We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Res judicata is a core belief of international law; the ICJ’s judgments are seen as final and without appeal, to doubt that is apparently equal to calling the entire international legal order into question. But the doctrine is not as absolute as the orthodoxy makes it out to be, neither as a matter of positive international law nor as a statement of legal theory. Even final judgements are not always final and appeals procedures and judicial review are not special in that they engage res judicata whereas regular legal change does not; rather, both do from a legal-theoretical vantage-point. This article makes the point by looking at ICJ interpretation judgments under Article 60; it argues that, far from leaving the original judgment’s res judicata intact, interpretation judgments actually impinge or even disrupt it. The article discusses ICJ interpretation judgments (the 2013 judgment in Preah Vihear serving as convenient example), introduces Adolf Julius Merkl’s Error Calculus theory as the theoretical framework best suited to analysing the nomomechanics and critiques the Preah Vihear interpretation judgment as change disguised as a hermeneutic exercise. It then turns the critical enterprise on its head to look at the Error Calculus theory itself to lay the groundwork for an even more audacious argument that the Error Calculus does not depend on errors in the narrow sense of the word: it is neither an ex post ratification of an imperfect norm nor a confirmation of invalidity, but the derogation of a perfectly valid norm.
There is a fundamental, eternal and unresolvable conundrum at the heart of customary international law (CIL): we do not know on what we should base our arguments. The debates on the theory of CIL continue unabated, because there is a strong belief that we need it in order to keep international law working. But is that legal reason enough to consciously or subconsciously change the mechanics of customary law to suit these needs? The ILC’s CIL project is suffused with the spirit of pragmatism, but it could not avoid taking a stance on theory. On the other side are foundational critiques of CIL, like Jean d’Aspremont’s: custom is merely a story international lawyers tell themselves. Both methods have virtues and very dangerous vices and contain the seeds for their own destruction. One aim of this chapter will therefore be an effort to show the relative merits of these techniques from a theoretical point of view. My portrayal usually stops at the recognition that we cannot find the law which tells us the rules of CIL-making. In this chapter, I will attempt to go a step further to a new method for conceptualising this: the Approximatively Plausible Empowerment Norm.
Although customary international law (CIL) has been central to international law from its inception, it is often misunderstood. This edited volume remedies that problem by tracing the history of CIL and provides an in-depth study of its theory, practice, and interpretation. Its chapters tackle the big questions which surround this source of international law such as: what are the rules that regulate the functioning of CIL as a source of international law? Can CIL be interpreted? Where do lines between identification, interpretation, application, and modification of a rule of CIL lie? Using recent developments, this volume revisits old debates and resolves them by proffering new and innovative solutions. With detailed examples from international and national courts, it places CIL in a range of settings to explain, explore and reflect upon this developing and highly significant field. This title is also available as Open Access on Cambridge Core.
Can a doctrinal scholarship which is based on the normativist-positivist framework espoused in this book do any better than mainstream legal scholarship? Starting from a critique of certain hyper-systematising approaches, the chapter introduces Kelsen’s idea of legal scholarship properly so called, one devoid of external influences because these make it impossible to correctly cognise the law. Reconstructed in this manner, doctrinal scholarship can provide a structural analysis of the law, both on the macro-level of system-coherence and on the micro-level as frame-determination. It can also give practical information on how awards have exercised their freedom within the frame of possible meanings.
Is arbitral investment case-law on expropriation precedential in a legally relevant sense? Orthodox approaches are marked by agreement on a narrow set of arguments, namely that international law is not a common law and arbitral awards do not have stare decisis power, that jurisprudence is hugely important and tribunals rely on it, and that there must therefore be a sort of de facto system of precedents in operation. In effect, ‘factual importance’ is fashioned into a source of legal authority. However, few arguments are given as to why this transfer from fact to law would occur and they do not provide a foundation for a general legal value for precedents. Yet the weight of arbitral jurisprudence is both too great to ignore and too helpful in discovering what ‘’ means in a pragmatic sense. Precedents are statements about general norms; outside the common law, judge-made law is merely an interpretation of a general norm in a judgment. Not even a constant tradition of decisions can turn such a statement into a norm.