Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T16:44:10.178Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Assigning Humanitarian Intervention and the Responsibility to Protect

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 January 2021

Get access

Summary

Introduction

I am concerned with an apparently straightforward question: who should undertake humanitarian intervention to help discharge the Responsibility to Protect (RtoP)? Although political and legal issues are important, this question is ultimately a normative one: the humanitarian intervention of which international actor would be morally preferable and, potentially, morally obligatory?

There are two central reasons why the question arises. First, RtoP doctrine does not clearly identify which international actor should intervene. Most versions of RtoP require the United Nations (UN) Security Council to authorise intervention, but this does not identify any particular agent to undertake the action. The problem, as David Miller notes, is one of diffused responsibility. That is, RtoP doctrine asserts a general duty that falls on the international community to do something when the state where the humanitarian crisis is occurring is manifestly failing to tackle the crisis, but does not outline who, in particular, should act. Second, as I will discuss below, there are no outstanding candidates for humanitarian intervention in the international community. The various potential options, such as the North Atlantic Treaty Organisation (NATO), the UN, the African Union (AU), the European Union (EU), states, and private military and security companies (PMSCs), possess some attractive features, but also several sizable drawbacks. The AU, for instance, is sometimes more willing to act, but suffers from large shortfalls in capacity, especially when intervening on a large scale. Certain states, especially the major Western powers, have more military might, but may – and perhaps for good reason – fail to have strong international and domestic support for their intervention. Accordingly, it is not clear which agent in the international community should discharge the humanitarian intervention part of RtoP. As such, I consider who it is that should intervene.

Two Clarifications

Two clarifications are necessary. To start with, let me say something about the relationship between humanitarian intervention and RtoP. It is increasingly common to hear that RtoP does not imply humanitarian intervention. The reasoning behind such moves seems to be the fear that equating humanitarian intervention with RtoP will erode some of the delicate support for the doctrine in the international community, especially amongst certain members of the Non-Aligned Movement.

Type
Chapter
Information
Responsibility to Protect
From Principle to Practice
, pp. 173 - 184
Publisher: Amsterdam University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×