Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T03:52:47.406Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 6 - Deontology and Deterrence for Free Will Deniers

from Part II - Alternatives to Retributive Punishment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 August 2019

Elizabeth Shaw
Affiliation:
University of Aberdeen
Derk Pereboom
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Gregg D. Caruso
Affiliation:
Corning Community College, State University of New York
Get access

Summary

In this chapter I outline what I take to be a solution to a problem about free will denial and the justification of punishment pointed out by Saul Smilansky. Smilansky argues that free will deniers must acknowledge that some institution of punishment is necessary to maintain law and order, but since criminals do not deserve to be punished, it is unjust to punish them, and we therefore have a duty to compensate them. Since this is a great injustice, we must compensate them very heavily, in fact so heavily that the institution of punishment will cease to deter and will instead become an incentive to commit crime. Previous responses to Smilansky’s “practical reductio” argument by Neil Levy, Derk Pereboom, and Gregg Caruso have emphasized consequentialist moral reasons. I advocate a deontological social contract approach to punishment that draws on Kantian and Rawlsian notions of treating criminals as ends by respecting their rational consent to punishment.

Type
Chapter
Information
Free Will Skepticism in Law and Society
Challenging Retributive Justice
, pp. 116 - 138
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Caruso, G. D. (2016). Free will skepticism and criminal behavior: A public health-quarantine model. Southwest Philosophical Review, 32(1), 2548.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2017). Public Health and Safety: The Social Determinants of Health and Criminal Behavior. London, UK: ResearchLinks Books.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2019). Free will skepticism and its implications: The case for optimism. In Shaw, E., Pereboom, D., and Caruso, G. D., eds., Free Will Skepticism in Law and Society: Challenging Retributivism, ch.3 [this volume]. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dolovich, S. (2004). Legitimate punishment in liberal democracy. Buffalo Law Review, 7(2), 314329.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J. (1975). Can the maximin principle serve as a basis for morality? A critique of John Rawls’s Theory. The American Political Science Review, 69(2), 594606.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996). The Metaphysics of Morals, ed. and trans. Gregor, M.. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2012). Skepticism and sanction: The benefits of rejecting moral responsibility. Law and Philosophy, 31(5), 477493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without Free Will. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2013). Free will skepticism and criminal punishment. In Nadelhoffer, T., ed., The Future of Punishment. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 4978.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2014). Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2011). Hard determinism and punishment: A practical reductio. Law and Philosophy, 30(3), 353367.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2009). Free will skepticism and personhood as a desert base. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(3), 489511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2013). Persons, punishment, and free will skepticism. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 143163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2015). Free will and the asymmetrical justifiability of holding morally responsible. Philosophical Quarterly, 65(261), 772789.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2017). Kant’s mature theory of punishment and a first Critique ideal abolitionist alternative. In Altman, M. C., ed., Palgrave Kant Handbook. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 617642.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×