Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-lvtdw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-15T14:00:31.351Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Necessity in Avicenna and the Arabic Tradition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2016

Paul Thom
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Max Cresswell
Affiliation:
Victoria University of Wellington
Edwin Mares
Affiliation:
Victoria University of Wellington
Adriane Rini
Affiliation:
Massey University, Auckland
Get access

Summary

Introduction

The expression ‘Arabic logic’ is used by scholars to cover a tradition of writing over a period stretching from the eighth century to the present day. The treatises and handbooks that belong to this tradition were written in various languages, including Arabic, Persian, Turkish, Hebrew, and Urdu. The central figures are Alfarabi (d. 950), Avicenna (d. 1037) and Averroes (d. 1198) (Street 2013a, introduction). Because of limitations of space, this chapter will omit Alfarabi, discussing only Avicenna and some of the more significant thinkers (including Averroes) whose work is based on, or reacts against, the latter's logical theories.

Avicenna

Avicenna uses the term ‘necessary’ to mark out (a) a class of beings, and (b) a class of propositions. His doctrine of the unique Necessary Being from which all contingent beings are derived is well known. Contingent beings are described as ‘possible’; but ‘possible’ here means two-sided possibility. A contingent being is one that can either exist or not exist. Whether it exists depends on a cause external to it. A necessary existent is one that cannot not exist, because its existence does not depend on anything external:

TEXT 1. And so we say that the things that fall under ‘being’ can be divided by the intellect into two groups. One of these comprises things which, when considered by themselves, do not possess necessary being; and it's clear also that their being is not impossible, otherwise they would not fall under ‘being’, and these are contained in the term ‘possibility’. The other comprises those which when considered by themselves possess necessary being. And so we say that a being which is necessary by itself does not have a cause, and that what is possible by itself has a cause.(Avicenna 1977, I, 6, 8 ff)

What is the connection between the usage of ‘necessary’ as a predicate of beings and its usage as a predicate of propositions? There is some evidence that, in Avicenna's view, the first usage is a particular case of the second – that to say a being is necessary is to say that the proposition expressing the being's existence is a necessary proposition. Avicenna's standard example of a proposition which is absolutely necessary is a proposition about the Necessary Being, namely, the proposition ‘God exists’ (Street 2004, 551).

Type
Chapter
Information
Logical Modalities from Aristotle to Carnap
The Story of Necessity
, pp. 91 - 112
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×