Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T18:22:19.210Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

When being wasteful appears better than feeling wasteful

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Ro’i Zultan*
Affiliation:
University College London
Maya Bar-Hillel
Affiliation:
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem
*
*Corresponding author: Ro’i Zultan, Department of Cognitive, Perceptual and Brain Sciences, University College London, 26 Bedford Way, London WC1H 0AP, UK. Email: r.zultan@ucl.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

“Waste not want not” expresses our culture’s aversion to waste. “I could have gotten the same thing for less” is a sentiment that can diminish pleasure in a transaction. We study people’s willingness to “pay” to avoid this spoiler. In one scenario, participants imagined they were looking for a rental apartment, and had bought a subscription to an apartment listing. If a cheaper subscription had been declined, respondents preferred not to discover post hoc that it would have sufficed. Specifically, they preferred ending their quest for the ideal apartment after seeing more, rather than fewer, apartments, so that the length of the search exceeds that available within the cheaper subscription. Other scenarios produced similar results. We conclude that people may sometimes prefer to be wasteful in order to avoid feeling wasteful.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2010] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

Recently, one of our friends was upset. She had just rented a perfect little apartment, advertised on a campus bulletin board. “But”, she said, “I had just paid a non-refundable fee for an apartments listing. Now I feel like a freier” (a Yiddish word, roughly meaning patsy, sucker, or pushover).

Spending more money than necessary is regarded as wasteful. When not intentional, and easily avoidable, it can make one feel like a freier. Admittedly, sometimes people overspend deliberately. People show off their wealth by shopping in wildly expensive places. Others flaunt their disregard for money by lighting up cigars with $20 bills. People also choose to be generous, giving expensive gifts, throwing elaborate parties, tipping ostentatiously, etc. Extravagance is not to be equated with waste. But when actions are self-defined as wasteful, the feeling of wastefulness can be as aversive, if not more, than the waste itself.

Mental accounting (Thaler, Reference Thaler1999) provides a useful framework for understanding waste. If you want a new pair of jeans, $500 is wasteful. But if you want Prada jeans, $500 may be a bargain. To please your hosts, a $30 wine may be adequate. But to impress them, you should lay out more. When you open a mental account, and enter a debit, you can judge for yourself whether the resulting outcome was “worth it”. But mental accounting does not explain why the feeling of waste is so aversive.

Arkes, an expert on the psychology of waste (Arkes, Reference Arkes1996; Arkes & Blumer, Reference Arkes and Blumer1985; Arkes & Ayton, Reference Arkes and Ayton1999; Arkes & Hutzel, Reference Arkes, Hutzel, Bazerman, Messick, Tenbrunsel and Wade-Benzoni1997), has defined waste in two ways. First, as mentioned above, a person is said to be wasteful if she “spends more money on an item than is necessary”. Second, the other side of waste is to “utilize the item that has been purchased” insufficiently (Arkes, Reference Arkes1996, p. 214). Arkes identified several behaviors driven by waste aversion.

  1. 1. Students who had received an unexpected discount when purchasing their theater subscription ultimately attended fewer plays; “waste” is greater when the play forgone is more expensive (Arkes & Blumer, Reference Arkes and Blumer1985).

  2. 2. Respondents predicted that after buying 2 movie tickets for $5 each, one would be less inclined to pay $5 for a third movie if one had earlier rejected a $12 deal for a 3-pack. Paying $5 for what could have cost $2 feels wasteful (Arkes, Reference Arkes1996, Experiment 1).

  3. 3. Respondents indicated they would be more likely to buy a new upgraded $80 item if their old one could be traded at purchase for a $30 rebate, than if the new item were simply reduced from $80 to $50. The old item seems “wasted” in the sale case, but “put to good use” in the rebate case (Arkes, Reference Arkes1996, Experiment 2).

Waste is contrary to one’s economic self-interest, and oftimes even considered immoral, so trying to avoid it is natural. Arkes showed, moreover, that even “to avoid the appearance of wastefulness [italics ours] people may be motivated to make choices that compromise their own self-interest (1996, p. 213)”. Spending too much hurts the pocket. Appearing to have spent too much hurts the ego. People may willingly overpay in economic currencies to reduce psychological costs. However, losses that are not one’s “own fault” (due, e.g., to theft, accident, or market behavior) are not accompanied by this second-order pain. Thus, people may also prefer to tolerate additional expenditures (of time, effort, pain, discomfort, etc.), if only to avoid the psychological costs of feeling that they wasted their money.

The present study extends waste aversion to scenarios where not only self-interest is violated, but dominance is violated as well — provided that can save one from feeling like a freier. Study 1 establishes the phenomenon, namely that, in order to avoid feeling that money was wasted people prefer an outcome that delivers the same result, but requires greater expenditure of effort, time or discomfort, and is therefore dominated.

Study 2 extends the results by introducing new dependent variables and manipulating the proximity of the protagonist. Study 3 replicates the results with a new population of participants and examines the relations between the preferences for a dominated outcome established in the previous studies and reported feelings of waste and regret.

Table 1: The scenarios of Study 1

Note: Italicized text appeared in one condition, and was missing in the other condition. The original Hebrew questionnaire is available from the authors upon request.

2 Study 1

Two scenarios were created, describing a protagonist who had chosen to pay a fixed amount for the successful completion of some goal over paying according to the actual amount of service needed to reach the goal. in each scenario, we offered two possible outcomes, differing with regard to whether the fixed amount turned out, after the fact, to be less or more expensive than the pay-per-use. the services were van hire for house moving and dental treatment, chosen specifically because both involve some unpleasant investment of time and effort. having to spend more time and effort in order to achieve some desired outcome justifies the prior decision to pay a fixed sum. contrarily, the swift completion of the task might create the feeling of wastefulness, as the protagonist feels like a freier for not having paid according to post-hoc actual use of the service. however, when a cheaper deal was never available, there is no feeling of wastefulness, so that wasting time and effort does not help to alleviate the feeling of wasted money.

2.1 Method

Participants and procedure. 137 students, 37% women, mean age 25. 86 students in 2 classrooms were asked to answer a short questionnaire just before exiting. 51 others were approached individually. Two prizes of 250NIS were promised, to be awarded by lottery.

Design and materials. We showed respondents the two scenarios presented in Table Footnote 1. The manipulated variable within each scenario was whether it did or did not mention a cheaper, albeit rejected, deal, italicized in Table 1. Respondents were assigned at random to a scenario and to an experimental condition.

The compared outcomes were deliberately close, both in terms of difference (consecutive integers, half an hour) and in terms of ratios (e.g., 7.5 hours is only 7% longer than 7 hours). We clearly stated that the goals were fully achieved (the teeth were “sparkling white”, and the mover has “finished the job”). Yet, it was absolutely transparent which choice accomplishes the desired outcome faster. Thus, the longer outcome is dominated by the quicker outcome.

2.2 Results and discussion

Figure 1: Percent of respondents predicting preference for the wasteful outcome in Study 1 (N’s are in parentheses).

Results appear in Figure 1. A 3-way log-linear analysis yields significant results with regard to the main independent variable. Overall, 64.2% of the respondents chose the option that appears less “wasteful” — but involves a higher expenditure of resources! — when a cheaper deal had been rejected (partial χ2(1) = 20.1, p < .001). The two scenarios differed (and why wouldn’t they?), with the Dentist scenario eliciting a significantly higher proportion of preference for the dominated outcome (57.4%) than the Van rental (33.3%) (partial χ2(1) = 8.78, p < .005). Yet, there is no interaction between the two variables (partial χ2(1) =.633, p=.426), and the same conclusion can be drawn based on both scenarios: If only one subscription exists, its cost is just a cost. But a cheaper yet adequate alternative presents a concrete counterfactual (“If only I’d taken it!”), exacerbating waste aversion. It is worth noting that the non-negligible proportion of participants indicating preference for the dominated outcome even when there was no other option available can be explained by the second definition of waste described in the introduction. Namely, the longer outcome represents a more extensive or full utilization of what was purchased.

3 Study 2

In order to test the robustness of the results of Study 1, we administered new questionnaires to a different group of participants. We extended the design in three aspects. First, we introduced two new scenarios. Second, whereas in Study 1 we asked about a stranger, in the new study we manipulated the identity of the protagonist to be either the respondent or a friend. People are sometimes more willing to attribute non-normative behavior and attitudes to others than to themselves (Fisher, Reference Fisher1993), or even exaggerate non-normative behavior when attributed to others (Jo, 2000). On the other hand, when people are asked to predict decisions made by others, they underestimate the effect of emotions on the decision (Faro & Rottenstreich, Reference Faro and Rottenstreich2006, cf. fMRI evidence obtained by Greene et al., Reference Greene, Somerville, Nystrom, Darley and Cohen2001). Therefore, the new scenarios test whether the effect is mitigated or enhanced due to proximity when brought “closer to home”. Finally, we introduced two new dependent variables, asking what the respondent “wishes for”, or what would make the protagonist “happy”, to test whether the effect depends on the specific framing used to elicit preferences. By manipulating the target person and by asking about emotions such as happiness, we are able to learn about the role of emotions in mediating the effect of wasteful feelings. Specifically, if the effect mainly depends on the emotional state, the effect observed for the existence of the previously rejected cheaper option would alter as the other two independent variables change.

3.1 Method

Participants and procedure. 302 Israeli students, 70% women, mean age 30, were recruited informally among our acquaintances. They volunteered a few minutes of their time to answer a short questionnaire. Participants, approached individually, were handed a questionnaire consisting of two questions, one from each scenario, and responded on the spot.

Design and materials. We showed respondents both scenarios presented in Table 2. As in Study 1, each either did or did not mention a cheaper, albeit rejected, deal. Two further manipulations, italicized in Table 2, were used to complete a 2 (whether or not a cheaper subscription was available) -by-2 (whether participants were asked which outcome would make one happier, or which outcome was wished for) -by-2 (whether the preference queried about was one’s own or a friend’s) design.

Table 2: The scenarios of Study 2, with either one deal or two deals offered.

Note: Italicized text was manipulated between conditions. The original Hebrew questionnaire is available from the authors upon request.

3.2 Results and discussion

Table 3 shows the results. A 4-way log-linear analysis tested the four main effects (three manipulated factors + scenario factor), the three 2-way interactions for the manipulated factors, and their 3-way interaction.Footnote 3

Table 3: Percent of respondents, among the total in that cell, choosing the dominated outcome in Study 2.

Respondents were assigned at random to one cell within the first scenario, and to its complementary cell (namely, the one with the complementary value on all three independent variables) in the second. Scenario order was randomized.

As in Study 1, The compared outcomes were deliberately close, while it was made clear that the goals were achieved without compromise (the apartment found was “perfect”, and the body was “hair-free forever”).

The scenario factor was not statistically significant, nor were its interactions with other factors (p-values between .242 and .933). Since the two scenarios yielded such similar results, Figure 2 combines them.

The data fully replicate the results of Study 1. The largest effect is whether a cheaper option had been rejected. Thirty-seven percent of respondents chose the dominated outcome after this rejection, but only 11% otherwise (partial χ2(1) = 58.7, p < .001). Once again, the prior availability of a cheaper deal makes the outcome that is, in fact, less wasteful contribute to the feeling of wastefulness, and therefore less attractive.

Furthermore, the effect is robust to the manipulations of target variable and identity of the protagonist. While the two variables have significant effects on the option chosen by respondents, the interaction with the effect under study here is not significant (partial χ2(1) < 1, p > .400 in all cases).

Figure 2: Percent of respondents choosing the dominated outcome in the different experimental conditions of Study 2.

A significant main effect was found for whether respondents were asked what would make one happier, or what they would wish for. 33% chose the dominated outcome in the former case, but only 15% in the latter (partial χ2(1) = 24.7, p < .001). Possibly, an emotion such as happiness tolerates violation of dominance better than an expressed desideratum. Whereas happiness doesn’t seem to require a normative justification, one feels more accountable, and held to higher standards, regarding what one endorses. However, the lack of significant interaction shows that the effect of the feeling of waste driven by the counterfactual comparison to the rejected option remain unaffected.

Whether the question was about oneself or a friend was also significant (20% chose the dominated outcome for themselves, versus 28% for their friend, partial χ2(1) = 5.39, p < .05). Again, no significant interaction with our primary independent variable was found.

There was a significant interaction between the last two variables (partial χ2(1) = 3.94, p < .05), whereby self versus friend mattered only with regard to predicting happiness, while regarding what one would wish for, responses are similar for oneself and for a friend. Perhaps two intuitions clash here. Inasmuch as participants are aware which choice is rational, social desirability might make them reluctant to openly admit the appeal of the dominated outcome. Asking about a friend could solicit less guarded responses. Indeed, 40% thought their friend would be happier with the dominated outcome, but only 25% admitted they themselves would be happier with it. On the other hand, if asked what they wish for, they might feel a moral obligation to wish “the right thing” for a friend, even if it wouldn’t necessarily make him/her happier — and a dominated outcome is hardly “the right thing”. Indeed, nearly the same proportion wished the dominating outcome for themselves (85%), and for their friend (86%). Thus, we find that our manipulations had a significant effect on choices made by respondents, and at the same time did not influence the effect of feeling of waste, which is our main interest in this study. We conclude that, although emotions do play a role in the type of scenarios that we investigate, the waste aversion manifested in the reduced attractiveness of the dominant outcome does not depend on the elicited emotions.

4 Study 3

Having rejected a cheaper deal makes the more efficient outcome appear to be wasteful and leads to a preference for the dominated outcome. As Arkes (1996) points out, wastefulness may include a component of regret. The dominated outcome triggers counterfactual comparison to “what would have happened had the other option been accepted,” which would have resulted in a better outcome. Conversely, without an alternative option, no counterfactual comparison arises. Thus, waste aversion is closely linked to the well-studied phenomenon of regret aversion (Bell, Reference Bell1982; Loomes & Sugden, Reference Loomes and Sugden1982; Ritov, Reference Ritov1996; Zeelenberg et al., Reference Zeelenberg, Beattie, van der Pligt and de Vries1996; Zeelenberg et al., Reference Zeelenberg and Beattie1997).

Study 3 was conducted to investigate the roles of subjective feelings of waste and regret in the observed effect. We repeated the design of Study 1 using the Van rental scenario, asking participants to estimate the feeling of wastefulness and feeling of regret associated with the more efficient outcome. This measurement serves multiple purposes: First, as a manipulation check, we test that feeling of waste is affected by our manipulation as hypothesized. Second, we test whether the preference for the dominated outcome is correlated with feeling of waste within conditions. Lastly, we look at whether reported feeling of regret mediates feeling of waste and outcome preferences.

4.1 Method

Participants and procedure. Ninety four participants, 52% women, mean age 23 from the participant pool of the Max Planck Institute of Economics in Jena, Germany were recruited by e-mail using ORSEE (Greiner, Reference Greiner, Kremer and Macho2004). Six prizes of 50€ each were promised, to be awarded by lottery.Footnote 2

Design and materials. The experiment was conducted online using LimeSurvey (Schmitz, Reference Schmitz2010). Participants were given the second scenario of Table 2 with the following changes: The Israeli name Amit was changed to Christian. Hourly Van rental prices were 20€ for the first 2 hours and 8€ for each additional hour, or part thereof. Renting the van for a full day cost 65€. The possible outcomes were 7 or 8 hours, respectively. In line with the previous studies, respondents were asked which outcome would be preferred by the protagonist. Next, respondents were presented with the following questions on a separate screen: “If Christian finds that the job required 7 hours, would he feel that he wasted money?” and “If Christian finds that the job required 7 hours, would he regret having hired the van for the full day?” Both questions appeared simultaneously on the same screen, in this order, and responses were given on a 7-points Likert scale.Footnote 3 Respondents were randomly allocated to the two experimental conditions, namely whether a cheaper option was rejected or not.

4.2 Results and discussion

The results of Study 1 were replicated with the German respondents. 72% (33/46) of the subjects chose the wasteful option in the presence of a rejected cheaper deal, compared to 35% (17/48) in the control condition (Fisher’s exact test, p<.001). As hypothesized, having rejected a cheaper option enhanced the “feeling of waste” from 2.98 to 4.00, on average (t(92)=2.95, p<.005). However, the “feeling of regret” did not differ between conditions (3.56 vs. 3.83, t(92)=.73, p=.466), although “waste” and “regret” are significantly correlated over conditions (r(94)=.57, p<.001).

We find that feeling of waste is more important than feeling of regret in inducing preference for the dominated outcome. In fact, regret does not predict outcome preference once feeling of waste is accounted for, as is evident in the logistic regression reported in Table 4. The probability of indicating preference for the dominated outcome increases with the “feeling of waste” that accompanies the more efficient outcome (Wald=6.35, p<.05) and with the existence of the alternative option (Wald=6.92, p<.01), but not the “feeling of regret” (Wald=.01, p=.935).Footnote 4

Table 4: Logistic regression predicting preferred outcome based on “feeling of waste”, “feeling of regret” and condition in Study 3.

R 2=.174 (Hosmer & Lemeshow), .214 (Cox & Snell), .286 (Nagelkerke), Model χ2(1)=22.65.

This supports our earlier interpretation: the dominated outcome sometimes appears more attractive precisely because the alternative appears wasteful. When a previously rejected cheaper option exists, the feeling of waste and therefore the attractiveness of the dominated outcome both increase.

Regret, however, was not found to mediate the effect of feeling of waste on outcome preference in our data, although it indeed appears to be a component of waste, as hypothesized by Arkes (1996).

5 General discussion

This paper adds a new type to “irrational” choices motivated by waste aversion. To avoid the feeling of wasted money (feeling! not real waste), people express willingness to expend extra resources — itself a waste. Specifically, after rejecting a cheaper deal, most respondents saw the appeal of an outcome that voids the regrettable “if only” counterfactual — even if it is wasteful. This paradoxical phenomenon is potentially relevant to customer satisfaction whenever a prix-fixe scheme is offered, and therefore is likely to be prevalent across many products and services.

How, one may ask, can a dominated outcome feel less wasteful? Perhaps because the currency in which people felt wasteful is money, whereas the currency paid to hide it is time and effort. Contrary to the common adage, time is not always like money. For various reasons, it is more ambiguous (Soman, Reference Soman2001), and more flexibly priced (Okada & Hoch, Reference Okada and Hoch2004).

Thaler (1980) suggested that prepaying for a subscription (to a concert series, a gym, or cooking classes) encourages more use than if payment were per use. Thus subscriptions can be a self-control device that people adopt willingly, harnessing waste aversion to their advantage. The present findings cannot be applied similarly. Presumably nobody would actually make one more appointment (with the dentist, say) if they are convinced it is unnecessary (namely that their teeth will get no whiter). While many of our respondents acknowledged the appeal of a dominated outcome, we doubt they would actually choose a wasteful action just to affect it. It is one thing to wish to find oneself in some circumstance, and quite another to bring it about. The latter requires self-deception, in addition to waste aversion, so that the person wrongly believes the wasteful action not to be wasteful (see, e.g., Gur & Sackeim, Reference Gur and Sackeim1979; Mele, Reference Mele1997). People sometimes engage in what observers would call self-deception, but successful self-deception requires that the self not be aware of it (Quattrone & Tversky, Reference Quattrone and Tversky1984).

Our phenomenon is related to the sunk-cost fallacy. The prototypical sunk-cost effect involves a preference for A over B (e.g., driving to a ballgame versus watching it at home on TV) when one had made a non-refundable payment for A, even though circumstances have changed since payment was made (e.g., the weather is foul and traffic is impossible), so that B would have been preferred to A in the absence of the sunk cost (e.g., Thaler, Reference Thaler1980; Arkes & Blumer, Reference Arkes and Blumer1985). Sunk-cost effects are weaker in one sense, and stronger in another, than the present effect.

Sunk-cost effects are weaker inasmuch as A is not dominated by B. In fact, at the time payment was made, A had not only been preferred to B, but even worth paying for. It is the change in circumstance that changed the preference. In our scenarios, on the other hand, one option dominates another unequivocally, and only the prepayment shifts preference to the dominated outcome.

Sunk-cost effects are stronger than the present effect inasmuch as they relate directly to behavior, and therefore can be observed in the real world, such as when public projects whose costs exceed expectation are pursued beyond a point at which they would not have been undertaken had a prior investment not already been made.

In sunk-cost situations, people do not necessarily accept the economic perspective which urges them to ignore sunk costs and look ahead only. In that sense, it seems more like an error of reasoning. In our case, however, it is so transparent that one outcome dominates another that the irrational choice cannot be attributed to error. Hence, people may wish they didn’t have to confront having been freiers, but would just live with it if they were, because self-deceit is nearly impossible. We ourselves were quite surprised that we could so easily lure a majority of respondents into preferring a dominated outcome.

Minimizing waste is economically and morally admirable, and not being a freier is good for the soul. What is remarkable is what people might sometimes prefer to endure rather than face up to occasional waste or the semblance thereof.

Footnotes

*

We thank Moty Amar for assisting with data collection. Financial support from the Max Planck Society is gratefully acknowledged.

This paper originated in a master’s thesis written by Nitsan Guy, who now has no academic affiliation, under the supervision of Maya Bar-Hillel.

1 This analysis necessarily treats each response as independent, thus neglecting the subject identity, which may result in a loss of power. Similar analyses performed separately for the two scenarios provide essentially the same results as the analysis reported here, indicating that the dependency between the two scenarios did not affect the statistical tests.

2 The lottery included 192 additional participants who participated in parallel studies.

3 The original German questionnaire is available from the authors upon request.

4 The significant effect of the condition is not inconsistent with feeling of waste as a mediating variable, since the measurement of feeling of waste is on an arbitrary scale and may be sensitive to the condition.

References

Arkes, H. R., (1996). The psychology of waste. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 9, 213224.3.0.CO;2-1>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arkes, H.R. & Ayton, P. (1999). The sunk cost and Concorde effects: Are humans less rational than lower animals? Psychological Bulletin, 125 591600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arkes, H.R & Blumer, C. (1985). The psychology of sunk cost. Organizational Behavior & Human Decision Processes, 35 124140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arkes, H.R. & Hutzel, L. (1997). Waste heuristics. In Bazerman, M. , Messick, D. , Tenbrunsel, A. , and Wade-Benzoni, K. (Eds.), Environment, Ethics, and Behavior: The Psychology of Environmental Valuation and Degradation (pp. 154168). San Francisco, CA: New Lexington Press.Google Scholar
Bell, D. E. (1982). Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research, 30 961981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faro, D. & Rottenstreich, Y. (2006). Affect, empathy, and regressive mispredictions of others’ preferences under risk’. Management Science, Vol. 52 529541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R. J. (1993). Social desirability bias and the validity of indirect questioning. Journal of Consumer Research, 20 303315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J.D., Somerville, R.B., Nystrom, L.E., Darley, J.M.& Cohen, J.D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral Judgment. Science, 293 21052108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greiner, B. (2004). An online recruitment system for economic experiments. In Kremer, K. and Macho, V. (Eds.), Forschung und wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. GWDG Bericht 63 (pp. 7993). Göttingen: Ges. für Wiss. Datenverarbeitung.Google Scholar
Gur, R. C. & Sackeim, H. A. (1979). Self-deception: A concept in search of a phenomenon. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37 147169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jo, M. S. (1999). Controlling social-desirability bias via method factors of direct and indirect questioning in structural equation models. Psychology and Marketing, 17 137148.3.0.CO;2-V>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G. & Sugden, R. (1982). Regret theory: An Alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. The Economic Journal, 92 805824.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, A.R. (1997) Real self-deception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20 91136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okada, E. M. & Hoch, S. J. (2004). Spending time versus spending money. Journal of Consumer Research, 31 313323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quattrone, G. A. & Tversky, A. (1984). Causal Versus Diagnostic Contingencies: On Self-Deception and on the Voter’s Illusion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46 237248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritov, I. (1996). Probability of regret: Anticipation of uncertainty resolution in choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 66 228236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmitz, C. (2010). Limesurvey [computer software]. http://www.limesurvey.org.Google Scholar
Soman, D. (2001). The mental accounting of sunk time costs: Why time is not like money. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 14 169185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1 3960CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H. (1999). Mental accounting matters. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12 183206.3.0.CO;2-F>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeelenberg, M. & Beattie, J. (MTk5Nw). Consequences of regret aversion 2: Additional evidence for effects of feedback on decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 72 6378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeelenberg, M., Beattie, J., van der Pligt, J. & de Vries, N. K. (1996). Consequences of regret aversion: effects of expected feedback on risky decision-making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 65 148158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: The scenarios of Study 1

Figure 1

Figure 1: Percent of respondents predicting preference for the wasteful outcome in Study 1 (N’s are in parentheses).

Figure 2

Table 2: The scenarios of Study 2, with either one deal or two deals offered.

Figure 3

Table 3: Percent of respondents, among the total in that cell, choosing the dominated outcome in Study 2.

Figure 4

Figure 2: Percent of respondents choosing the dominated outcome in the different experimental conditions of Study 2.

Figure 5

Table 4: Logistic regression predicting preferred outcome based on “feeling of waste”, “feeling of regret” and condition in Study 3.