Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-fmk2r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T03:31:56.775Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HOMER AND THE LAW - (S.) Almog The Origins of the Law in Homer. (Law and Literature 21.) Pp. viii + 142. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter, 2022. Cased, £72.50, €79.95, US$91.99. ISBN: 978-3-11-076593-9.

Review products

(S.) Almog The Origins of the Law in Homer. (Law and Literature 21.) Pp. viii + 142. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter, 2022. Cased, £72.50, €79.95, US$91.99. ISBN: 978-3-11-076593-9.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 May 2023

Edward M. Harris*
Affiliation:
Durham University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

This volume attempts to introduce the Iliad and the Odyssey ‘into the law and literature canon’ (p. 1). A. follows in the footsteps of J.B. White's The Legal Imagination: Studies in the Nature of Legal Thought and Expression (1973), but sidesteps the issue of the poems’ historicity (one cannot find essays like J.P. Crielaard, ‘Homer, History and Archaeology: Some Remarks on the Date of the Homeric World’, in: J.P. Crielaard [ed.], Homeric Questions [1995], pp. 201–88). A. addresses three main themes: the long conceptualisation of Greek law, ‘the regimentation and juridification (sic) of anger’ and female agency, which was available to women in the Odyssey, but according to A. is blocked in the Oresteia (p. 4).

Chapter 1, ‘Law and Story’, lays out A.'s approach of law alongside literature. In contrast to ‘law as literature’ and ‘law in literature’, law alongside literature ‘reveals the elasticity of the boundaries separating law and literature, and the fluidity that characterizes their interactions’ (p. 15) and involves two stages. The first ‘critically examines the conception of law as a holistic, autonomous, self-contained system by emphasizing the inherently flawed nature of law’ (p. 15). A. does not explain why law is ‘inherently flawed’. According to A. ‘the Homeric epics introduce the need for law by highlighting the individual and societal price incurred by its absence’ (p. 16). The second stage ‘focuses on negotiating the limits and failures of law’ and ‘uses narratives that derive from imagination to suggest solutions’ (p. 16). According to A. literature promotes empathy (p. 16), which may be true of some works of art, but many Attic dramas are hardly sympathetic to non-Greeks (see E.M. Hall, Inventing the Barbarian [1989]). This leads to ‘the establisher (sic) of criminal law in Oresteia’ (p. 16), which ‘depicts law from its inception as a tool serving men and wronging women’ (p. 17). This is certainly one aspect of Athenian law (see already M. Arthur, ‘Early Greece: the Origins of The Western Attitude Towards Women’, Arethusa 6 [1973], 7–58), but it is not the only aspect. One finds no mention of the laws protecting women against sexual violence, the stories in which men attacking women are punished or the laws ensuring the return of the dowry after a divorce.

Chapter 2, ‘Law in the Odyssey – the Story of Motion’, contrasts the ending of the Odyssey with that of the Oresteia. In each work ‘the crisis of revenge poses a threat to the entire public’ and ‘the crisis of revenge is resolved’, but the end of the epic is ‘law-less’ (p. 23). Yet the trial scene on the shield of Achilles shows that ‘a system of conflict resolution already existed in Homeric society’ (p. 25). A. therefore realises that ‘Although the crisis of revenge that ends the Odyssey is not resolved by a judicial procedure, it does not lack a legal dimension’ (p. 31), but ‘the rule of law and respect for the law … did not exist in the Homeric age’ (p. 40). It would have helped if A. had clearly defined what she means by the terms ‘law’ and ‘the rule of law’. One would also like to have seen a discussion of the terms δίκη, θέμις and εὐνομία (Od. 17.487). According to A., ‘The Eumenides is a detailed account of the transfer of divine authority to human responsibility, and an exemplar of how the judicial spectacle should be conducted’ (p. 36). At the same time, the play portrays ‘the relocation of ancient law or retaliation from the realm of the personal to the realm of the polis’ (p. 40). The goddess Athena plays a key role in both works, but A. finds flaws in her decisions because she reveals partiality (p. 44) and aligns her interests with those of the patriarchal elite (p. 46).

Chapter 3, ‘From the Iliad to the Odyssey – Toward the Juridification of Anger’, examines the wrath of Achilles, Odysseus and the gods. The character of Achilles ‘is an amalgam of warning signs against situations in which anger unchecked has fatal and far-reaching consequences that are detrimental to society’ (p. 63). The Iliad is therefore ‘a story of the absence of societal defenses against wrath’ (p. 65). A. claims that Odysseus rejects ‘the social convention regulating revenge’ (p. 68) and exonerates the suitors whose conduct is ‘quite understandable … under the political circumstances’ (p. 70). As a result, A. believes that the end of the Odyssey ‘betrays Homer's discomfort with the intensity and scope of Odysseus’ revenge and the fact that Odysseus escapes punishment’ (p. 69). Not all readers will find the suitors’ plot to kill Telemachus ‘understandable’. The final part of the chapter discusses the will of the gods vs the free will of humans in the Iliad and Odyssey, but misses the important discussion of A. Lesky, Göttliche und menschliche Motivation im homerischen Epos (1961), which shows how both co-exist without affecting human responsibility. A. sees less wrath and more concern for justice among the gods in the Odyssey than in the Iliad (p. 81), but still finds ‘brutal divine anger’ in the Odyssey (p. 83). By contrast, the Oresteia sees the need for the regimentation of anger (p. 86).

Chapter 4, ‘The Metis Syndrome: Women and Law in the Odyssey’, argues that there is a ‘complex dynamic balance that affords women a relatively broad spectrum of action’ in the Odyssey, but that with the rise of formal justice in the Oresteia ‘such spectrum of female action is blocked’ (p. 87). This leads to a discussion of the female agency of Metis (pp. 89–95), Penelope (pp. 95–106), Calypso and Circe (pp. 106–11), Nausicaa and Arete (pp. 111–17), the serving women (sic) (pp. 117–23) and Athena (pp. 123–7). A. does not address the issue of slavery either and labels Eurycleia and Melantho ‘servants’ (pp. 118–23), which is at best misleading (see D.M. Lewis, Greek Slave Systems in their Eastern Mediterranean Context, c. 800–146 b.c. [2018], pp. 107–24). The contrast between the Odyssey and the Oresteia is overdrawn: Electra plays an important role in the Choephoroi, and Athena is the guiding divinity in the Eumenides.

A. is right to see a development in ideas about law from the Iliad and the Odyssey to the Oresteia, but is rather vague about the differences between the epics and the drama because she never decides whether Homeric society is lawless or has respect for legal norms and because she never defines ‘the rule of law’. The book would have benefited from the important discussion of C. Pelloso, ‘The Myth of Priority over Substance in the Light of Early Greek Epos’ (RDE 3 [2013], 223–75), who shows that there is a notion of subjective rights in the Iliad and the Odyssey. The Greeks believed that these rights were better protected by the overthrow of one-man rule and the suppression of anarchy (Aeschylus, Eumenides 526–30).