Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-lvwk9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T22:31:34.004Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is generalization decay a fundamental law of psychology?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2024

David R. Mandel*
Affiliation:
Defence Research and Development Canada and York University, Toronto, ON, Canada drmandel66@gmail.com https://sites.google.com/site/themandelian/home
*
*Corresponding author.

Abstract

Generalizations strengthen in traditional sciences, but in psychology (and social and behavioral sciences, more generally) they decay. This is usually viewed as a problem requiring solution. It could be viewed instead as a law-like phenomenon. Generalization decay cannot be squelched because human behavior is metastable and all behavioral data collected thus far have resulted from a thin sliver of human time.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Generalizations decay.

Lee J. Cronbach (1975, p. 122)

In traditional scientific disciplines, to use Scriven's (Reference Scriven, Feigl and Scriven1956) terminology, generalizations generally strengthen and can even trigger productive theoretical upheavals. The partial overthrow of Newton's mechanics by Einstein's special theory of relativity would not have happened had Einstein not generalized the Galilean principle of relativity in mechanics (also apparent in Newton's theory) to electrodynamics. Generalization strengthens understanding, sometimes at great cost to status-quo theories. In contrast, in psychology – and more broadly, the social and behavioral sciences – generalizations decay.

The “problem” of generalization decay has long been the subject of scholarly attention, yet no satisfactory solution has been found (Cronbach, Reference Cronbach1975; Scriven, Reference Scriven, Feigl and Scriven1956). A widely discussed reason for such decay is that behavioral phenomena are interactively determined but psychological theories invariably underspecify the full range of interactions and often misspecify the nature of effects (Campbell, Reference Campbell1957; Yarkoni, Reference Yarkoni2022). An optimistic view is that psychology can overcome generalization decay by adopting an interactionist approach to theory generation and testing (e.g., Cronbach, Reference Cronbach1957; Eysenck, Reference Eysenck1997). Calls for methodological reform such as Almaatouq et al.'s proposed “integrative experiment design” also fall into the optimist's camp. However, none of the optimists’ proposals confront the fact that for most topics, psychology does not offer a theoretical basis for knowing how high the order of interactions must be for generalization decay to be squelched.

Take Almaatouq et al.'s example where the design space (i.e., the space defined by all of the measured independent variables and putative moderators) has upward of 50 factors. Even if each factor was binary, the design space would have over a quadrillion cells. Almaatouq et al. cryptically refer to statistical methods that could start with a highly circumscribed sample of cells in this overwhelming space, but these statements do little to inspire confidence in the overall project.

Permitting less ambition, assume a design space of a mere dozen variables split equally between binary and ternary factors. This space has 46,656 cells. Imagine that the researchers learn that, of the 5,667 possible interaction effects, several hundred are significant including over a dozen with n > 7. Would anyone have reason for confidence that such higher-order interactions would replicate if such a costly experiment could ever be repeated? Even if they were all replicable (an amazingly improbable occurrence), would they productively advance fundamental theory in psychology? After all, Newell's (Reference Newell and Chase1973) concern (the entry point for Almaatouq et al.) was not mainly about the lack of generalizability in psychology but, rather, about the slim prospect of theoretical unification even among fine examples of work by the best and brightest minds of his time.

Generalization decay cannot be eliminated through design mandates or interactionist projects because human behavior is metastable over time (Gergen, Reference Gergen1973). Psychologists often make claims about human behavior and cognition as if it applied to all humans across time, but this is unknowable since virtually all research participant data have been collected in a sliver of human history, and even historical records only go back thousands, not hundreds of thousands, of years, as would be required. However, even if psychologists fully exploited historical records of “dead minds,” as Atari and Henrich (Reference Atari and Henrich2023) call for, or even if they miraculously recovered the full record of humanity's past, we have no trace of humanity's actual future. We do not know what proportion of human existence lies ahead or what metastable states it will occupy. Our theories do not project us clearly into the future as in physics, which provides a basis for estimation of physical transformations of the universe over unimaginable timescales (Dyson, Reference Dyson1979; Krauss & Starkman, Reference Krauss and Starkman2000). They do not even project us as well into the past. We have no equivalent of the cosmic microwave background.

Psychologists cannot study the moderating role of social factors that do not yet exist. When life expectancy is universally less than 100 years, psychologists cannot formulate a generalizable theory of lifespan development that applies to humans who might live in an epoch following actuarial escape velocity – the point at which remaining life expectancy increases with time due to mortality rates that plummet due to disruptive scientific and technological breakthroughs (de Grey, Reference de Grey2004). We do not know what human experience will be like in the future. Imagine that in 50 years, the interpretation of quantum mechanics (based on evidence or insights that currently do not exist) indisputably favors the Everettian many worlds hypothesis and it becomes common knowledge that each of us exists in possibly infinite branches of decohered worlds – duh! – what then will social psychologists have to say about the self concept?

Psychology's uncertainty about humanity's past and future may be inevitable, but its comfort with a focus on the moving present reveals a parochial disposition that the traditional sciences outgrew long ago. If young Einstein did not stretch his mind to imagine whether light waves would appear to him to be at rest if he were able to run alongside at the speed of light, and if he did not have Maxwell's equations to show that the wave-at-rest counterfactual could not resolve the equations, he may not have discovered one of the most important theories in the history of science. Psychology banished introspection as a reliable method long ago; and it does not have the equivalent of Maxwell's equations, but where are its creative Machian Gedankenexperiments that may lead us out of musty local minima? The absence of thought experiments that revolutionize theoretical understanding in psychology is itself a mystery that deserves scholarly attention.

Returning to Scriven, “science has not advanced by solving all problems but often by abandoning them…” (Reference Scriven, Feigl and Scriven1956, p. 339). If psychology pines for generalizability, resisting the apparent law of generalization decay, psychologists will need to seek new problems and ways of understanding. A productive path forward may be to seek greater consilience with traditional sciences (Wilson, Reference Wilson1998). Biocosmology offers a promising recent example (Cortês, Kauffman, Liddle, & Smolin, Reference Cortês, Kauffman, Liddle and Smolin2022). Alternatively, psychology could accept historicism as a metatheoretical foundation (Gergen, Reference Gergen1973), and its future might split along such lines.

Financial support

This work was funded by Canadian Safety and Security Program Project CSSP-2018-TI-2394.

Competing interest

None.

Note

His Majesty the King in Right of Canada as represented by Department of National Defence.

References

Atari, M., & Henrich, J. (2023). Historical psychology. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 32(2), 176183. https://doi.org/10.1177/09637214221149737CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, D. T. (1957). Factors relevant to the validity of experiments in social settings. Psychological Bulletin, 54(4), 297312. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0040950CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cortês, M., Kauffman, S. A., Liddle, A. R., & Smolin, L. (2022). Biocosmology: Biology from a cosmological perspective. https://doi.org/10.48550/arXiv.2204.09379CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronbach, L. J. (1957). The two disciplines of scientific psychology. American Psychologist, 12(11), 671684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronbach, L. J. (1975). Beyond the two disciplines of scientific psychology. American Psychologist, 30(2), 116127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Grey, A. D. N. J. (2004). Escape velocity: Why the prospect of extreme human life extension matters now. PLoS Biology, 2(6), e187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyson, F. J. (1979). Time without end: Physics and biology in an open universe. Reviews of Modern Physics, 51(3), 447460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eysenck, H. J. (1997). Personality and experimental psychology: The unification of psychology and the possibility of a paradigm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73(6), 12241237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gergen, K. J. (1973). Social psychology as history. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 26(2), 309320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krauss, L. M., & Starkman, G. D. (2000). Life, the universe, and nothing: Life and death in an ever-expanding universe. The Astrophysical Journal, 531, 2230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, A. (1973). You can't play 20 questions with nature and win: Projective comments on the papers of this symposium. In Chase, W. G. (Ed.), Visual information processing: Proceedings of the eighth annual Carnegie symposium on cognition (pp. 283310). Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scriven, M. (1956). A possible distinction between traditional scientific disciplines and the study of human behavior. In Feigl, H. & Scriven, M. (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 1, pp. 330339). University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. (1998). Consilience: The unity of knowledge. Vintage.Google Scholar
Yarkoni, T. (2022). The generalizability crisis. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 45(e1), 178. doi:10.1017/S0140525X20001685CrossRefGoogle Scholar