation, that is,

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathrm{id\,}_{C(F)}{\otimes} \xi^{-1}_{A,B}) \rho_{A{\otimes} B} \xi_{A,B}\in Nat_{\! m}(\widetilde{H}, C(F){\otimes} \widetilde{H}),\end{align*} $$

then there exists a morphism $m:C(F){\otimes } C(F)\to C(F)$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\omega(m)_{A\boxtimes B}=(\mathrm{id\,}_{C(F)}{\otimes} \xi^{-1}_{A,B}) \rho_{A{\otimes} B} \xi_{A,B}.\end{align*} $$

Using the rigidity axioms, the naturality of $\sigma $ , and the formula for $\pi _{A\boxtimes B}$ , this equation implies (7.31). Using (7.31), it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}m\circ (m{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})= m\circ (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} m),\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}m \circ( u{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,} )=\mathrm{id\,}=m\circ (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} u).\end{align*} $$

It follows also from (7.31) that $\xi $ is a comodule morphism, giving the functor $\widehat {F}$ structure of monoidal functor.

Definition 7.12 For any monoidal module functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ , we shall denote by

$$ \begin{align*}H(F)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)\in {\mathcal C}\end{align*} $$

the bialgebra with product given by Theorem (7.11) and coproduct (7.3).

Remark 7.13 In Theorem 7.11, some hypothesis on the functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ are superfluous. It follows from [Reference Deligne8, Corollaire 2.10] that if F is right exact, then it is exact and faithful.

Let $(H,\Delta , m)$ be a bialgebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . In the next results, we shall be devoted to prove that the bialgebra reconstructed in Theorem 7.11, from the forgetful functor $f:{}^H{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ , coincides with the original bialgebra H.

In Lemma 7.3, we already proved that the reconstructed coalgebra coincides with H. Moreover, if $(W, \rho _W)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ , then we have defined dinatural transformations

$$ \begin{align*}\pi_W:W{\otimes} {}^*W\to H,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\pi_W=\bar{\psi}^H_{W,W}(\rho_W)=(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_W)(\rho_W{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*W}).\end{align*} $$

See (3.8) for the definition of isomorphisms $\bar {\psi } $ . In order to see that the reconstructed multiplication coincides with the product of H, we only need to prove that the original product m satisfies diagram (7.31). This will be done in the next proposition.

Proposition 7.14 Let $(H,\Delta , m)$ be a bialgebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . Using dinatural transformations $\pi _W:W{\otimes } {}^*W\to H,\ \pi _W=\bar {\psi }^H_{W,W}(\rho _W),$ we have that equation

$$ \begin{align*} m (\pi_V{\otimes} \pi_W{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{V{\otimes} W})&(\mathrm{id\,}_{V{\otimes} {}^*V}{\otimes} \sigma_{V, W{\otimes} {}^*W}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_W)(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_V{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_W)= \\ &=\rho_{V{\otimes} W} \end{align*} $$

holds for any pair $(V, \rho _V), (W,\rho _W)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ .

Proof It follows using the naturality of $\sigma $ and (5.6).

7.5 The antipode of $H(F)$

In the next results, we shall construct an antipode $S:H(F)\to H(F)$ , making the bialgebra $ H(F)$ a Hopf algebra in ${\mathcal C}$ .

Lemma 7.15 Let $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ be a braided tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Let $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be an exact and faithful monoidal module functor. For any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , there are natural isomorphisms

(7.32) $$ \begin{align} t_{B,V}: {}^*(B \triangleleft V)\to {}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V\end{align} $$

such that the diagram

(7.33)

is commutative.

Proof We shall freely use the fact that $F({}^*B)= {}^*F(B)$ , for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ . Since we are under the same hypothesis as Theorem 7.7, the functor $F:{\mathcal B}\to {}^H{\mathcal C}$ is full. Since $F({}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V)$ is a left H-comodule and the composition

$$ \begin{align*}h=c^{-1}_{{}^*B,{}^*V} \sigma_{ {}^*V, F(B)} (\phi^l_{F(B),V})^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{B,V}):{}^*F(B \triangleleft V)\to F({}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V)\end{align*} $$

is an isomorphism, we can endow ${}^*F(B \triangleleft V)$ with some H-comodule structure such that h is a H-comodule map. Fullness of F implies that there exist some $t_{B,V}$ such that $F(t_{B,V})=h$ .

We shall use the same notation as in previous sections. We denote by

$$ \begin{align*}\pi_A:F(A){\otimes} {}^*F(A)\to H(F)=\oint^{B\in {\mathcal B}} F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)\end{align*} $$

the dinatural transformations of the relative coend $H(F)$ . Also, recall from Proposition 7.4 that for any $A\in {\mathcal B}$ , we have that $(F(A),\rho _A)$ is a left $H(F)$ -comodule, with structure given by

$$ \begin{align*}\rho_A=\psi^{H(F)}_{F(A),F(A)}(\pi_A)=(\pi_A{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(A)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(A)}).\end{align*} $$

Henceforth, for simplicity, we shall denote $H=H(F)$ .

Lemma 7.16 Let $({\mathcal C},\sigma )$ be a braided tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. For any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , let us recall morphisms $ d_{B,V}$ , defined in Lemma 7.8, as

$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}:{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)\to {}^*V{\otimes}{}^*F(B) ,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}d_{B,V}= \big(\phi^l_{F(B), V} \big)^{-1} {}^*(c^{-1}_{B,V}).\end{align*} $$

Then, for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have

(7.34) $$ \begin{align} (\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} d_{B,V})\rho_{ {}^*(B\triangleleft V )}=(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^*B}) d_{B,V}. \end{align} $$

Proof Using Lemma 7.15, there are natural isomorphisms $t_{B,V}: {}^*(B \triangleleft V)\to {}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V$ such that

(7.35) $$ \begin{align} c_{{}^*B, {}^*V}F(t_{B,V})=\sigma_{{}^*V, F(B)} d_{B,V}. \end{align} $$

The naturality of $\phi ^l$ and c implies that

(7.36) $$ \begin{align} F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V ))=({}^*(\mbox{coev}_V){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B)}) d_{B,{}^*V{\otimes} V }, \end{align} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Using the dinaturality of $\pi $ , we obtain that

(7.37) $$ \begin{align} \pi_{{}^*(B\triangleleft V)}= \pi_{{}^*B\triangleleft {}^*V}\big(F(t_{B,V}){\otimes} {}^*F(t^{-1}_{B,V}) \big), \end{align} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Also, dinatural transformations $\pi $ satisfy (4.5); this implies that, for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , we have

(7.38) $$ \begin{align} \begin{split} \pi_{B \triangleleft {}^*V}& = \pi_B \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_B\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V )) \big) \big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{B\triangleleft {}^*V,V} \big)\\ &\big( c_{B,{}^*V} {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B\triangleleft {}^*V)}\big). \end{split} \end{align} $$

Next, when it is not absolutely necessary, as a space saving measure, we shall write the identities $\mathrm {id\,}$ , without using subscripts. Using the definition or $\rho $ , we obtain that

$$ \begin{align*}(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} d_{B,V})\rho_{ {}^*(B\triangleleft V )} d^{-1}_{B,V}\end{align*} $$

is equal to

$$ \begin{align*} &=(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} d_{B,V}) (\pi_{{}^*(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)})d^{-1}_{B,V}\\ &=(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)}) (\pi_{{}^*B\triangleleft {}^*V} {\otimes} d_{B,V}) (F(t_{B,V}){\otimes} {}^*F(t^{-1}_{B,V}){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B\triangleleft V)})d^{-1}_{B,V}\\ &=(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)}) (\pi_{{}^*B\triangleleft {}^*V} {\otimes} d_{B,V}) (F(t_{B,V}){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F({}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V)} {\otimes} F(t^{-1}_{B,V}))\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F({}^*B\triangleleft {}^*V)})d^{-1}_{B,V}\\ &=(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)})(\pi_{{}^*B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} F({}^*(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*B}\triangleleft \mbox{coev}_V )){\otimes} \mathrm{ id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} d_{{}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\\ & (c_{{}^*B, {}^*V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\big(F(t_{B,V})d^{-1}_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F({}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V)} {\otimes} d_{B,V} F(t^{-1}_{B,V})\big) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{{}^*B,{}^*V}{\otimes} c^{-1}_{{}^*B, {}^*V} )\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V})(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^* F(B\triangleleft V)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*V} )\\ &=(\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ {}^* F(B)})(\pi_{{}^*B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} ({}^*(\mbox{coev}_V){\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*B}))d_{B,{}^*V{\otimes} V }{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} d_{{}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}) \big(c_{{}^*B, {}^*V} F(t_{B,V})d^{-1}_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F({}^*B \triangleleft {}^*V)} {\otimes} d_{B,V} F(t^{-1}_{B,V})c^{-1}_{{}^*B, {}^*V}\big)\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{{}^*B,{}^*V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,} ) (\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V})(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^* F(B\triangleleft V)} {\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*V} )\\ &= (\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V} {\otimes} \pi_{{}^*B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}) (\sigma^{-1}_{ {}^*V, F({}^*B){\otimes} {}^*F({}^*B) }{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,} {\otimes} \mbox{ev}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F({}^*B){\otimes} {}^*V{\otimes} {}^*F(B)})\\ &(\sigma_{{}^*V, {}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^{**}V{\otimes} {}^*F({}^*B)} {\otimes} \sigma_{{}^*V, {}^*F(B)}) (\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V{\otimes} {}^*F(B){\otimes} {}^{**}V}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V})\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*V})\\ &=(\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*V}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^* B}). \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from (7.37), the third equality follows from (3.3), the fourth one follows from (7.38), and the fifth equality follows from (7.36). The sixth equality follows by using (3.6) and (7.35), and the last equality follows by using the rigidity axioms and (5.1).

Recall that sometimes we are denoting $H=H(F)$ .

Theorem 7.17 Let ${\mathcal C}$ be a tensor category, and let ${\mathcal B}$ be a monoidal right ${\mathcal C}$ -module category. Let $(F,c):{\mathcal B}\to {\mathcal C}$ be an exact and faithful monoidal module functor. There exists a map $S:H(F)\to H(F)$ such that it corresponds, under isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\omega: \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(H(F),V)\to \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(F, V{\otimes} F)\end{align*} $$

presented in (7.2), to the natural module transformation $\alpha :F\to H(F){\otimes } F,$

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha_B=(\mbox{ev}_{F(B)}&{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H(F){\otimes} F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*F(B),H(F)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)})\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^*B}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}). \end{align*} $$

That is, $\omega (S)=\alpha $ .

Proof We only need to prove that, indeed, $\alpha $ is a module natural transformation, that is,

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} c_{B,V}) \alpha_{B\triangleleft V}= (\alpha_B{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V) c_{B,V},\end{align*} $$

for any $B\in {\mathcal B}$ , $V\in {\mathcal C}$ . Equations (3.20) and (3.21) imply that

(7.39) $$ \begin{align} \mbox{ev}_{F(B\triangleleft V )} = \mbox{ev}_{F(B)}\big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_V{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,} \big)\big(c_{B,V}{\otimes} d_{B,V}\big), \nonumber\\ \mbox{coev}_{F(B\triangleleft V )}= \big( d^{-1}_{B,V}{\otimes} c^{-1}_{B,V}\big)\big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}\big) \mbox{coev}_V. \end{align} $$

Using the definition of $\alpha $ , we obtain that $(\mathrm {id\,}_H{\otimes } c_{B,V}) \alpha _{B\triangleleft V} c^{-1}_{B,V}$ is equal to

$$ \begin{align*} &= (\mbox{ev}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H{\otimes} F(B){\otimes} V)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*F(B\triangleleft V),H}{\otimes} c_{B,V} )\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^*(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B\triangleleft V)})c^{-1}_{B,V}\\ &=(\mbox{ev}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H{\otimes} F(B){\otimes} V)}) \big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_V{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B) {\otimes} H{\otimes} F(B){\otimes} V} \big)\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B){\otimes} V}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*V{\otimes} {}^*F(B),H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B){\otimes} V} ) \big(c_{B,V}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H}{\otimes} d_{B,V} {\otimes} c_{B,V}\big)\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^*(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)})\big( \mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} d^{-1}_{B,V}{\otimes} c^{-1}_{B,V}\big) \\ &\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V){\otimes} {}^*V}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V\big) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_V) c^{-1}_{B,V}\\ &=(\mbox{ev}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H{\otimes} F(B){\otimes} V)}) \big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \mbox{ev}_V{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B) {\otimes} H{\otimes} F(B){\otimes} V} \big)\\ &(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*F(B),H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,})(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*V,H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}) \big(\mathrm{id\,}{\otimes} (\mathrm{ id\,}_{H}{\otimes} d_{B,V} ) \rho_{{}^*(B\triangleleft V)} d^{-1}_{B,V} {\otimes} \mathrm{id\,} \big)\\ &\big(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V){\otimes} {}^*V}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{F(B)}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V\big) (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B\triangleleft V)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_V)\\ &=\alpha_B{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_V. \end{align*} $$

The second equality follows from (7.39) and the naturality of $\sigma $ , and the third equality follows by (5.1). The last equality follows from (7.34) and rigidity axioms.

Remark 7.18 The above result is the most sensitive statement to prove in order to prove the existence of the antipode for $H(F)$ . In the case ${\mathcal C}=\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ , the isomorphism

$$ \begin{align*}\omega: \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(H(F),V)\to \mathrm{Nat\,}(F, V{\otimes} F)\end{align*} $$

lands in the space of all natural transformations. So, in that case, there is nothing to prove, and the existence of S is guaranteed by the fact that $\omega $ is an isomorphism.

Corollary 7.19 The bialgebra $H(F)$ , from Definition 7.12, is actually a Hopf algebra. The antipode $S:H(F)\to H(F)$ is determined as the unique morphism such that

(7.40)

is commutative. Here,

$$ \begin{align*}\nu_B= (\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*F(B),H(F)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B)}{\otimes} \pi_{{}^*B}{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{{}^*F(B)})(\mathrm{id\,}_{F(B){\otimes} {}^*F(B)}{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_{{}^*F(B)}).\end{align*} $$

Proof Taking the map $S:H(F)\to H(F)$ defined in Theorem 7.17, and using the definition of $\alpha $ , one can prove that S satisfies diagram (7.40).

Axioms

$$ \begin{align*}m\circ (\mathrm{id\,}_H{\otimes} S)\circ \Delta=u\circ \varepsilon,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}m\circ ( S{\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_H)\circ \Delta=u\circ \varepsilon\end{align*} $$

follow from (7.40) by a lengthy, but straightforward, computation.

Remark 7.20 A version of the Hopf algebra $H(F)$ has been previously considered in the work of Lyubashenko [Reference Lyubashenko16, Reference Lyubashenko17] when F is some fiber functor and in [Reference Lyubashenko14, Reference Lyubashenko15] when F is the identity functor. See also the work of Schauenburg [Reference Schauenburg23], where ${\mathcal C}$ is the category of finite-dimensional vector spaces. However, there are new ingredients in our definition. We require that ${\mathcal B}$ is actually a monoidal ${\mathcal C}$ -module category and the functor F is a monoidal module functor. The use of the relative coend is another new feature of our construction.

Let $(H,\Delta , m, S)$ be a Hopf algebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . In the next proposition, we shall see that the reconstructed antipode given in Theorem 7.17, out of the forgetful functor $f:{}^H{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ , coincides with the original antipode $S:H\to H$ .

Proposition 7.21 Let $(H,\Delta , m, S)$ be a Hopf algebra in ${\mathcal C}$ . Using the identification $H=H(f)$ proven in Lemma 7.3, the reconstructed antipode obtained in Corollary 7.19 coincides with the antipode S of H.

Proof Let us denote by $\widehat {S}:H\to H$ the map reconstructed in Proposition 7.19. For any $V\in {\mathcal C}$ , recall the isomorphism (7.2)

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \omega: \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal C}(H(f),V)\to \mathrm{Nat\,}_{\! m}(f, V{\otimes} f),\\ \omega(g)_{(W,\rho_W)}= (g{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{W})\psi^{H}_{W,W}(\pi_W) \end{split} \end{align*} $$

for any $(W,\rho _W)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ . Corollary 7.17 implies that, if $\alpha :f\to H{\otimes } f$ is the module natural transformation defined as

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha_{(W,\rho_W)}=( \mbox{ev}_{W}&{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{H{\otimes} W})(\mathrm{id\,}_{W}{\otimes} \sigma^{-1}_{{}^*W,H}{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{ W})\\ & (\mathrm{id\,}_{W}{\otimes} \rho_{{}^*W} {\otimes}\mathrm{id\,}_{W})(\mathrm{id\,}_W{\otimes} \mbox{coev}_W), \end{align*} $$

for any $(W,\rho _W)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ , then

$$ \begin{align*}\omega(\widehat{S})=\alpha.\end{align*} $$

Using formula (5.7) for $\rho _{{}^*W}$ , we get that

$$ \begin{align*}\alpha_{(W,\rho_W)}= (S{\otimes} \mathrm{id\,}_{W})\, \rho_W=\omega(S)_{(W,\rho_W)},\end{align*} $$

for any $(W,\rho _W)\in {}^H{\mathcal C}$ . Whence $S=\widehat {S}$ .

8 Examples and applications

8.1 Generic example

The next example was treated along the paper. At the end, we proved that the reconstructed Hopf algebra from the forgetful functor $F:{^H}{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ coincides with $H.$

Example 8.1 Let H be a Hopf algebra in a braided finite tensor category ${\mathcal C}$ and consider the tensor category ${\mathcal B}={^H}{\mathcal C}$ . Then the forgetful functor admits an exact faithful monoidal functor $F:{^H}{\mathcal C}\to {\mathcal C}$ and the counit $\varepsilon _H$ gives rise to a monoidal section ${^H}{\mathcal C}\leftarrow {\mathcal C}$ that turns ${^H}{\mathcal C}$ into a ${\mathcal C}$ -module category.

Example 8.2 Let $H\subset L$ be Hopf algebras in $\mathrm {vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}}$ with $\iota :H\to L$ the inclusion, and assume that there is a left-inverse Hopf algebra map $\pi :H\rightarrow L$ , called projection. Then we have the restriction functor $\iota ^*\,:\operatorname {Rep}(H)\leftarrow \operatorname {Rep}(L)$ and in addition ${\mathcal B}=\operatorname {Rep}(L)$ becomes a modules category over ${\mathcal C}=Rep(H)$ via $\pi ^*:\,\operatorname {Rep}(H)\leftarrow \operatorname {Rep}(L)$ . Assume that H is quasitriangular. Hence, our result shows that there exists a Hopf algebra $C\in \operatorname {Rep}(H)$ such that there is an equivalence of monoidal modular categories

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(L)\cong {^C}\operatorname{Rep}(H).\end{align*} $$

We now discuss how this is related to the classical Radford Projection Theorem [Reference Radford21]. This result states that the existence of a Hopf algebra projection $\pi $ implies that L is isomorphic to a Radford biproduct

$$ \begin{align*}L\cong R\# H,\end{align*} $$

where R is a Hopf algebra in ${^H_H}{\mathcal YD}(\mathrm {Vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}})$ . In our case, we have assumed that H is quasitriangular and $\iota ^*$ lifts to a braided functor to the center of ${\mathcal B}$ . This gives rise to a choice of a functor $\operatorname {Rep}(H)\to {^H_H}{\mathcal YD}(\mathrm {Vect\,}_{\mathbb {k}})$ and shows R to be in the image – more explicitly the R-matrix of H determines the H-coaction from the H-action. Then this R is precisely the dual of our Hopf algebra C.

8.2 Generic consequences

Our results has certain general implications, for example:

Example 8.3 If $({\mathcal C}, \sigma )$ is a braided tensor category, then the forgetful functor $f:Z({\mathcal C})\to {\mathcal C}$ has a section $G:{\mathcal C}\to Z({\mathcal C})$ , $G(V)=(V, \sigma _V)$ . Theorems 7.7 and 7.17 imply that there exists a Hopf algebra $H\in {\mathcal C}$ such that $Z({\mathcal C})\simeq {}^H{\mathcal C}$ . For ${\mathcal C}=\operatorname {Rep}(H)$ for a factorizable Hopf algebra H, this can be obtained from the defining equivalence $Z({\mathcal C})\simeq {}^H{\mathcal C}\boxtimes {}^H{\mathcal C}$ , but in the non-nondegenerate case or the case without fiber functor, we are not aware of such a result. In general, we recover thereby the recent result [Reference Liu and Zhu13].

8.3 Lifting and cocycles deformations

In the classification of (e.g., pointed) Hopf algebras H, the strategy in the Andruskiewisch–Schneider program [Reference Andruskiewitsch and Schneider1] is to consider the coradical $H_0$ (which is assumed to be a Hopf algebra, for example, a group ring) and classify the possible Nichols algebras R, and then obtain H as a lifting of $\mathrm {gr}(H)=R\#H_0$ . It is an important question to determine whether this lifting is a $2$ -cocycle twist, and the observation is that this holds in almost all cases [Reference Angiono and Garcia Iglesias2].

We view this problem in our setting: since a main assumption is that $H_0\subset H$ , we have a tensor functor $\iota ^*:\,\mathrm {Comod}(H_0)\to \mathrm {Comod}(H)$ . The lifting is a $2$ -cocycle twist precisely iff there is a tensor functor $\mathrm {Comod}(H_0)\leftarrow \mathrm {Comod}(H)$ , if the $2$ -cocycle is trivial then it comes from a Hopf algebra projection $\pi $ , and then our relative coend is $R^*$ .

While this view does not allow to decide the difficult question when a lifting is a $2$ -cocycle twist, it shows the natural categorical context of this question and it produces general statements, for example, if R as a coalgebra has a trivial lifting, then there is a monoidal section and hence the lifting is tensor functor and thus the lifting comes from a $2$ -cocycle twist.

8.4 The logarithmic Kazhdan Lusztig conjecture

In conformal field theory, there is in good situations a modular tensor category of representations of a vertex algebra $\mathcal {V}$ , which reflects the analytic properties, for example, of solution spaces to certain differential equations (e.g., the braiding reflects the monodromy around the singularity $z=0$ ). One is often confronted with the very difficult question to determine the representation category of representations of a vertex subalgebra $\mathcal {W}\subset \mathcal {V}$ if the representation theory of $\mathcal {V}$ is known, for example, being a free-field realization. A brief introduction, references, and an account for the statements below can be found in [Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert6, Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert7].

Categorically, one can understand as $\operatorname {Rep}(\mathcal {W})$ being a modular tensor category and $A=\mathcal {V}$ being a commutative algebra in this category and ${\mathcal C}=\operatorname {Rep}(\mathcal {V})$ is the category of local A-modules $\operatorname {Rep}^\mathrm{loc}(A)$ . Then, by the results in [Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert6, Section 3], we have under suitable conditions that $\operatorname {Rep}(\mathcal {W})$ is a relative Drinfeld center of $\operatorname {Rep}(A)$ with respect to the subcategory ${\mathcal C}=\operatorname {Rep}^\mathrm{loc}(A)$ . In the cases relevant to logarithmic (i.e., nonsemisimple) conformal field theory, it is often the case that all simple modules in $\operatorname {Rep}(A)$ are already in $\operatorname {Rep}^\mathrm{loc}(A)$ . This gives rise via the socle filtration to a monoidal section functor (see [Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert6, Section 4])

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}^\mathrm{loc}(A)\rightleftarrows \operatorname{Rep}^\mathrm{loc}(A).\end{align*} $$

Then the results in our paper produce a Hopf algebra $R^*$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(A)={^{R^{*}}}{\mathcal C},\end{align*} $$

and in this case the mentioned equivalence to the relative Drinfeld center means explicitly (see Section 5.2)

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(\mathcal{W}) \cong {^R_R}{\mathcal YD}({\mathcal C}).\end{align*} $$

For example, the celebrated and notoriously difficult logarithmic Kazhdan Lusztig conjecture considers the lattice vertex algebra $\mathcal {V}_\Lambda $ of the root lattice of a semisimple complex finite-dimensional Lie algebra $\mathfrak {g}$ rescaled by an integer p, whose category of representations is the category of vector spaces graded by an abelian group

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(\mathcal{V}_\Lambda)=\mathrm{Vect\,}_{\Lambda^*/\Lambda}.\end{align*} $$

Then it asserts that $\mathcal {V}_\Lambda $ contains as kernel of screening operators a certain vertex algebra $\mathcal {W}_p(\mathfrak {g})\subset \mathcal {V}_\Lambda $ , whose category of representation is conjectured to be equivalent to the category of representations of the small quantum group $u_q(\mathfrak {g})$ for $q=e^{\pi i / p}$ . In the first author’s paper [Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert6], the approach is to view the small quantum group category as a category of Yetter–Drinfeld modules over the Nichols algebra $\mathcal {N}$

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(u_q(\mathfrak{g}))\cong {^{\mathcal{N}}_{\mathcal{N}}}{\mathcal YD}(\mathrm{Vect\,}_{\Lambda^*/\Lambda})\end{align*} $$

and develop the categorical tools above to reduce the equivalence in question to proving that

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Rep}(A)\cong {_{\mathcal{N}}}\mathrm{Vect\,}_{\Lambda^*/\Lambda}.\end{align*} $$

In the case $\mathfrak {sl}_2$ , the abelian category could be determined and this gives a systematic proof of the conjecture in this case (initially we have used more complicated proof methods for the case $\mathfrak {sl}_2,p=2$ in [Reference Creutzig, Lentner and Rupert6], while [Reference Gannon and Negron11] has used very different arguments for $\mathfrak {sl}_2,p$ ). A main motivation for writing the present paper is that now we have the clear statement that the category $\operatorname {Rep}(A)$ is for abstract reasons given as category of representations of a Hopf algebra $\mathcal {N}$ in ${\mathcal C}$ , and it now remains to determine that $\mathcal {N}$ is, indeed, the expected Nichols algebra, namely the Nichols algebra of screenings.

9 Questions

Question 9.1 The result should be applicable if ${\mathcal C}$ is merely locally finite tensor category and/or if $\mathcal {N}$ is infinite. The example we have in mind is maybe the quantum group $U_q(\mathfrak {g})$ at generic q.

Question 9.2 For given classes of semisimple modular tensor categories $\mathcal {C}$ (for example, the category of representations of an affine Lie algebra at positive integer level), can we classify semisimple Hopf algebras over $\mathcal {C}$ ?

Question 9.3 Is there a general argument that the embedding of the coradical $H_0$ into a pointed Hopf algebra H admits a categorical section of comodule categories, if we assume in addition that the Yetter–Drinfeld module $H_1/H_0$ is semisimple over $H_0$ ?

Acknowledgements

The work of both authors was partially done during the Workshop on Hopf algebras and Tensor categories held in May 2023, in Marburg, Germany. We thank the organizers, and in particular to Istvan Heckenberger. The attendance of M.M., to this workshop, was possible due to a grant of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, under a Research Group Linkage Programme. Part of the work of M.M. was done during a visit at Hamburg University. M.M. thanks Christoph Schweigert for the warm hospitality and for providing us with reference [Reference Husemöller12].

Footnotes

The work of M.M. was partially supported by Secyt-U.N.C., Foncyt, and CONICET Argentina. S.L. thanks T. Gannon and T. Creutzig for hospitality at the University of Alberta and the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation for financial support via the Feodor Lynen Fellowship.

References

Andruskiewitsch, N. and Schneider, H.-J., On the classification of finite-dimensional pointed Hopf algebras . Ann. of Math. 171(2010), no. 1, 375417.Google Scholar
Angiono, I. and Garcia Iglesias, A., Pointed Hopf algebras: a guided tour to the liftings . Rev. Colomb. Math. 53(2019), 144.Google Scholar
Bespalov, Y. N., Crossed modules, quantum braided groups and ribbon structures . Theor. Math. Phys. 103(1995), 368387.Google Scholar
Bortolussi, N. and Mombelli, M., (Co)ends for representations of tensor categories . Theory Appl. Categ. 37(2021), no. 6, 144188.Google Scholar
Bruguières, A. and Virelizier, A., Hopf monads . Adv. Math. 215(2007), 679733.Google Scholar
Creutzig, T., Lentner, S., and Rupert, M., Characterizing braided tensor categories associated to logarithmic vertex operator algebras. Preprint, arXiv:2104.13262.Google Scholar
Creutzig, T., Lentner, S., and Rupert, M.. An algebraic theory for logarithmic Kazhdan–Lusztig correspondences. Preprint, arXiv:2306.11492.Google Scholar
Deligne, P., Catgories tannakiennes . In: The Grothendieck festschrift, Vol. II, Progress in Mathematics, 87, Birkhauser, Boston, MA, 1990, pp. 111195.Google Scholar
Douglas, C. L., Schommer-Pries, C., and Snyder, N., The balanced tensor product of module categories . Kyoto J. Math. 59(2019), no. 1, 167179.Google Scholar
Etingof, P. and Ostrik, V., Finite tensor categories . Mosc. Math. J. 4(2004), no. 3, 627654.Google Scholar
Gannon, T. and Negron, C., Quantum SL(2) and logarithmic vertex operator algebras at (p,1)-central charge. Preprint, arXiv:2104.12821.Google Scholar
Husemöller, D., Lectures on tensor categories. Notes, Haverford College.Google Scholar
Liu, Z. and Zhu, S., Centers of braided tensor categories . J. Algebra 614(2023), 115153.Google Scholar
Lyubashenko, V., Modular transformations for tensor categories . J. Pure Appl. Algebra 98(1995), 279327.Google Scholar
Lyubashenko, V., Invariants of 3-manifolds and projective representations of mapping class groups via quantum groups at roots of unity . Commun. Math. Phys. 172(1995), no. 3, 467516.Google Scholar
Lyubashenko, V., Squared Hopf algebras and reconstruction theorems . Banach Cent. Publ. 40(1997), 111137.Google Scholar
Lyubashenko, V., Squared Hopf algebras, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1999.Google Scholar
Majid, S., Reconstruction theorems and rational conformal field theories . Int. J. Modern Phys. A 6(1991), 43594374.Google Scholar
Majid, S., Braided groups . J. Pure Appl. Algebra 86(1993), 187221.Google Scholar
Majid, S., Cross products by braided groups and Bosonization . J. Algebra 163(1994), 165190.Google Scholar
Radford, D. E., The structure of Hopf algebras with a projection . J. Algebra 92(1985), 322374.Google Scholar
Rivano, N. S., Catégories tannakiennes . Bull. Soc. Math. France 100(1972), 417430.Google Scholar
Schauenburg, P., Tannaka duality for arbitrary Hopf algebras, Algebra Berichte, 66, Reinhard Fischer, München, (1992).Google Scholar
Shimizu, K., The monoidal center and the character algebra . J. Pure Appl. Algebra 221(2017), no. 9, 23382371.Google Scholar
Shimizu, K., On unimodular finite tensor categories . Int. Math. Res. Not. 2017(2017), 277322.Google Scholar
Takeuchi, M., Finite Hopf algebras in braided tensor categories . J. Pure Appl. Algebra 138(1999), no. 1, 5982.Google Scholar