Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T01:21:47.750Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Decision analysis from a neo-Calvinist point of view

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Drazen Prelec
Affiliation:
Sloan School of Management at MIT
Adam Oliver
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Get access

Summary

By neo-Calvinist point of view, I refer to analysis focused on assessing the diagnostic significance of policy decisions, rather than establishing the direct consequences of decisions. Diagnostic significance refers to information revealed by an irrevocable act, information about some underlying collective value or belief. Decisions, especially those that break with precedent, can expose the tradeoffs between competing values, tradeoffs that society tacitly endorses. In these situations, the role of analysis might be not so much to recommend a course of action, but to clarify what is at stake, the ‘diagnostic risk’ as it were, created by the choice.

Here I outline a simple framework for how this analysis might proceed. The core ideas are taken from an earlier self-signalling model of choice (Bodner and Prelec, 2003; Prelec and Bodner, 2003). That model postulated a distinction between two types of utility: utility that flows directly from the causal consequences of choice, and diagnostic utility, which is the pleasure or pain derived from learning something positive or negative about one’s own internal state, disposition, ability or future prospects. People are presumed to be chronically uncertain about where they stand with respect to these broad attributes, which in turn makes their choices diagnostic. Anticipation of diagnostic reward, or fear of diagnostic pain, promotes self-control and inhibits self-indulgence.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ainslie, G. (1992). Picoeconomics: The Strategic Interaction of Successive Motivational States Within the Person. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bem, D. (1972). Self-Perception Theory. In Berkowitz, L. (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. New York: Academic Press, pp. 1–62.Google Scholar
Benabou, R. and Tirole, J. (2004). Willpower and Personal Rules. Journal of Political Economy 112: 848–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B. and Thomadsen, R. (2005). Memory and Anticipation. Economic Journal 115: 271–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodner, R. and Prelec, D. (2003). Self-Signalling and Diagnostic Utility in Everyday Decision-Making. In Brocas, I. and Carillo, J. (eds.), Psychology of Economic Decisions, vol. 1. Oxford University Press, pp. 105–24.Google Scholar
Cho, I. and Sobel, J. (1990). Strategic Stability and Uniqueness in Signaling Games. Journal of Economic Theory 50: 381–413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginossar, Z. and Trope, Y. (1987). Problem Solving in Judgment under Uncertainty. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52: 464–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mijovic-Prelec, D. and Prelec, D. (2010). Self-Deception as Self-Signaling: A Model and Experimental Evidence. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biology 365: 227–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monterosso, J. R. and Ainslie, G. (1999). Beyond Discounting: Possible Experimental Models of Impulse Control. Psychopharmacology (Berl). 146: 339–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Prelec, D. and Bodner, R. (2003). Self-Signaling and Self-Control. In Loewenstein, G., Read, D. and Baumeister, R. F. (eds.), Time and Decision. New York: Russell Sage, pp. 277–98.Google Scholar
Quattrone, G. and Tversky, A. (1984). Causal versus Diagnostic Contingencies: On Self-Deception and on the Voter’s Illusion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 46: 237–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sanitioso, R., Kunda, Z. and Fong, G. T. (1990). Motivated Recruitment of Autobiographical Memory. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59: 229–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, M. (2002). The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Trans. Baehr, P. and Wells, G. C.. Penguin Books.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×