Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T15:04:58.106Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Neurophenomenology: An Introduction for Neurophilosophers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Evan Thompson
Affiliation:
Canada Research Chair and Associate Professor of Philosophy, York University
Antoine Lutz
Affiliation:
Postdoctoral Fellow, W. M. Keck Laboratory for Functional Brain Imaging and Behavior, Waisman Center, University of Wisconsin–Madison
Diego Cosmelli
Affiliation:
Ecole Polytechnique, Paris
Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Carleton University, Ottawa
Kathleen Akins
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Get access

Summary

Introduction

One of the major challenges facing neuroscience today is to provide an explanatory framework that accounts for both the subjectivity and neurobiology of consciousness. Although neuroscientists have supplied neural models of various aspects of consciousness, and have uncovered evidence about the neural correlates of consciousness (or NCCs), there nonetheless remains an ‘explanatory gap’ in our understanding of how to relate neurobiological and phenomenological features of consciousness. This explanatory gap is conceptual, epistemological, and methodological:

  • An adequate conceptual framework is still needed to account for phenomena that (ⅰ) have a first-person, subjective-experiential or phenomenal character; (ⅱ) are (usually) reportable and describable (in humans); and (ⅲ) are neurobiologically realized.

  • The conscious subject plays an unavoidable epistemological role in characterizing the explanandum of consciousness through first-person descriptive reports. The experimentalist is then able to link first-person data and third-person data. Yet the generation of first-person data raises difficult epistemological issues about the relation of second-order awareness or meta-awareness to first-order experience (e.g., whether second-order attention to first-order experience inevitably affects the intentional content and/or phenomenal character of first-order experience).

  • The need for first-person data also raises methodological issues (e.g., whether subjects should be naïve or phenomenologically trained).

Neurophenomenology is a neuroscientific research program whose aim is to make progress on these issues associated with the explanatory gap. In this chapter we give an overview of the neurophenomenological approach to the study of consciousness.

Type
Chapter
Information
Cognition and the Brain
The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement
, pp. 40 - 97
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J. 1998. Zen and the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Baars, B. J. 2002. The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 47–52CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bitbol, M. 2002. Science as if situation mattered. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 181–224CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blake, R. 2001. A primer on binocular rivalry, including current controversies. Brain and Mind 2: 5–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blake, R., and Logothetis, N. 2002. Visual competition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3: 1–11CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. 1997. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 375–416. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2001. Paradox and cross purposes in recent work on consciousness. Cognition 79: 197–219CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Botero, J.-J. 1999. The immediately given as ground and background. In Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M. (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, pp. 440–463. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1997. Two kinds of consciousness. In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 427–434. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 1997. Availability: The cognitive basis of experience? In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 421–424. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 2000. What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In Metzinger, T. (ed.), Neural Correlates of Consciousness, pp. 18–39. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Church, J. 1997. Fallacies or analyses? In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 425–426. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 2002. Brainwise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Cosmelli, D. 2004. Des montagnes et des vallées: Perception consciente et structure dynamique de l'intégration cérebrale chez l'être humain dans l'expérience de rivalité binoculaire. Doctoral thesis. Paris: Ecole PolytechniqueGoogle Scholar
Cosmelli, D., David, O., Lachaux, J.-P., Martinerie, J., Garnero, L., Renault, B., and Varela, F. J. 2004. Waves of consciousness: Ongoing cortical patterns during binocular rivalry. Neuroimage 23: 128–140CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crick, F., and Koch, C. 1998. Consciousness and neuroscience. Cerebral Cortex 8: 97–107CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crick, F., and Koch, C. 2003. A framework for consciousness. Nature Neuroscience 6: 119–126CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Damasio, A. R. 1990. Synchronous activation in multiple cortical regions: A mechanism for recall. Seminars in the Neurosciences 2: 287–297Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt BraceGoogle Scholar
David, O., Cosmelli, D., and Friston, K. J. 2004. Evaluation of a different measures of functional connectivity using a neural mass model. Neuroimage 21: 659–673CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
David, O., Cosmelli, D., Hasboun, D., and Garnero, L. 2003. A multitrial analysis for revealing significant corticocortical networks in magentoencaphalography and electroencephalography. Neuroimage 20: 186–201CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
David, O., Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-P., Baillet, S., Garnero, L., and Martinerie, J. 2003. A theoretical and experimental introduction to the non-invasive study of large-scale neural phase-synchronization in human beings (invited paper). International Journal of Computational Cognition (http://www.YangSky.com/yangijcc.htm) 1: 53–77Google Scholar
David, O., Garnero, L., Cosmelli, D., and Varela, F. J. 2002. Estimation of neural dynamics from MEG/EEG cortical current density maps: Application to the reconstruction of large-scale cortical synchrony. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical Engineering 49: 975–987CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davidson, R. J., Kabat-Zinn, J., Schumacher, J., Rosenkranz, M., Muller, D., Santorelli, S. F., Urbanowski, F., Harrington, A., Bonus, K., and Sheridan, J. F. 2003. Alterations in brain and immune function produced by mindfulness meditation. Psychosomatic Medicine 65: 564–570CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dehaene, S., and Naccache, L. 2001. Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition 79: 1–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little BrownGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. 1997. The path not taken. In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 417–420. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. 2001. Are we explaining consciousness yet? Cognition 79: 221–237CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dennett, D. C., and Kinsbourne, D. C. 1992. Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15: 183–247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depraz, N. 1999. The phenomenological reduction as praxis. In Varela, F. J. and Shear, J. (eds.), The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study of Consciousness, pp. 95–110. Thorverton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Depraz, N., and Cosmelli, D. 2004. Empathy and openness: Practices of intersubjectivity at the core of the science of consciousness. In Thompson, E. (ed.), The Problem of Consciousness: New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume. Calgary: University of Alberta PressGoogle Scholar
Depraz, N., Varela, F. J., and Vermersch, P. 2000. The gesture of awareness: An account of its structural dynamics. In Velmans, M. (ed.), Investigating Phenomenal Consciousness, pp. 121–136. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depraz, N., Varela, F. J., and Vermersch, P. 2003. On Becoming Aware. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derryberry, D., and Tucker, D. M. 1994. Motivating the focus of attention. In Niedenthal, P. M. and Kitayama, S. (eds.), The Heart's Eye: Emotional Influences in Perception and Attention, pp. 167–196. New York: Academic PressGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. 1991. Being-In-The-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. 2002. Intelligence without representation – Merleau-Ponty's critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 367–383CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H., and Dreyfus, S. 1982. Mind over Machine. New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Ellis, R. 2001. Implications of inattentional blindness for ‘enactive’ theories of consciousness. Brain and Mind 2: 297–322CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engel, A., and Singer, W. 2001. Temporal binding and the neural correlates of sensory awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5: 16–25CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Engel, A. K., Fries, P., and Singer, W. 2001. Dynamic predictions: Oscillations and synchrony in top-down processing. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2: 704–716CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Epstein, M. 1996. Thoughts Without a Thinker. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Foreman, R. K. C. (ed.). 1990. The Problem of Pure Consciousness. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Freeman, W. J. 1999a. How Brains Make up Their Minds. London: Weidenfeld and NicolsonGoogle Scholar
Freeman, W. 1999b. Consciousness, intentionality, and causality. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6: 143–172Google Scholar
Freeman, W. J. 2000. Emotion is essential to all intentional behaviors. In Lewis, M. and Granic, I. (eds.), Emotion, Development, and Self-Organization, pp. 209–235. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Fries, P., Reynolds, J. H., Rorie, A. E., and Desimone, R. 2001. Modulation of oscillatory neuronal synchronization by selective visual attention. Science 291: 1560–1563CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friston, K. J. 2000a. The labile brain. I. Neuronal transients and nonlinear coupling. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B 355: 215–236CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friston, K. J. 2000b. The labile brain. II. Transients, complexity, and selection. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B 355: 237–252CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frith, C. 2002. How can we share experiences? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 374CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gallagher, S. 1986. Lived body and environment. Research in Phenomenology 16: 139–170CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendlin, E. T. 1981. Focusing. New York: BantamGoogle Scholar
Gupta, B. 1998. The Disinterested Witness. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University PressGoogle Scholar
Gurwitsch, A. 1964. The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh, PA: Dusquesne University PressGoogle Scholar
Hanna, R., and Thompson, E. 2004. Neurophenomenology and the spontaneity of consciousness. In Thompson, E. (ed.), The Problem of Consciousness: New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume. Calgary: University of Alberta PressGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1996. Being and Time. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York PressGoogle Scholar
Hobson, J. A. 1999. Consciousness. New York: W. H. FreemanGoogle Scholar
Hurlbert, R. T., and Heavey, C. L. 2001. Telling what we know: Describing inner experience. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5: 400–403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurley, S. L., and Noë, A. 2003. Neural plasticity and consciousness. Biology and Philosophy 18: 131–168CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 2001. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Trans. A. J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic PublishersCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jack, A. I., and Roepstorff, A. 2002. Introspection and cognitive brain mapping: From stimulus-response to script-report. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 333–339CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jack, A. I., and Roepstorff, A. (eds.). 2003. Trusting the Subject? The Use of Introspective Evidence in Cognitive Science. Volume 1. Thorverton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Jack, A. I., and Shallice, T. 2001. Introspective physicalism as an approach to the science of consciousness. Cognition 79: 161–196CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jonas, H. 1966. The Phenomenon of Life. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Kabat-Zinn, J. 1990. Full Catastrophe Living: Using the Wisdom of Your Body and Mind to Face Stress, Pain, and Illness. New York: DellGoogle Scholar
Kahana, M. J., Seelig, D., and Madsen, J. R. 2001. Theta returns. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 11: 739–744CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kanwisher, N. 2001. Neural events and perceptual awareness. Cognition 79: 89–113CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelso, J. A. S. 1995. Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Köhler, W. 1947. Gestalt Psychology. New York: LiverightGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2003. Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: Two views and an argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 103–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Lachaux, J.-P., Chavez, M., and Lutz, A. 2003. A simple measure of correlation across time, frequency and space between continuous brain signals. Journal of Neuroscience Methods 123: 175–188CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., Martinerie, J., and Varela, F. J. 1999. Measuring phase synchrony in brain signals. Human Brain Mapping 8: 194–2083.0.CO;2-C>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lambie, J. A., and Marcel, A. J. 2002. Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: A theoretical framework. Psychological Review 109: 219–259CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Quyen, M. 2003. Disentangling the dynamic core: A research program for neurodynamics at the large scale. Biological Research 36: 67–88CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Quyen, M., and Petitmengin, C. 2002. Neuronal dynamics and conscious experience: An example of reciprocal causation before epileptic seizures. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 169–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, M. D. 2000. Emotional self-organization at three time scales. In Lewis, M. D. and Granic, I. (eds.), Emotion, Development, and Self-Organization: Dynamic Systems Approaches to Emotional Development, pp. 37–69. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, M. D. In press. Bridging emotion theory and neurobiology through dynamic systems modeling. Behavioral and Brain SciencesGoogle Scholar
Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D., and Pedroarena, C. 1998. The neuronal basis for consciousness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B 353: 1801–1818CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lutz, A. 2002. Toward a neurophenomenology as an account of generative passages: A first empirical case study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 133–167CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lutz, A., and Thompson, E. 2003. Neurophenomenology: Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10: 31–52Google Scholar
Lutz, A., Lachaux, J.-P., Martinerie, J., and Varela, F. J. 2002. Guiding the study of brain dynamics by using first-person data: Synchrony patterns correlate with ongoing conscious states during a simple visual task. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 99: 1586–1591CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maturana, H. R. 1969. The neurophysiology of cognition. In Garvin, P. (ed.), Cognition: A Multiple View. New York: Spartan BooksGoogle Scholar
Maturana, H. R. 1970. Biology of cognition. In Maturana, H. R. and Varela, F. J., Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living, pp. 2–58. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 43. Dordrecht: D. ReidelGoogle Scholar
Maturana, H. R., and Varela, F J. 1980. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 42. Dordrecht: D. ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. C. Smith. London: Routledge PressGoogle Scholar
Metzinger, T. (ed.). 2000. Neural Correlates of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Moran, D. 2000. Introduction to Phenomenology. London: Routledge PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moustakas, C. 1994. Phenomenological Research Methods. Thousand Oaks, London, New Delhi: Sage PublicationsCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 1979. What is it like to be a bat? In Nagel, T., Mortal Questions, pp. 165–180. New York: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Noë, A., and Thompson, E. 2004a. Are there neural correlates of consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 3–28Google Scholar
Noë, A., and Thompson, E. 2004b. Sorting out the neural basis of consciousness: Authors' reply to commentators. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 87–98Google Scholar
Ohl, F. W., Scheich, H., and Freeman, W. J. 2001. Change in pattern of ongoing cortical activity with auditory category learning. Nature 412: 733–736CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O'Keefe, J., and Burgess, N. 1999. Theta activity, virtual navigation and the human hippocampus. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11: 403–406CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Regan, J. K., and Noë, A. 2001. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 939–1031CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Panksepp, J. 1998a. Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Panksepp, J. 1998b. The periconscious substrates of consciousness: Affective states and the evolutionary origins of self. Journal of Consciousness Studies 5: 566–582Google Scholar
Parvizi, J., and Damasio, A. 2001. Consciousness and the brainstem. Cognition 79: 135–159CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pessoa, L., Thompson, E., and Noë, A. 1998. Finding out about filling-in: A guide to perceptual completion for visual science and the philosophy of perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21: 723–802CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Petitmengin, C. 2001. L'expérience intuitive. Paris: L'HarmattanGoogle Scholar
Petitmengin-Peugeot, C. 1999. The intuitive experience. In Varela, F. J. and Shear, J. (eds.), The View from Within, pp. 43–78. Thorveton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M. (eds.). 1999. Naturalizing Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Price, D., and Barrell, J. 1980. An experiential approach with quantitative methods: A research paradigm. Journal of Humanistic Psychology 20: 75–95Google Scholar
Price, D., Barrell, J., and Rainville, P. 2002. Integrating experiential-phenomenological methods and neuroscience to study neural mechanisms of pain and consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 11: 593–608CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rees, G., Krieman, G., and Koch, C. 2002. Neural correlates of consciousness in humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3: 261–270CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rodriguez, E., George, N., Lachaux, J. P., Martinerie, J., Renault, B., and Varela, F. J. 1999. Perception's shadow: Long-distance synchronization of human brain activity. Nature 397: 430–433CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rosenthal, D. M. 1997. A theory of consciousness. In Block, N. et al. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness, pp. 729–753. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Roy, J.-M. 2004. Phenomenological claims and the myth of the given. In E. Thompson (ed.), The Problem of Consciousness: New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume
Roy, J.-M., Petitot, J., Pachoud, B., and Varela, F. J. 1999. Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M. (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology, pp. 1–80. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Rudrauf, D., Lutz, A., Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-P., and Van Quyen, M. 2003. From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. Biological Research 36: 27–66CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sarnthein, J., Petsche, H., Rappelsberger, P., Shaw, G. L., and Stein, A. 1998. Synchronization between prefrontal and posterior association cortex during human working memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 95: 7092–7096CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sartre, J.-P. 1956. Being and Nothingness. Trans. Hazel Barnes. New York: Philosophical LibraryGoogle Scholar
Schiff, S. J., So, P., Chang, T., Burke, R. E., and Sauer, T. 1996. Detecting dynamical interdependence and generalized synchrony through mutual prediction in a neural ensemble. Physical Review E 54: 6706–6724CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schooler, J. W. 2002. Re-representing consciousness: Dissociations between experience and meta-consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 339–344CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Searle, J. S. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. 2000. Consciousness. Annual Review of Neuroscience 23: 557–578CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Searle, J. 2004. Comments on Noë & Thompson ‘Are there NCCs?’Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 79–82Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1956. Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In Feigl, H. and Scriven, M. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 1. The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, pp. 253–329. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Singer, W. 1999. Neuronal synchrony: A versatile code for the definition of relations? Neuron 24: 49–65CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Steinbock, A. J. 1999. Saturated intentionality. In Welton, Donn (ed.), The Body, pp. 178–199. Oxford: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8: 1–32Google Scholar
Thompson, E. (ed.). 2004. The Problem of Consciousness. New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume. Calgary: University of Alberta PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. Forthcoming. Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E., and Varela, F. J. 2001. Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5: 418–425CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thompson, E., and Zahavi, D. In press. Contemporary Continental perspectives: Phenomenology. In Zelazo, P. D. and Moscovitsch, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Consciousness. New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E., Noë, A., and Pessoa, L. 1999. Perceptual completion: A case study in phenomenology and cognitive science. In Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M. (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, pp. 161–195. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E., Palacios, A., and Varela, F. J. 1992. Ways of coloring: Comparative color vision as a case study for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15: 1–74. Reprinted in Alva Noë and Evan Thompson (eds.), Vision and Mind: Readings in the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002
Tononi, G., and Edelman, G. M. 1998. Consciousness and complexity. Science 282: 1846–1851CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
VanRullen, R., and Koch, C. 2003. Is perception discrete or continuous? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 207–213CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Varela, F. J. 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier North HollandGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1991. Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In Tauber, A. (ed.), Organism and the Origin of Self, pp. 79–107. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic PublishersCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1995. Resonant cell assemblies: A new approach to cognitive functions and neuronal synchrony. Biological Research 28: 81–95Google ScholarPubMed
Varela, F. J. 1996. Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3: 330–350Google Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1997a. Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1997b. The naturalization of phenomenology as the transcendence of nature. Alter 5: 355–381Google Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1999. The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In Petitot, J. et al. (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology, pp. 266–314. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J., and Bourgine, P. (eds.). 1991. Toward a Practice of Autonomous Systems: Proceedings of the First European Conference on Artificial Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J., and Shear, J. 1999a. First-person accounts: Why, what, and how. In Varela, F. J. and Shear, J. (eds.), The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study of Consciousness, pp. 1–14. Thorveton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J., and Shear, J. (eds.). 1999b. The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study of Consciousness. Thorverton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J., and Thompson, E. 2003. Neural synchrony and the unity of mind: A neurophenomenological perspective. In Cleeremans, A. (ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration and Dissociation, pp. 266–287. New York: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J., Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., and Martinerie, J. 2001. The brainweb: Phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2: 229–239CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Stein, A., and Sarnthein, J. 2000. Different frequencies for different scales of cortical intergration: From local gamma to long range alpha/theta synchronization. International Journal of Psychophysiology 38: 301–313CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, A., Chiang, C., and König, P. 2000. Top-down processing mediated by interareal synchronization. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 97: 14748–14753CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, A. 1998. The Bridge of Quiescence: Experiencing Tibetan Buddhist Meditation. La Salle, IL: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Wallace, A. 1999. The Buddhist tradition of shamatha: Methods for refining and examining consciousness. In Varela, F. J. and Shear, J. (eds.), The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study of Consciousness, pp. 175–188. Thorverton, UK: Imprint AcademicGoogle Scholar
Watt, D. F. 1999. Emotion and consciousness: Implications of affective neuroscience for extended reticular thalamic activating system theories of consciousness. Electronic publication of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Available at: http://server.philvt.edu/assc/watt/default.htm
Wider, K. V. 1997. The Bodily Basis of Consciousness: Sartre and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Williams, P. 1998. The Reflexive Nature of Awareness. London: Curzon PressGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-Awareness and Alterity. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University PressGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2002. First-person thoughts and embodied self-awareness: Some reflections on the relation between recent analytic philosophy and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 7–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2003. Husserl's Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2004. Intentionality and phenomenality: A phenomenological take on the hard problem. In Thompson, E. (ed.), The Problem of Consciousness: New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume. Calgary: University of Alberta PressGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D., and Parnas, J. 1998. Phenomenal consciousness and self-awareness: A phenomenological critique of representational theory. Journal of Consciousness Studies 5: 687–705Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×