Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
Hostname: page-component-59b7f5684b-j5sqr Total loading time: 0.469 Render date: 2022-09-26T10:16:53.621Z Has data issue: true Feature Flags: { "shouldUseShareProductTool": true, "shouldUseHypothesis": true, "isUnsiloEnabled": true, "useRatesEcommerce": false, "displayNetworkTab": true, "displayNetworkMapGraph": false, "useSa": true } hasContentIssue true

Article contents

Respecting Persons, Respecting Preferences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2007

MIKHAIL VALDMAN*
Affiliation:
Virginia Commonwealth Universitymvaldman@vcu.edu

Abstract

In this article, I argue that the state has a prima facie obligation to help its citizens satisfy their autonomous preferences. I argue that this obligation is grounded in the state's obligation to respect its citizens as persons, and that part of what is involved in respecting someone as a person is helping her satisfy her autonomous preferences. I argue that that which makes preferences autonomous is also that which makes them, and not their non-autonomous counterparts, worthy of respect. In addition, I reject other views of what makes preferences worthy of respect, in particular Ronald Dworkin's view that only preferences for one's own enjoyment of some goods or opportunities deserve political consideration. Finally, I consider the state's obligation towards immoral autonomous preferences, and I argue that the state's prima facie obligation to promote the satisfaction of autonomous preferences is quite strong.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See, for instance, Dworkin, Ronald, ‘Liberalism’, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, 1985).

Google Scholar

2 See, for instance, Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, 1971).

Google Scholar

3 Robert Goodin makes a similar point. See Goodin, Robert, ‘The Political Theories of Choice and Dignity’, American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981), pp. 91100.

Google Scholar

4 Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork for a Metaphysic of Morals (Cambridge, 1998).

CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Hill, Thomas, ‘Humanity as an End in Itself’, Ethics 91.1 (1980), p. 97.

Google Scholar

6 Goodin, ‘Choice and Dignity’, p. 95; emphasis in original.

7 I leave it open whether everyone, and not just the state, has an obligation to respect a person's preferences. While I think that we all have a moral reason to respect each other as persons, and that we therefore have a moral reason to respect each other's autonomous preferences, these reasons do not straightforwardly generate moral obligations. I assume, however, that the state has an obligation to respect its citizens as persons and not just a moral reason to do so. My aim in this article is to show that this obligation creates a further obligation to respect people's autonomous preferences. If, however, all moral reasons entail moral obligations, or if all of us have an obligation and not just a moral reason to respect each other as persons, then my conclusion would apply to all persons and not just to states. For more on the connection between moral reasons and moral obligations, see Shelley Kagan, ‘Defending Options’, Ethics 104 (1994), pp. 333–51. Kagan argues that if there is a moral reason to do X, and it is not outweighed by other moral reasons, then doing X is morally required.

8 While it is doubtful that a preference could be constitutive of one's personal identity on bodily continuity views, it seems that it could be on psychological continuity views. If that which makes you the same person that you were five minutes ago is a matter of psychological continuity, then an especially deep preference could be constitutive of your personal identity. For a defense of the bodily continuity view see, for instance, Van Inwagen, Peter, Material Beings (Ithaca, 1990). For more on the psychological continuity view see, for instance, Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford, 1984). For the sake of the discussion I will assume that preferences can be constitutive of one's personal identity, but I will show that this is irrelevant for determining which preferences are worthy of respect. If, however, preferences cannot be constitutive of one's personal identity, then an important competitor to my view is eliminated.

9 Modern conceptions have parted ways with the related though distinct notion of moral autonomy developed primarily by Kant. On the former, being autonomous essentially amounts to living according to one's freely chosen conception of a worthwhile life. The Kantian conception, on the other hand, is essentially a view about the nature of morality.

10 Many who write on autonomy accept some version of the capacity view. See, for instance, Richards, David, ‘Rights and Autonomy’, Ethics 92 (1981), pp. 320; Dworkin, Gerald, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (New York, 1988); Frankfurt, Harry, ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), pp. 829–39.

11 I describe these capacities as ‘latent’ because this view's proponents consider the mere possession of these capacities as sufficient for autonomy whether or not they are ever exercised.

12 Virtually everyone writing on autonomy appeals to some such metaphorical description. Among those who use the ‘author of your life’ metaphor are Joseph Raz, Thomas Nagel, Richard Lindley, and, to some extent Joel Feinberg. Among those who use the idea of being self-governing are Gerald Dworkin, Harry Frankfurt, Robert Young, and Lawrence Haworth. See Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (New York, 1986); Nagel, Thomas, The View From Nowhere (New York, 1986), p. 114; Lindley, R., Autonomy (London, 1986); Feinberg, Joel, Harm to Self (New York, 1986); Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy; Frankfurt, ‘Freedom of the Will’; Young, R., Personal Autonomy: Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty (New York, 1986); Haworth, Lawrence, Autonomy: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology and Ethics (New Haven, 1986).

13 See, for example, Christman, John, ‘Autonomy and Personal History’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy (1991), pp. 124; Elster, Jon, Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality (New York, 1983).

14 Harry Frankfurt, Laura Ekstrom, and Gerald Dworkin are among those who hold structural theories. See Frankfurt, ‘Freedom of the Will’; Ekstrom, Laura, ‘A Coherence Theory of Autonomy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1993), pp. 599616; Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy.

CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Recently, George Sher and Sigurdur Kristinsson have proposed substantive theories of autonomy where a necessary condition of being autonomous is being responsive to reasons. See Kristinsson, Sigurdur, ‘The Limits of Neutrality: Toward a Weakly Substantive Account of Autonomy’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30.2 (2000), p. 257. George Sher, ‘Liberal Neutrality and the Value of Autonomy’, Social Philosophy and Policy (1995), pp. 136–59.

CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 Indeed, I think these views are more plausibly understood as accounts of autonomous preferences than of autonomous persons. To see this, note that, in their current form, none of the achievement conceptions can account for the non-autonomy of the prisoner who is involuntarily chained to a dungeon wall. After all, he can have motivations that developed in the right way, that presently cohere with other elements of his character and values, and he can be fully responsive to reasons. Thus, as accounts of autonomous persons, these views are incompatible with paradigm cases of non-autonomy. As accounts of autonomous preferences, however, they each have some merit.

17 Clearly, this preference violates the historical condition. In addition, we can suppose that it does not resonate with other elements of Jim's character, and that Jim has no powerful reasons for preferring detective fiction to biographies. To be sure, one might ask whether Jim's desire to read detective fiction provides him with a reason to do so. Perhaps it does, but on the reason-oriented view, desires cannot straightforwardly give rise to autonomy-conferring reasons because otherwise all desire-based actions would be autonomous.

18 This preference is a good candidate for autonomy on all three views. Nothing in its history suggests a ‘wrong’ origin, it seems to cohere with other elements of her character and values, and we can assume that Mary has good reasons for choosing this career.

19 I selected a preference for detective fiction and for painting because neither seems to have intrinsic worth or, for that matter, any moral dimension at all. If, however, the reader thinks there is something intrinsically good about painting and not about reading detective fiction that may distort our judgment, she can substitute a more neutral preference for it, or just assume that Mary and Jim have the same preference though they acquired it differently. This shouldn't affect the intuition.

20 It is unclear whether mere preference satisfaction is a component of well-being. It is not on mental state theories of well-being, but it may be on desire-satisfaction theories and objective list theories. In any case, nothing here hinges on this question. At this stage, I am merely attempting to generate intuitions that the state has a reason to promote the satisfaction of autonomous preferences. As will become clear, I do not think that the state's obligation to help persons satisfy their autonomous preferences is grounded in considerations of well-being. Note, however, that my position is incompatible with the view that mere preference satisfaction is not an element of well-being and that only considerations of well-being provide reasons for state action.

21 Here I am denying what some refer to as the Slogan, or the idea that one situation cannot be better (or worse) than another if there is no one for whom it is better (or worse). I am claiming that one world can be better than another even if it is not better for anyone in that world. For a defense of the Slogan, see, for example, Broome, John, Weighing Goods (Cambridge, 1991); Doran, Brett, ‘Reconsidering the Levelling-Down Objection against Egalitarianism’, Utilitas, 13.1 (2001), pp. 6585. I, however, find the arguments for rejecting the Slogan entirely persuasive. For this, see Temkin, Larry, ‘Harmful Goods, Harmless Bads’, Value, Welfare, and Morality, ed. Frey, R. G. and Morris, C. (Cambridge 1993), pp. 290324. See also Crisp, Roger, ‘Equality, Priority, and Compassion’, Ethics 113 (2003), pp. 745–63.

22 See, for example, Barkow, Jerome, Cosmides, Leda, and Tooby, John, The Adapted Mind (New York, 1992); Pinker, Stephen, How the Mind Works (New York, 1997).

23 The analogy between object and preference ownership is not perfect. In order to be a preference's owner, you must make it your own. Objects, however, can become yours accidentally, such as when you are bequeathed a large sum of money by an unknown relative.

24 To be sure, these kinds of preferences are not necessarily non-autonomous because it is possible to exercise some control over them.

25 Perhaps one could autonomously choose such a life, but this choice cannot be passive in the above sense.

26 This case was suggested to me by Larry Temkin.

27 While I do not offer an account of the distinction between positive and negative duties, on any reasonable account a duty to help someone satisfy their autonomous preferences must be classified as a positive one.

28 See, for example, Dworkin, Ronald, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, 1985); Larmore, Charles, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge, 1987), pp. 5966; Rawls, John, ‘The Priority of Right and the Ideas of the Good’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (1988), pp. 251–76; Mason, Andrew, ‘Autonomy, Liberalism, and State Neutrality’, The Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 433–52. While my arguments call this view into question, they are not necessarily incompatible with it because I focus on preferences in general rather than on conceptions of the good life.

29 Dworkin, Ronald, ‘Reverse Discrimination’, Taking Rights Seriously (London, 1977).

Google Scholar

30 Dworkin, ‘Reverse Discrimination’, p. 233.

31 Dworkin, ‘Reverse Discrimination’, p. 234.

32 Dworkin, ‘Reverse Discrimination’, p. 235; emphasis added.

33 Dworkin backs away from this argument in his response to Herbert Hart. I consider this momentarily.

34 Here we must assume that having certain local political preferences facilitates the satisfaction of your national political preferences, and vice versa. They have to be mutually reinforcing.

35 Here I am assuming that there is more to welfare than mere preference satisfaction.

36 Dworkin, Ronald, ‘Rights as Trumps’, Theories of Rights, ed. Waldron, J. (Oxford, 1984). See also Hart, Herbert, ‘Between Utility and Rights’, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford, 1983).

37 The other argument concerns whether a utilitarian can be neutral between the truth of his own theory and that of competing non-egalitarian theories such as the theory that certain people's preferences should be weighed more heavily than others. Though interesting, this is not immediately relevant for my purposes.

38 Dworkin, ‘Rights as Trumps’, p. 366; emphasis added.

39 See Raz, The Morality of Freedom, p. 380.

40 Equality may be an important distributive ideal even if it is not important in every context. See, for instance, Temkin, Larry, ‘Egalitarianism Defended’, Ethics 113 (2003), pp. 764–82.

CrossRefGoogle Scholar

41 See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 126–30.

42 See Raz, The Morality of Freedom, ch. 14.

43 I would like to thank Jim Griffin, Ruth Chang, Doug Husak, Howard McGary, Anthony Ellis, and especially Larry Temkin for their extremely helpful comments on earlier versions of this article.

Save article to Kindle

To save this article to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Respecting Persons, Respecting Preferences
Available formats
×

Save article to Dropbox

To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Respecting Persons, Respecting Preferences
Available formats
×

Save article to Google Drive

To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Respecting Persons, Respecting Preferences
Available formats
×
×

Reply to: Submit a response

Please enter your response.

Your details

Please enter a valid email address.

Conflicting interests

Do you have any conflicting interests? *