Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-26T14:14:07.789Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 3 - The Single Observer Standpoint and Its Limits

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Anthony J. Cascardi
Affiliation:
University of California, Berkeley
Get access

Summary

Alongside Plato’s theory of Forms and Aristotle’s writings on mimesis, there is perhaps no more powerful set of views on questions of truth in philosophy than those that revolve around the modern conception of the “single observer standpoint.” In epistemology, this underlies the notion of truth as seen from an objective position; in moral philosophy, it underlies the notion of judgment from an impartial perspective. The stance of the distanced and impartial observer underlies the conviction that the world is as it is, can be known as it is, and can be represented as it is known independent of our conceptual frames, linguistic practices, historical conditions, and conventional agreements. What is also important to notice is how readily the “ideal” and “impartial” standpoints are thought of in relation to the activity of observation. Observation is understood as a form of impartial looking, which is why it has served as such a powerful metaphor for knowledge and judgment.

In beginning to speak about conventions and agreements in Chapter 2, we have already begun to explore some views that offer alternatives to such ideas. But before we go further in exploring alternatives, we need to explain how the attempt to find a ground for truth and a similarly universal standpoint for morality came to rely on vision, and specifically how these efforts came to rely on vision as modeled on the sight of the “punctual” individual. Observation is modeled as we have come to imagine human vision is: it involves the “sight” of an individual who regards the world from a punctual standpoint but impersonally. To understand how these metaphors became so powerful, and to understand how the idea of vision in the punctual, individual sense could serve to support so many ideas underlying conceptions of truth and value, we need to invoke a third notion. This is the notion of the subject. Heidegger described subjectivity through its Latin and Greek roots (subiectum, hypokeimenon), which point to the idea of an “underlying ground” for everything that is. Beginning with Descartes, subjectivity was not just one world view among others, or a realm of competing world views, and it certainly was not a synonym for relativism. Rather, it became the position from which we set the world before us as if it were a representation to be viewed.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Butler, Judith, Gender Trouble (New York: Routledge, 1999).Google Scholar
Cascardi, Anthony J., The Subject of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, John, Art and Education (New York: Capricorn, 1958).Google Scholar
Dewey, John, The Quest for Certainty (New York: Putnam, 1960).Google Scholar
Habermas, Jurgen, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Lawrence, Frederick (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987).Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund, Cartesian Meditations, trans. Cairns, Dorion (The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1960).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judovitz, Dalia, Subjectivity and Representation in Descartes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).Google Scholar
Nancy, Jean-Luc, “Larvatus Pro Deo,” In Glyph, 2, trans. Daniel Brewer, (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), pp. 14–36.Google Scholar
Pippin, Robert, The Persistence of Subjectivity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiss, Timothy, The Discourse of Modernism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Richetti, John, Philosophical Writing: Locke, Berkeley, Hume (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vardoulakis, Dimitris, The Doppelgänger: Literature’s Philosophy (New York: Fordham University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×