We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
We present the true stages machinery and illustrate its applications to descriptive set theory. We use this machinery to provide new proofs of the Hausdorff–Kuratowski and Wadge theorems on the structure of $\mathbf {\Delta }^0_\xi $, Louveau and Saint Raymond’s separation theorem, and Louveau’s separation theorem.
We define the Scott complexity of a countable structure to be the least complexity of a Scott sentence for that structure. This is a finer notion of complexity than Scott rank: it distinguishes between whether the simplest Scott sentence is
$\Sigma _{\alpha }$
,
$\Pi _{\alpha }$
, or
$\mathrm {d-}\Sigma _{\alpha }$
. We give a complete classification of the possible Scott complexities, including an example of a structure whose simplest Scott sentence is
$\Sigma _{\lambda + 1}$
for
$\lambda $
a limit ordinal. This answers a question left open by A. Miller.
We also construct examples of computable structures of high Scott rank with Scott complexities
$\Sigma _{\omega _1^{CK}+1}$
and
$\mathrm {d-}\Sigma _{\omega _1^{CK}+1}$
. There are three other possible Scott complexities for a computable structure of high Scott rank:
$\Pi _{\omega _1^{CK}}$
,
$\Pi _{\omega _1^{CK}+1}$
,
$\Sigma _{\omega _1^{CK}+1}$
. Examples of these were already known. Our examples are computable structures of Scott rank
$\omega _1^{CK}+1$
which, after naming finitely many constants, have Scott rank
$\omega _1^{CK}$
. The existence of such structures was an open question.
We show that there is a cuppable c.e. degree, all of whose cupping partners are high. In particular, not all cuppable degrees are ${\operatorname {\mathrm {low}}}_3$-cuppable, or indeed ${\operatorname {\mathrm {low}}}_n$ cuppable for any n, refuting a conjecture by Li. On the other hand, we show that one cannot improve highness to superhighness. We also show that the ${\operatorname {\mathrm {low}}}_2$-cuppable degrees coincide with the array computable-cuppable degrees, giving a full understanding of the latter class.
We describe punctual categoricity in several natural classes, including binary relational structures and mono-unary functional structures. We prove that every punctually categorical structure in a finite unary language is ${\text {PA}}(0')$-categorical, and we show that this upper bound is tight. We also construct an example of a punctually categorical structure whose degree of categoricity is $0''$. We also prove that, with a bit of work, the latter result can be pushed beyond $\Delta ^1_1$, thus showing that punctually categorical structures can possess arbitrarily complex automorphism orbits.
As a consequence, it follows that binary relational structures and unary structures are not universal with respect to primitive recursive interpretations; equivalently, in these classes every rich enough interpretation technique must necessarily involve unbounded existential quantification or infinite disjunction. In contrast, it is well-known that both classes are universal for Turing computability.
A problem is a multivalued function from a set of instances to a set of solutions. We consider only instances and solutions coded by sets of integers. A problem admits preservation of some computability-theoretic weakness property if every computable instance of the problem admits a solution relative to which the property holds. For example, cone avoidance is the ability, given a noncomputable set A and a computable instance of a problem
${\mathsf {P}}$
, to find a solution relative to which A is still noncomputable.
In this article, we compare relativized versions of computability-theoretic notions of preservation which have been studied in reverse mathematics, and prove that the ones which were not already separated by natural statements in the literature actually coincide. In particular, we prove that it is equivalent to admit avoidance of one cone, of
$\omega $
cones, of one hyperimmunity or of one non-
$\Sigma ^{0}_1$
definition. We also prove that the hierarchies of preservation of hyperimmunity and non-
$\Sigma ^{0}_1$
definitions coincide. On the other hand, none of these notions coincide in a nonrelativized setting.
We review the current knowledge concerning strong jump-traceability. We cover the known results relating strong jump-traceability to randomness, and those relating it to degree theory. We also discuss the techniques used in working with strongly jump-traceable sets. We end with a section of open questions.
This article contributes to the general program of extending techniques and ideas of effective algebra to computable metric space theory. It is well-known that relative computable categoricity (to be defined) of a computable algebraic structure is equivalent to having a c.e. Scott family with finitely many parameters (e.g., [1]). The first main result of the article extends this characterisation to computable Polish metric spaces. The second main result illustrates that just a slight change of the definitions will give us a new notion of categoricity unseen in the countable case (to be stated formally). The second result also shows that the characterisation of computably categorical closed subspaces of ${\Cal R}^n $ contained in [17] cannot be improved. The third main result extends the characterisation to not necessarily separable structures of cardinality κ using κ-computability.
We introduce a new hierarchy of computably enumerable degrees. This hierarchy is based on computable ordinal notations measuring complexity of approximation of ${\rm{\Delta }}_2^0$ functions. The hierarchy unifies and classifies the combinatorics of a number of diverse constructions in computability theory. It does so along the lines of the high degrees (Martin) and the array noncomputable degrees (Downey, Jockusch, and Stob). The hierarchy also gives a number of natural definability results in the c.e. degrees, including a definable antichain.
We use concepts of continuous higher randomness, developed in Bienvenu et al. [‘Continuous higher randomness’, J. Math. Log.17(1) (2017).], to investigate $\unicode[STIX]{x1D6F1}_{1}^{1}$-randomness. We discuss lowness for $\unicode[STIX]{x1D6F1}_{1}^{1}$-randomness, cupping with $\unicode[STIX]{x1D6F1}_{1}^{1}$-random sequences, and an analogue of the Hirschfeldt–Miller characterization of weak 2-randomness. We also consider analogous questions for Cohen forcing, concentrating on the class of $\unicode[STIX]{x1D6F4}_{1}^{1}$-generic reals.
We construct an increasing ${\it\omega}$-sequence $\langle \boldsymbol{a}_{n}\rangle$ of Turing degrees which forms an initial segment of the Turing degrees, and such that each $\boldsymbol{a}_{n+1}$ is diagonally nonrecursive relative to $\boldsymbol{a}_{n}$. It follows that the DNR principle of reverse mathematics does not imply the existence of Turing incomparable degrees.
We show that a Δ02 Turing degree computes solutions to all computable instances of the finite intersection principle if and only if it computes a 1-generic degree. We also investigate finite and infinite variants of the principle.
We study the computable structure theory of linear orders of size $\aleph _1 $ within the framework of admissible computability theory. In particular, we characterize which of these linear orders are computably categorical.
We study the computable structure theory of linear orders of size $\aleph _1 $ within the framework of admissible computability theory. In particular, we study degree spectra and the successor relation.
We show the existence of noncomputable oracles which are low for Demuth randomness, answering a question in [15] (also Problem 5.5.19 in [34]). We fully characterize lowness for Demuth randomness using an appropriate notion of traceability. Central to this characterization is a partial relativization of Demuth randomness, which may be more natural than the fully relativized version. We also show that an oracle is low for weak Demuth randomness if and only if it is computable.
Classical computable model theory is most naturally concerned with countable domains. There are, however, several methods – some old, some new – that have extended its basic concepts to uncountable structures. Unlike in the classical case, however, no single dominant approach has emerged, and different methods reveal different aspects of the computable content of uncountable mathematics. This book contains introductions to eight major approaches to computable uncountable mathematics: descriptive set theory; infinite time Turing machines; Blum-Shub-Smale computability; Sigma-definability; computability theory on admissible ordinals; E-recursion theory; local computability; and uncountable reverse mathematics. This book provides an authoritative and multifaceted introduction to this exciting new area of research that is still in its early stages. It is ideal as both an introductory text for graduate and advanced undergraduate students and a source of interesting new approaches for researchers in computability theory and related areas.
In contrast with the notion of complexity, a set A is called anti-complex if the Kolmogorov complexity of the initial segments of A chosen by a recursive function is always bounded by the identity function. We show that, as for complexity, the natural arena for examining anti-complexity is the weak-truth table degrees. In this context, we show the equivalence of anti-complexity and other lowness notions such as r.e. traceability or being weak truth-table reducible to a Schnorr trivial set. A set A is anti-complex if and only if it is reducible to another set B with tiny use, whereby we mean that the use function for reducing A to B can be made to grow arbitrarily slowly, as gauged by unbounded nondecreasing recursive functions. This notion of reducibility is then studied in its own right, and we also investigate its range and the range of its uniform counterpart.
Abstract We use the theory of recursion on admissible ordinals to develop an analogue of classical computable model theory and effective algebra for structures of size ℵ1, which, under our assumptions, is equal to the continuum. We discuss both general concepts, such as computable categoricity, and particular classes of examples, such as fields and linear orderings.
§1. Introduction. Our aim is to develop computable structure theory for uncountable structures. In this paper we focus on structures of size ℵ1. The fundamental decision to be made, when trying to formulate such a theory, is the choice of computability tools that we intend to use. To discover which structures are computable, we need to first describe which subsets of the domain are computable, and which functions are computable. In this paper, we use admissible recursion theory (also known as α-recursion theory) over the domain ω1. We believe that this choice yields an interesting computable structure theory. It also illuminates the concepts and techniques of classical computable structure theory by observing similarities and differences between the countable and uncountable settings. In particular, it seems that as is the case for degree theory and for the study of the lattice of c.e. sets, the difference between true finiteness and its analogue in the generalised case, namely countability in our case, is fundamental to some constructions and reveals a deep gap between classical computability and attempts to generalise it to the realm of the uncountable.