Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T15:14:38.551Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2017

Remy Debes
Affiliation:
University of Memphis
Karsten R. Stueber
Affiliation:
College of the Holy Cross, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Ethical Sentimentalism
New Perspectives
, pp. 250 - 267
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aaltolta, E. 2014. “Affective Empathy as Core Moral Agency: Psychopathy, Autism, and Reason Revisited,” Philosophical Explorations 17: 7692.Google Scholar
Abramson, K. and Leite, A. 2011. “Love as a Reactive Emotion,” Philosophical Quarterly 61: 673699.Google Scholar
Adler, H. E., Menze, A., and Palma, M. (tr. and eds.). 1997. Herder on World History: An Anthology. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. D. 2000. “Culpable Control and the Psychology of Blame,” Psychological Bulletin 126: 556574.Google Scholar
Ames, R. T. 1991. “The Mencian Conception of Ren Xing: Does It Mean Human Nature?,” in Rosemont, Henry Jr. (ed.), Chinese Texts and Philosophical Contexts: Essays Dedicated to Angus C. Graham. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 143175.Google Scholar
Ames, R. T. 2002. “Mencius and a Process Notion of Human Nature,” in Chan, Alan Kam-leung (ed.), Mencius: Contexts and Interpretations. Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press, 7290.Google Scholar
Appiah, K. A. 2008. Experiments in Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, R. 2013. Moral Perception. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. 1936. Language, Truth, and Logic. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, C. (ed.). 2011. Morality and the Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagnoli, C. (ed.). 2013. Constructivism in Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, A. C. 1980. “Hume on Resentment,” Hume Studies 6.2: 133149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, A. C. 1986. “Trust and Anti-Trust,” Ethics 96: 231260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, A. C. 1991. Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Baier, A. C. 1995. Moral Prejudices. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bartky, S. L. 1997. “Sympathy and Solidarity: On a Tightrope with Scheler,” in Meyers, D. T. (ed.), Feminists Rethink the Self. Boulder, CO: Westview, 177196.Google Scholar
Bedke, M. 2009. “Intuitive Non-Naturalism Meets Cosmic Coincidence,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90: 188209.Google Scholar
Behrens, T. E. J., Hunt, L. T., and Rushworth, M. F. S. 2009. “The Computation of Social Behavior,” Science 324: 11601164.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Behrens, T. E. J., Hunt, L. T., Woolrich, M. W., and Rushworth, M. F. S. 2008. “Associative Learning of Social Value,” Nature 456: 245250.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beierholm, U. R., Quartz, S. R., and Shams, L. 2009. “Bayesian Priors are Encoded Independently from Likelihoods in Human Multisensory Perception,” The Journal of Vision 9 (5), 23: 19.Google Scholar
Beiser, F. 1992. “Kant's Intellectual Development: 1746–1781,” in Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2661.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. 1980. “Accountability,” in Van Straaten, Z. (ed.), Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson. New York: Oxford University Press, 1447.Google Scholar
Berker, S. 2014. “Does Evolutionary Psychology Show that Normativity is Mind-Dependent?,” in D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Agency: Philosophical Essays on the Science of Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 215252.Google Scholar
Bernecker, S. 2011. “Keeping Track of the Gettier Problem,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (2): 127152.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1988. “How to Be an Ethical Antirealist.” in Blackburn, S. (ed.), 1993. Essays in Quasi-Realism. New York: Oxford University Press, 166181.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1998. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blair, R. J. R. 1995. “A Cognitive Developmental Approach to Morality: Investigating the Psychopath,” Cognition 57: 129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bloom, I. (tr.). 2009. Mencius. Edited by Ivanhoe, P. J.. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Butler, J. 1983. Five Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel and a Dissertation Upon the Nature of Virtue. Edited by Darwall, S. L.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Calhoun, C. 1994. “Separating Lesbian Theory from Feminist Theory,” Ethics 104: 558571.Google Scholar
Capes, J. 2012. “Blameworthiness Without Wrongdoing,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (3): 417437.Google Scholar
Cartwright, D. E. 1987. “Kant's View of the Moral Significance of Kindhearted Emotions and the Moral Insignificance of Kant's View,” The Journal of Value Inquiry 21: 291304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchill, T. (tr.). 1966. Herder's Outlines of a Philosophy of the History of Man (originally published 1800). New York: Bergman Publishers.Google Scholar
Clarke, S. 1964. “Discourse upon Natural Religion,” in Selby-Bigge, L. A. (ed.), British Moralists, vol. 2. Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill Company, 356.Google Scholar
Clarke-Doane, J. 2012. “Morality and Mathematics: The Evolutionary Challenge,” Ethics 122 (2): 313340.Google Scholar
Clore, G. L. and Ortony, A. 2000. “Cognition in Emotion: Always, Sometimes, or Never?,” in Lane, R. E. and Nadel, L. (eds.), Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press, 2461.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 1996. “Reason, Humanity, and the Moral Law,” in Korsgaard, (ed.), The Sources of Normativity. New York: Oxford Univeristy Press, 166188.Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. 1946/1994. The Idea of History (revised edition). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Confucius, , 1998, The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation. Translated and edited by Ames, Roger T. and Rosemont, Henry, Jr. New York: Random House Publishing.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1999. Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, N. 1994. “The Inaugural Address: Understanding,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 68: 126.Google Scholar
Coplan, A. 2011. “Understanding Empathy: Its Features and Effects,” in Coplan, and Goldie, (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 318.Google Scholar
Coplan, A. and Goldie, P. (eds.). 2011. Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Courville, A. C., Daw, N. D., and Touretzky, D. S. 2008. “Bayesian Theories of Conditioning in a Changing World, ” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10: 294300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, E. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crenshaw, K. 1991. “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence against Women of Color,” Stanford Law Review 43: 12411299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowe, M. J., ed. 2008. The Extraterrestrial Life Debate, Antiquity to 1915: A Source Book. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Cuneo, T. 2003. “Reidian Moral Perception,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 229258.Google Scholar
Cuneo, T. 2007. “Recent Faces of Moral Nonnaturalism,” Philosophy Compass 2 (6): 850879.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 1994. “Expressivism, Morality, and the Emotions,” Ethics 104: 739763.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2000a. “Sentiment and Value,” Ethics 110: 722748.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2000b. “The Moralistic Fallacy,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61: 6590.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2003. “The Significance of Recalcitrant Emotions (or, Anti-Quasijudgmentalism),” Philosophy, Supp. 52: 127145.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2006. “Sensibility Theory and Projectivism,” in Copp, D. (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. New York: Oxford University Press, 186218.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2014a. “Wrong Kinds of Reason and the Opacity of Normative Force,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 9. New York: Oxford University Press, 215244.Google Scholar
D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2014b. “Sentimentalism and Scientism,” in D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Agency: Philosophical Essays on the Science of Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 253278.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. 1994. Descartes’ Error. New York, NY: Harper.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. and Van Hoesen, G. W. 1983. “Emotional Disturbances Associated with Focal Lesions of the Limbic Frontal Lobe,” in Heilman, K. M. and Satz, P. (eds.), Neuropsychology of Human Emotion. New York, NY: Guilford Press, 85110.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1977. “Two Kinds of Respect,” Ethics 88: 3649.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1983. Impartial Reason. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1997. “Reasons, Motives, and the Demands of Morality: An Introduction,” in Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. (eds.), Moral Discourse and Practice: Some Philosophical Approaches. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1998. “Empathy, Sympathy, Care,” Philosophical Studies 89: 261282.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2002. Welfare and Rational Care. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2006a. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2006b. “Morality and Practical Reason: A Kantian Approach,” in Copp, D. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. New York: Oxford University Press, 282320.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2011. “Being With,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Supplement 49: 424.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2013. “Morality's Distinctiveness,” in Morality, Authority, and Law: Essays in Second-Personal Ethics I. New York: Oxford University Press, 319.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2017a. “Love's Second-Personal Character: Reciprocal Holding, Beholding, and Upholding,” in Kroeker, E. and Schaubroeck, K. (eds.), Love, Reason, and Morality. London: Routledge, 93109.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2017b. “Trust as a Second-Personal Attitude (of the Heart),” in Faulkner, P. and Simpson, T. (eds.), The Philosophy of Trust. New York: Oxford University Press, 93109.Google Scholar
Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. 1992. “Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends,” The Philosophical Review 101: 115189.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, S. 2015. “The Possibility of Physicalism,” The Journal of Philosophy 111 (9/10): 557592.Google Scholar
Dayan, P. and Daw, N. D. 2008. “Decision-Theory, Reinforcement Learning, and the Brain,” Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience 4: 429453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. 2010. Naturalism and Normativity. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
de Sousa, R. 1987. The Rationality of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
de Vignemont, F. and Jacob, P. 2012. “What is it like to feel another's pain?” Philosophy of Science 79 (2): 295316.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2009. “Neither Here Nor There: The Cognitive Nature of Emotion,” Philosophical Studies 146 (1): 127.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2010. “Which Empathy? Limitations in the Mirrored ‘Understanding’ of Emotion,” Synthese 175: 219239.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2012a. “Adam Smith on Dignity and Equality,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20: 109140.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2012b. “Recasting Scottish Sentimentalism: The Peculiarity of Moral Approval,” Journal of Scottish Philosophy 10: 91115.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2014. “Moral Rationalism and Moral Realism,” in Garrett, Aaron (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 500534.Google Scholar
Debes, R. 2015. “From Einfühlung to Empathy: Sympathy in Early Phenomenology and Psychology,” in Schliesser, E. (ed.), Sympathy: A History. New York: Oxford University Press, 286322.Google Scholar
Decety, J. and Chaminade, T. 2003. “When the Self Represents the Other: A New Cognitive Neuroscience View on Psychological Identification,” Consciousness and Cognition 12: 577596.Google Scholar
Deigh, J. 2012. “Reactive Attitudes Revisited,” in Bagnoli, (ed.), Morality and the Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press, 197216.Google Scholar
Dick, S. J. 1984. The Plurality of Worlds: The Extraterrestrial Life Debate from Democritus to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dixon, T. 2012. “‘Emotion’: The History of a Keyword in Crisis,” Emotion Review 4: 338344.Google Scholar
Döring, S. 2007. “Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation,” Dialectica 61: 363394.Google Scholar
Doris, J. 2005. Lack of Character. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Driver, J. 2001. Uneasy Virtue. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Driver, J. 2008. “Imaginative Resistance and Psychological Necessity,” Social Philosophy and Policy 25: 301313.Google Scholar
Du Bos, J.-B. 1719. Critical Reflections on Poetry, Painting, and Music, vol. 1., Nugent, T. (tr.). London: John Nourse.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2006. “Agency, Shmagency: Why Normativity Won't Come from What is Constitutive of Agency,” Philosophical Review 115: 169198.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2009. “Can there be a Global, Interesting, Coherent Constructivism about Practical Reason?,” Philosophical Explorations 12: 319339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2010a. “Shmagency Revisited,” in Brady, M., (ed.), New Waves in Metaethics. Basingstoke: Palgrave/Macmillan, 208233.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2010b. “The Epistemological Challenge to Metanormative Realism: How Best to Understand It, and How to Cope with It,” Philosophical Studies 148 (3): 413438.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. and Schechter, J. 2008. “How are basic belief-forming methods justified?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76.3: 547579.Google Scholar
Eskine, J. K., Kacinik, A. N., and Prinz, J. J. 2011. “A Bad Taste in the Mouth: Gustatory Disgust Influences Moral Judgment,” Psychological Science 22: 295299.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. 1947. The Definition of the Good. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Ferrero, L. 2009. “Constitutivism and the Inescapability of Agency,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 4, New York: Oxford University Press, 303333.Google Scholar
Festa, L. 2006. Sentimental Figures of Empire in Eighteenth-Century Britain and France. Baltimore: John Hopkins Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2002. “Varieties of Necessity,” in Gendler, T. & Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press, 253281.Google Scholar
Fingarette, H. 1972. Confucius: The Secular as Sacred. New York: Waveland Press.Google Scholar
FitzPatrick, W. 2009. “Thomson's Turnabout on the Trolley,” Analysis 69.4: 636643.Google Scholar
FitzPatrick, W. 2015. “Debunking Evolutionary Debunking of Ethical Realism,” Philosophical Studies 172.4: 883904.Google Scholar
Fleischacker, S. 1999. The Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1978. Virtues and Vices. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forman-Barzilai, F. 2001. “Whose Context? Which Impartiality? Reflections on Griswold's Smith,” Perspectives on Political Science 30: 146150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forman-Barzilai, F. 2010. Adam Smith and the Circles of Sympathy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Forster, M. N. (tr. and ed.). 2002. Herder: Philosophical Writings. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, R. H. 2001. “Cooperation through Emotional Commitment,” in Nesse, R. M. (ed.), Evolution and the Capacity for Commitment. New York: Russell Sage, 5776.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1971. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” The Journal of Philosophy 68.1: 520.Google Scholar
Frazer, M. 2010. The Enlightenment of Sympathy: Justice and the Moral Sentiments in Eighteenth Century and Today. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frijda, N. 1986. The Emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaier, U. et al. (eds.). 1985. Johann Gottfried Herder, Werke in Zehn Bänden. Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag.Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. 2012. “Empathy, Simulation, and Narrative,” Science in Context 25: 355381.Google Scholar
Gendler, T. S. 2006. “Imaginative Resistance Revisited,” in Nichols, S. (ed.), The Architecture of the Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press, 149174.Google Scholar
Gert, J. 2002. “Korsgaard's Private-Reasons Argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64: 303324.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, A. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gill, M. B. 1996. “A Philosopher in his Closet: Reflexivity and Justification in Hume's Moral Theory,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26.2: 231256.Google Scholar
Gill, M. B. 2000. “Shaftesbury's Two Accounts of the Reason to be Virtuous,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 38.4: 529548.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2000. The Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2003. “Narrative and Perspective; Values and Appropriate Emotions,” in Hatzimoysis, A. (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press, 201220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2007. “Dramatic Irony, Narrative, and the External Perspective,” in Hutto, D. (ed.), Narrative and Understanding Persons. New York: Cambridge University Press, 6984.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2011. “Anti-Empathy,” in Coplan, and Goldie, (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 302318.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2006. Simulating Minds. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2011. “Two Routes to Empathy: Insights from Cognitive Neuroscience,” in Coplan, and Goldie, (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 3144.Google Scholar
Goodwin, G. P. and Darley, J. M. 2008. “The Psychology of Meta-Ethics: Exploring Objectivism,” Cognition 106: 13391366.Google Scholar
Greene, J. and Haidt, J. 2002. “How (and Where) Does Moral Judgment Work?,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 517523.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., and Cohen, J. D. 2001. “An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment,” Science 293: 21052108.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. 1995. Practical Guilt: Moral Dilemmas, Emotions, and Social Norms. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Griswold, C. 1998. Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Griswold, C. 2001. “Reply to My Critics,” Perspectives on Political Science 30: 163167.Google Scholar
Gruen, L. 2009. “Attending to Nature: Empathetic Engagement with the More than Human World,” Ethics and the Environment 14: 2348.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. 2001. “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment,” Psychological Review 108: 814834.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K. and Wynn, K. 2011. “Young Infants Prefer Prosocial to Antisocial Others,” Cognitive Development 26: 3039.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1977. The Nature of Morality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 2000. “Moral Agent and Impartial Spectator,” in Explaining Value and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 181195.Google Scholar
Held, V. 2006. The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political, Global. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henrich, J. 2000. “Does Culture Matter in Economic Behavior? Ultimatum Game Bargaining among the Machiguenga of the Peruvian Amazon,” American Economic Review 90: 973979.Google Scholar
Henson, R. G. 1979. “What Kant Might Have Said: Moral Worth and the Overdetermination of Dutiful Action.” The Philosophical Review 88: 3954.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Th. 1994. Leviathan. Edited by Curley, Edwin. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hoffman, M. 2011. “Empathy, Justice, and the Law,” in Coplan, and Goldie, (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 230254.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 2015. “Injecting Phenomenology into the Free Will Debate,” in Shoemaker, D. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, vol. 3, New York: Oxford University Press, 3461.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 2012. “Introspection about Phenomenal Consciousness: Running the Gamut from Infallibility to Impotence,” in Smythies, D. and Stoljar, D. (eds.), Introspection and Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 405422.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Potrč, M. 2010. “The Epistemic Relevance of Morphological Content,” Acta Analytica 25: 155173.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. 2002. “The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality,” in Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. New York: Oxford University Press, 520533.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2006a. “Expressivism, Yes! Relativism, No!,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press, 7398.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2006b. “Cognitivist Expressivism,” in Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (eds.), Metaethics after Moore. New York: Oxford University Press, 255298.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2008. “What Does Moral Phenomenology Tell Us about Moral Objectivity?,” Social Philosophy & Policy 25: 267300.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2009. “Expressivism and Contrary-Forming Negation,” Philosophical Issues 19: 92112.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2011. “Introspection and the Phenomenology of Free Will,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 18: 180205.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. In Preparation. Illuminating Reasons: An Essay on Moral Phenomenology.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1739–1740/2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Norton, David Fate and Norton, Mary J.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1740. “Abstract of a Book Lately Published.” London: Borbet. Facsimile edition at www.davidhume.org/texts/abs.html.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1748/1999. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Beauchamp, Tom L.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1751/1998. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Edited by Beauchamp, Tom L.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd edition, Selby-Bigge, L. A. (ed.) and Nidditch, P. H. (rev.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1987. “Of the Standard of Taste, ” in Miller, E. F. (ed.), Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 226249.Google Scholar
Hurley, P. 2006. “Does Consequentialism Make Too Many Demands, or None at All?” Ethics 116 (4): 680706.Google Scholar
Hussain, N. and Shah, N. 2006. “Misunderstanding Metaethics: Korsgaard's Rejection of Realism,” Oxford Studies of Metaethics 1: 265294.Google Scholar
Hussain, N. and Shah, N. 2013. “Meta-Ethics and its Discontents: A Case Study of Korsgaard,” in Bagnoli, (ed.), Constructivism in Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press, 82107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutcheson, F. 1728–1742/2002. An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, with Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Edited with an Introduction by Garrett, Aaron. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Hutchseon, F. 1742–1747/2007. Philosophiae Moralis Insitutio Compenderia, with A Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Edited with an Introduction by Turco, Luigi. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Hutcheson, F. 1755/2005. A System of Moral Philosophy. With an Introduction by Carey, Daniel. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Hutcheson, F. 2004. An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue, ed. Leidhold, Wolfgang. Indianapolis: Liberty Press.Google Scholar
Immerwahr, J. 1989. “Hume's Essays on Happiness,” Hume Studies 15: 307324.Google Scholar
Jacob, P. 2011. “The Direct-Perception Model of Empathy: A Critique,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2: 519540.Google Scholar
Jacobson, D. 2013. “Regret, Agency, and Error,” Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility 1: 95125.Google Scholar
Jaggar, A. 1989. “Love and Knowledge: Emotion in Feminist Epistemology,” in Garry, A. and Pearsal, M. (eds.), Women and Knowledge. Boston: Unwin Hyman, 166190.Google Scholar
Johnston, M. 2001. “The Authority of Affect,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 181214.Google Scholar
Jones, K. 1996. “Trust as an Affective Attitude,” Ethics 107: 425Google Scholar
Joyce, R. 2007. The Evolution of Morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. 2013. Thinking Fast and Thinking Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, & Giroux.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (eds.). 2000. Choices, values and frames. New York: Cambridge University Press and Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. 2007. Intricate Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kane, R. 2010. Ethics and the Quest for Wisdom. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1902–. (“KGS”) Gesammelte Schriften. Hrsg. von der Koeniglich-Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1992. Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770. Translated and edited by Walford, David and Meerbote, Ralf. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1996. Practical Philosophy. Translated and edited by Gregor, Mary J.. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. General Introduction by Allen Wood. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1997. Lectures on Ethics Translated by Peter Heath. Edited by Heath, Peter and Schneewind, J. B.. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. 2014a. “Moral Sentimentalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-sentimentalism/.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. 2014b. “Fittingness and Idealization,” Ethics 124 (3), 572588.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. 2015. “Favoring,” Philosophical Studies 172, 19531971.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. 2016. “Character and Blame in Hume and Beyond,” in Fileva, Iskra (ed.), Questions of Character. Oxford University Press, 4662.Google Scholar
Kelly, D. 2011. Yuck!: The Nature and Moral Significance of Disgust. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, T. and McGrath, S. 2010. “Is Reflective Equilibrium Enough?” Philosophical Perspectives 24: 325339.Google Scholar
Kittay, E. F. 1999. Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Knoblock, John. 1988–1994. Xunzi: A Translation and Study of the Complete Work, 3 vols. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1996a. The Sources of Normativity. With responses by G. A. Cohen, Raymond Geuss, Thomas Nagel and Bernard Williams. Edited by O'Neill, Onora. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1996b. “From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action,” in Engstrom, S. and Whiting, J. (eds.), Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. New York: Cambridge University Press, 203236.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1997. “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason,” in Cullity, G. and Gaut, B. (eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon, 215254.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2008. The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, D. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuehn, M. 2001. Kant: A Biography. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lamm, C., Batson, C. D., and Decety, J. 2007. “The Neural Substrate of Human Empathy: Effects of Perspective-Taking and Cognitive Appraisal,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19: 4258.Google Scholar
LeDoux, J. 1996. The Emotional Brain. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Lenman, J. and Shemmer, Y. (eds.). 2012. Constructivsm in Practical Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, D. 2014. “Darwinian Normative Skepticism,” in Bergmann, M. and Kain, P. (eds.), Challenges to Moral and Religious Belief: Disagreement and Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press, 220236.Google Scholar
Loeb, L. E. 2002. Stability and Justification in Hume's Treatise. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lorde, A. 1984. Sister Outsider. Freedom, CA: Crossing Press.Google Scholar
Louden, R. B. 2000. Kant's Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lugones, M. C. 1987. “Playfulness, ‘World’-Travelling, and Loving Perception,” Hypatia 2: 319.Google Scholar
Lugones, M. C. and Spelman, E. V. 1983. “Have We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism, and the Demand for ‘the Women's Voice,’” Women's Studies International Forum 6: 573578.Google Scholar
Luo, S. 2007. Classical Confucianism and Moral Sentimentalism. Saarbrücken: VDM Verlag.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 1966. “Hume on ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’,” in Campbell, V. C. (ed.), Modern Studies in Philosophy: Hume. New York: Anchor Books, 240264.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, C. 2006. “Imagining Other Lives,” Philosophical Papers 35: 293325.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. 2013a. “‘Screw You!’ and ‘Thank you!,’Philosophical Studies 165: 893914.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. 2013b. “Taking Demands out of Blame,” in Coates, and Tognazzini, (eds.), Blame: Its Nature and Norms. New York: Oxford University Press, 141161.Google Scholar
Mandeville, B. 1988a. The Fable of the Bees. (2 vols.), Edited by Kaye, F. B.. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Press.Google Scholar
Mandeville, B. 1988b. “A Search into the Nature of Society,” in Mandeville, , The Fable of the Bees 2: 323370.Google Scholar
Martin, A. 2014. How We Hope. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, M. A. 1994. “Hume as Classical Moralist,” International Philosophical Quarterly 34.3: 323334.Google Scholar
Mason, M. 2003. “Contempt as a Moral Attitude,” Ethics 113: 234272.Google Scholar
McBrayer, J. 2010a. “A Limited Defense of Moral Perception,” Philosophical Studies 149: 305320.Google Scholar
McBrayer, J. 2010b. “Moral Perception and the Causal Objection,” Ratio 23: 201307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 1998. “Values and Secondary Qualities,” in Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 131150.Google Scholar
McGrath, S. 2004. “Moral Knowledge by Perception,” Philososophical Perspectives 18: 209229.Google Scholar
McGrath, S. 2014. “Relax? Don't Do It! Why Moral Realism Won't Come Cheap.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 9: 186214.Google Scholar
McRae, E. 2011. “The Cultivation of Moral Feelings and Mengzi's Method of Extension,” Philosophy East & West 61.4: 587608.Google Scholar
Meinecke, F. 1936/1972. Historicism: The Rise of a New Historical Outlook. Translated by Anderson, J. E. with a Foreword by Sir Isaiah Berlin. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Melis, A. P., Hare, B., and Tomasello, M. 2006. “Chimpanzees Recruit the Best Collaborators,” Science 311: 12971300.Google Scholar
Mendus, S. 1985. “The Practical and the Pathological,” The Journal of Value Inquiry 19: 235243.Google Scholar
Meyers, D. T. 2009. “Narrative Structures, Narratives of Abuse, and Human Rights,” in Tessman, L. (ed.), Feminist Ethics and Social and Political Philosophy: Theorizing the Non-Ideal. Dordrecht: Springer, 253270.Google Scholar
Meyers, D. T. 2016. Victims’ Stories and the Advancement of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1963. Utilitarianism, in Robson, J. M. (ed.), Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. 10. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Miller, D. 2013. Justice for Earthlings: Essays in Political Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903/1993. Principia Ethica. Edited with an Introduction by Thomas Baldwin. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nadler, J. and McDonnell, M. 2012. “Moral Character, Motive, and the Psychology of Blame,” Cornell Law Review 97: 1143.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1972. “War and Massacre,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 123144.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1979. “Equality,” in Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press, 106127.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1986. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. 2004. Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Folds-Bennett, T. 2003. “Are Children Moral Objectivists? Children's Judgments about Moral and Response-Dependent Properties,” Cognition 90: B23B32.Google Scholar
Norcross, A. 2008. “Off Her Trolley? Frances Kamm and the Metaphysics of Morality,” Utilitas 20.1: 6580.Google Scholar
Nunner-Winkler, G. and Sodian, B. 1988. “Children's Understanding of Moral Emotions,” Child Development 59: 13231338.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1988. “Narrative Emotions: Beckett's Genealogy of Love,” Ethics 98: 225254.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotion. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nyholm, S. 2012. On the Universal Law and Humanity Formulas. PhD Dissertation, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters. 2 vols. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pessoa, L. 2008. “On the Relationship between Emotion and Cognition,” Nature Reviews: Neuroscience 9: 149158.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1991. “Realism and Response-Dependence,” Mind 100: 587626.Google Scholar
Pew Research Center. 2010. “The Decline of Marriage and Rise of New Families.” Retrieved October 10, 2015, from http://pewsocialtrends.org/files/2010/11/pew-social-trends-2010-families.pdf.Google Scholar
Pizarro, D. A. and Tannenbaum, D. 2012. “Bringing Character Back: How the Motivation to Evaluate Character Influences Judgments of Moral Blame,” in Mikulincer, M. and Shaver, P. R. (eds.), The Social Psychology of Morality: Exploring the Causes of Good and Evil. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association, 91108.Google Scholar
Potkay, A. 2000. The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson and David Hume. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2003. “Truth as Convenient Friction,” Journal of Philosophy 100: 167190.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2004. Gut Feelings: A Perceptual Theory of Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2007. The Emotional Construction of Morals. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2011a. “Against Empathy,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Supplement 49: 214233.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2011b. “Is Empathy Necessary for Morality?” in Coplan, and Goldie, (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 211229.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2016. “Sentimentalism and the Moral Brain,” in Liao, S. M. (ed.), Moral Brains: The Neuroscience of Morality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. Forthcoming. The Moral Self. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2012. “Anti-Luck Virtue Epistemology,” Journal of Philosophy 109.3: 247279.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2000. “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist,” Noûs 34.4: 517549.Google Scholar
Quinn, W. 1989. “Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 18.4: 334351.Google Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. and Ronnow-Rasmussen, T. 2004. “The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Value,” Ethics 104: 291423.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 1997. “Aesthetic Value, Moral Value, and the Ambitions of Naturalism,” in Levinson, J. (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 59105.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2013. “Reliance, Trust, and Belief,” Inquiry 57: 122150.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2014. “The Affective Dog and Its Rational Tale: Intuition and Attunement,” Ethics 124: 813859.Google Scholar
Raposa, M. L. 2004. “Ritual Inquiry: The Pragmatic Logic of Religious Practice,” in Schilbrack, K. (ed.), Thinking Through Rituals: Philosophical Perspectives. New York: Routledge, 115130.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1980. “Kantian Constructivism in Ethical Theory,” The Journal of Philosophy 77: 515572.Google Scholar
Reeder, G. B. and Brewer, M. B. 1979. “A Schematic Model of Dispositional Attribution in Interpersonal Perception,” Psychological Review 86: 6179.Google Scholar
Richerson, P. J., Boyd, R., and Henrich, J. 2003. “The Cultural Evolution of Human Cooperation,” in Hammerstein, P. (ed.), The Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 357388.Google Scholar
Ridge, M. 2006. “Ecumenical Expressivism: Finessing Frege,” Ethics 116: 302336.Google Scholar
Ridge, M. 2012. “Kantian Constructivism: Something Old, Something New,” in Lenman, and Shemmer, (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 138158.Google Scholar
Roseman, I. 2013. “Appraisal in the Emotion System: Coherence in Strategies for Coping,” Emotion Review 5: 141149.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. 2010. “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction,” in Hale, B. and Hoffmann, A. (eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press, 109136.Google Scholar
Ross, L. and Nisbett, R. E. 1991. The Person and the Situation: Perspectives of Social Psychology. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rozin, P. and Singh, L. 1999. “The Moralization of Cigarette Smoking in the United States,” Journal of Consumer Psychology 8: 321337.Google Scholar
Rozin, P., Markwith, M., and Stoess, C. 1997. “Moralization and Becoming a Vegetarian: The Transformation of Preferences into Values and the Recruitment of Disgust,” Psychological Science 8: 6773.Google Scholar
Sarkissian, H., Park, J., Tien, D., Wright, J., and Knobe, J. 2012. “Folk Moral Relativism,” Mind and Language 26: 482505.Google Scholar
Sayre-McCord, G. 2010. “Sentiments and Spectators: Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Judgment,” The Adam Smith Review 5: 124144.Google Scholar
Sayre-McCord, G. 2013. “Hume and Smith on Sympathy, Approbation, and Moral Judgment,” Social Philosophy and Policy 30: 208236.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2008. Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, and Blame. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2014. Being Realistic about Reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A. 2014. “The Motivational Theory of Emotion, ” in D'Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Agency: Philosophical Essays on the Science of Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2010. “Evolution and Normative Scepticism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88.3: 471488.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2013. “Quasi-Realism, Projectivism, and the Explanatory Challenge,” in Hubbs, G. and Lind, D. (eds.), Pragmatism, Law, and Language. Oxford: Routledge, 136151.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2014. “Knowledge and Two Faces of Non-Accidental Truth,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2): 373393.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2015a. “How Common is Peer Disagreement? On Self-Trust and Rational Symmetry,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91: 2546.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2015b. “Constructivism and Realism in Kantian Metaethics (1 & 2),” Philosophy Compass 10 (10): 690713.Google Scholar
Scheman, N. 1993. Engenderings: Constructions of Knowledge, Authority, and Privilege. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Scherer, K. 2005. “What are Emotions? And How Can They be Measured?,” Social Science Information 44: 695729.Google Scholar
Schilpp, P. A. 1938/1960. Kant's Pre-Critical Ethics. Second Edition. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Schilpp, P. A. (ed.). 1942. The Philosophy of G. E. Moore. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Schmidt, E. Z. and Bonelli, R. M. 2008. “Sexuality in Huntington's Disease,” Wiener Medizinische Wochenschrift 158: 8490.Google Scholar
Scholz, S. 2010. “Persons Transformed by Political Solidarity,” Appraisal 8: 1927.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, A. 1840/1995. On the Basis of Morality. Translated by Payne, E. F. J.. With an Introduction by David E. Cartwright. Providence, RI: Berghan Books.Google Scholar
Schroeter, F. 2006. “The Limits of Sentimentalism,” Ethics 116: 337361.Google Scholar
Schultz, W. 2002. “Getting Formal with Dopamine and Reward”. Neuron 36: 241263.Google Scholar
Schwarz, N. and Clore, G. L. 2003. “Mood as Information: 20 Years Later,” Psychological Inquiry 14: 296303.Google Scholar
Scruton, R. 1987. “Laughter,” in Morreall, John (ed.), The Philosophy of Laughter and Humor. Albany: SUNY Press, 156171.Google Scholar
Seidel, A. and Prinz, J. J. 2013a. “Sound Morality: Irritating and Icky Noises Amplify Divergent Moral Domains,” Cognition 127: 15.Google Scholar
Seidel, A. and Prinz, J. J. 2013b. “Mad and Glad: Musically Induced Emotions Have Divergent Moral Impact,” Motivation and Emotion 37: 269237.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 2002. “Open and Closed Impartiality,” The Journal of Philosophy 99: 445469.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2012. Knowing Right From Wrong. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. 2008. “Defending Ethical Intuitionism,” in Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology (5 vols.), vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 8396.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. 2012. “Evolutionary Debunking, Moral Realism, and Moral Knowledge.” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7.1: 138.Google Scholar
Shaftesbury, A. A. C., Third Earl of. 1711/2001. Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times. Foreword by Uyl, Douglas Den. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S. 1985/2011. Leviathan and the Air Pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Experimental Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Shell, S. M. 1996. The Embodiment of Reason: Kant on Spirit, Generation and Community. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sher, G. 2006. In Praise of Blame. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1990. “The Place of Emotions in Kantian Morality,” in Flanagan, O. and Rorty, A. Oksenberg (eds.), Identity, Character and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 149170.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1997. Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1998. “Empathy and Imagination,” Philosophy of Emotions, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 22: 82119.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1981. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis, IN.: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2011. The Contents of Perception. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 2008. Moral Psychology, 5 vols., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 2003. Morals from Motives. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 2007. The Ethics of Care and Empathy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 2010. Moral Sentimentalism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A. 1759/1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by Raphael, D. D. and Macfie, A. L.. The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. 1980. “Emotions and Choice,” in Rorty, A. (ed.), Explaining Emotions. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 251281.Google Scholar
Soto, F. A., Gershman, S. J., and Niv, Y. 2014. “Explaining Compound Generalization in Associative and Causal Learning through Rational Principles of Dimension Generalization,” Psychological Review 121: 526558.Google Scholar
Spelman, E. V. 1988. Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought. Boston: Beacon.Google Scholar
Stern, R. 2013. “Moral Skepticism, Constructivism and the Value of Humanity,” in Bagnoli, (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 2240.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. 1944. Ethics and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. 1963. Facts and Values: Studies in Ethical Analysis. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Storbeck, J. and Clore, G. L. 2007. “On the Interdependence of Cognition and Emotion,” Cognition & Emotion 21: 12121237.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1962. “Freedom and Resentment,” Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 125. Reprinted in Watson (ed.). 1982. Free Will. Oxford University Press: 59–80. Page references are to the reprint.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1980. “Replies,” in van Straaten, Z. (ed.), Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson. New York: Oxford University Press, 260296.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2006. “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value,” Philosophical Studies 127: 109166.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2008. “Constructivism about Reasons,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 3. New York: Oxford University Press, 207245.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2009. “Evolution and the Normativity of Epistemic Reasons,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39, suppl. 1: 213248.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2010. “What is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics?” Philosophy Compass 5: 363384.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2011. “Mind-Independence Without the Mystery: Why Quasi-Realists Can't Have It Both Ways,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 6. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 132.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2012. “Coming to Terms with Contingency: Humean Constructivism about Practical Reason,” in Lenman, and Shemmer, (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 4059.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 1994. “Practice, Indeterminacy, and Private Language: Wittgenstein's Dissolution of Scepticism,” Philosophical Investigations 17: 1436.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2006. Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2008. “Reasons, Generalizations, Empathy, and Narratives: The Epistemic Structure of Action Explanation,” History and Theory 47: 3143.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2011. “Imagination, Empathy, and Moral Deliberation: The Case of Imaginative Resistance,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Supplement 49: 156180.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2012. “Varieties of Empathy, Neuroscience and the Narrativist Challenge to the Contemporary Theory of Mind Debate,” Emotion Review 4: 5563.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2013. “The Causal Autonomy of Reason Explanations and How Not to Worry about Causal Deviance,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43: 2445.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2014. “Empathy,” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/empathy/.Google Scholar
Stueber, K. 2015. “Naturalism and the Normative Domain: Accounting for Normativity with the Help of 18th Century Empathy-Sentimentalism,” Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia e Psicologia 6: 2436.Google Scholar
Suphan, B. et al. ed. 1967–1968. Johann Gottfried Herder Sämtliche Werke. Originally Published 1887–1913. Reprinted Hildesheim and New York: Georg Olms Verlag.Google Scholar
Szendy, P. 2013. Kant in the Land of Extraterrestrials: Cosmopolitical Philosofictions. Translated by Will Bishop. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Tannenbaum, D., Uhlmann, E. L., and Diermeier, D. 2011. “Moral Signals, Public Outrage, and Immaterial Harms,” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 47: 12491254.Google Scholar
Tenenbaum, J. B., Kemp, C., Griffths, T. L., and Goodman, N. D. 2011. “How to Grow a Mind: Statistics, Structure, and Abstraction,” Science 331: 12791285.Google Scholar
Thompson, R. 2006. “The Development of the Person: Social Understanding, Relationships, Conscience, Self,” in Eisenberg, N. (ed.), Handbook of Child Psychology, 6th edition, vol. 3. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley, 2498.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. 1999. “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Two Moral Arguments,” Ethics 109.3: 497518.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. 2008. “Turning the Trolley,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 36.4: 359374.Google Scholar
Tobler, P. N. et al. 2006. “Reward Value Coding Distinct from Risk Attitude-Related Uncertainty Coding in Human Reward Systems,” Journal of Neurophysiology 97: 16211632.Google Scholar
Trevarthen, C. 2001. “Intrinsic Motives for Companionship in Understanding: Their Origin, Development, and Significance for Mental Health,” Infant Mental Health Journal 22: 95131.Google Scholar
Uhlmann, E. L. and Zhu, L. 2014. “Acts, Persons, and Intuitions: Person-centered Cues and Gut Reactions to Harmless Transgressions,” Social Psychological and Personality Science 5: 279285.Google Scholar
Uhlmann, E. L., Zhu, L., and Diermeier, D. 2014. “When Actions Speak Volumes: The Role of Inferences about Moral Character in Outrage over Racial Bigotry,” European Journal of Social Psychology 44: 2329.Google Scholar
Uhlmann, E. L., Zhu, L., and Tannenbaum, D. 2013. “When it Takes a Bad Person to Do the Right Thing,” Cognition 126: 326334.Google Scholar
Vaish, A., Carpenter, M., and Tomasello, M. 2011. “Young Children's Responses to Guilt Displays,” Developmental Psychology 47: 12481262.Google Scholar
Van Straaten, Z. (ed.). 1980. Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Vauvenargues, Marquis de, Clapiers, Luc de. 1857. Introduction à la connaissance de l'esprit humain, in Gilbert, D.-L. (ed.), Oeuvres de Vauvenargues. Paris: Furne et Cie.Google Scholar
Vavova, K. 2014. “Debunking Evolutionary Debunking,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics. vol. 9. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 76101.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 1999. “Love as a Moral Emotion,” Ethics 109: 338374.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 2003. “Narrative Explanation,” The Philosophical Review 112: 125.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 2009. How We Get Along. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 2013. Foundations of Moral Relativism. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. 1996. Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. 2012. “Constructivism about Normativity: Some Pitfalls,” in Lenman, and Shemmer, (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1839.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (ed.). 1982. Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. 1994. “Responsibility and the Limits of Evil: Variations on a Strawsonian Theme,” in Fischer, and Ravizza, (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 119148.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2007. The Nature of Normativity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Werner, D. 1979. “A Cross-Cultural Perspective on Theory and Research on Male Homosexuality,” Journal of Homosexuality 4: 345362.Google Scholar
White, R. 2005. “Problems for Dogmatism,” Philosophical Studies 131: 525557.Google Scholar
Wielenberg, E. 2010. “On the Evolutionary Debunking of Morality,” Ethics 120.3: 441464.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1987. “A Sensible Subjectivism,” in Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value. Oxford: Blackwell, 185214.Google Scholar
Willenken, T. 2011. “Moorean Responses to Skepticism: A Defense.” Philosophical Studies 154: 125.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1995a. “Who Needs Ethical Knowledge?,” in Making Sense of Humanity, New York: Cambridge University Press, 203212.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1995b. “What Does Intuitionism Imply?,” in Making Sense of Humanity, New York: Cambridge University Press, 182191.Google Scholar
Winkler, K. P. 2011. “Hume and the Sensible Qualities,” in Nolan, L. (ed.), Primary and Secondary Qualities: The Historical and Ongoing Debate. New York: Oxford University Press, 239273.Google Scholar
Winter, L. and Uleman, J. S. 1984. “When are Social Judgments Made? Evidence for the Spontaneousness of Trait Inferences,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 47: 237252.Google Scholar
Wong, D. B. 2002. “Reasons and Analogical Reasoning in Mengzi.” in Liu, Xiusheng and Ivanhoe, Philip J. (eds.), Essays on the Moral Philosophy of Mengzi. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 187220.Google Scholar
Wong, D. B. 2015. “Early Confucian Philosophy and the Development of Compassion,” Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 14: 157194.Google Scholar
Wood, A. 1999. Kant's Ethical Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, J. C., Grandjean, P., and McWhite, C. 2012. “The Meta-Ethical Grounding of Our Moral Beliefs: Evidence for Meta-Ethical Pluralism,” Philosophical Psychology 26: 336361.Google Scholar
Yamada, M. 2011. “Getting It Right By Accident,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83.1: 72105.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. 1997. Intersecting Voices: Dilemmas of Gender, Political Philosophy, and Policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zammito, John H. 2002. Kant, Herder and the Birth of Anthropology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Edited by Remy Debes, University of Memphis, Karsten R. Stueber, College of the Holy Cross, Massachusetts
  • Book: Ethical Sentimentalism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316105672.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Edited by Remy Debes, University of Memphis, Karsten R. Stueber, College of the Holy Cross, Massachusetts
  • Book: Ethical Sentimentalism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316105672.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Edited by Remy Debes, University of Memphis, Karsten R. Stueber, College of the Holy Cross, Massachusetts
  • Book: Ethical Sentimentalism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316105672.015
Available formats
×