Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-pwrkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-06T10:21:45.284Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Geometry, Convention, and the Relativized A Priori: Reichenbach, Schlick, and Carnap

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Michael Friedman
Affiliation:
Indiana University
Get access

Summary

Kant's analysis of scientific knowledge – as articulated especially in his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science of 1786– is based on a sharp distinction between “pure” and “empirical” parts. The pure part of scientific knowledge consists of physical geometry (which, for Kant, is of course necessarily Euclidean geometry), more generally, the totality of applied mathematics presupposed by Newtonian physics (viz., classical analysis), Galilean kinematics (the classical velocity addition law), and the Newtonian laws of motion. In short, the entire spatiotemporal framework of Newtonian physics-what we now call the structure of Newtonian space-time – belongs to the pure part of natural science. The empirical part then consists of specific laws of nature formulated within this antecedently presupposed framework: for example, and especially, the law of universal gravitation and, more generally, the various specific force laws that can be formulated in the context of the Newtonian laws of motion.

Kant holds that the pure part of scientific knowledge consists entirely of synthetic a priori judgments. It does not represent merely conceptual knowledge but rather results from applying the conceptual faculty of pure understanding to the distinct sensible faculty of pure intuition. (This is what Kant calls the “schematism” of the pure concepts of the understanding.) The synthetic a priori judgments belonging to the pure part of scientific knowledge then represent the conditions of possibility of the empirical part: the former must be in place before the latter have well-defined meaning and truth value (“relation to an object”) in the first place.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×