Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-27gpq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T01:54:08.242Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nietzsche's Virtues: A Personal Inquiry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

Give style to your character, a great and rare art.

Nietzsche Gay Science (290)

What are we to make of Nietzsche? There has been an explosion of scholarship over the past twenty years, much of it revealing and insightful, a good deal of it controversial if not polemical. The controversy and polemics are for the most part straight from Nietzsche, of course, and the scholarly disputes over what he ‘really’ meant are rather innocuous and often academic compared with what Nietzsche meant (or might have meant) with his conscientiously inflammatory rhetoric and hyperbole. We have been treated to extended debates about Nietzsche's politics, his attacks on Christianity and morality, his famed notion of the übermensch and his less lampooned (but more edifying) doctrine of the ‘eternal recurrence’. We have recently heard Nietzsche reinterpreted as an analytic philosopher, as a deconstructionist, as a feminist, even as a closet Christian and a liberal. Stephen Aschheim suggests in his recent book that Nietzsche provides us with something like a Rorschach test, inviting readers with amazingly different commitments and ideologies to ‘make their own Nietzsche’ (as a Times Literary Supplement review bluntly put it). But there is another approach to Nietzsche, something quite different from interpreting him in terms of his various ‘theses’ and positions, unpacking his ‘system’ or repeating unhelpfully that he displayed no such coherence and consistency, something more than finding out ‘who’ Nietzsche is as opposed to what we have made out of him. The simplest way of getting at this alternative approach might be to ask, what Nietzsche would make of us? I grant that this is a bit cryptic, and it invites a variety of unflattering answers. But I think it is very much in the spirit of what he (and his spokesman Zarathustra) are all about. It is an intimately personal approach to Nietzsche, an approach that will, no doubt, be somewhat different for each and every one of us. But that, too, of course, is just what Nietzsche (and Zarathustra) would have demanded.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Aschheim, Stephen, The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany, 1890–1990 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992).Google Scholar

2 See, for example, Williams, Bernard review and critique of Martha Nussbaum's Therapy of Desire, her analysis and praise of the Stoics precisely in terms of their providing such ‘moral advice’.Google Scholar

3 Collected and printed in The Will to Power, trans, and ed., Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Random House, 1969). The status of Nietzsche's unpublished notes (Nachlass) has been exhaustively debated and no doubt commented upon by virtually every commentator on Nietzsche. The best policy, it seems to me, is to trust Nietzsche's notes only when they are confirmed by (and thus reiterate, occasionally in more striking language) Nietzsche's published statements. In the case of external recurrence as a physical hypothesis, no such statements exist are to be found.Google Scholar

4 For example, the Magnus book already mentioned, Nietzsche's Existential Imperative (Indiana University Press, 1978)Google ScholarNehamas, Alexander, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985)Google Scholar, Higgins, Kathleen M., Nietzsche's Zarathustra (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987)Google Scholar, Young, Julian, Nietzsche's Theory of Art (Cambridge University Press, 1992)Google Scholar,Clark, Maudemarie, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 1990).Google Scholar

5 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans by Hollingdale, R. J. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973), IV §10.Google Scholar

6 Magnus, Stewart and Miller, , Nietzsche's Case (New York: Routledge, 1995) with reference to Maudemarie Clark's (excellent) discussion of a similar thesis.Google Scholar

7 As has often been noted, the phrase conies from Pindar.

8 Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human, trans by Hollingdale, R. J. (Cambridge University Press, 1986), §301.Google Scholar

9 Zarathustra, Nietzsche II ‘On the Virtuous’.Google Scholar

10 Oliver, Kelly, Womanizing Nietzsche (New York: Routledge, 1995).Google Scholar

11 This is certainly true of Jacques Derrida, who recently has emerged from his own web of obscurantism to make it amply clear that deconstruction as he practices it is rich with ‘political’ implications (see, e.g., his recent The Specter of Marx (New York: Routledge, 1994)Google Scholar and Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty (introduction to her translation of Jacques Derrida's Of Grammatology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976)Google Scholar, who has always made her political commitments (if not her prose) quite explicit.

12 Not that the topic itself is thin. See Nehamas on Nietzsche and Socrates in The Art of Living (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998).Google Scholar

13 The phrase is a title briefly considered by Nietzsche for his last several works, but he wisely rejected it, I presume because even he found it too pretentious.Google Scholar

14 The interpretation of Nietzsche's philosophy as an ethics of virtue has been prosecuted at length by Lester Hunt in his Nietzsche and the Origins of Virtue (Routledge, 1991)Google Scholar. I first defended this interpretation in ‘A More evere Morality: Nietzsche's Affirmative Ethics’ in Nietzsche as affirmative thinker: papers presented at the Fifth Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter, ed. Yovel, Y., 1983 (Dordrecht:M. Nijhoff, 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, reprinted in From Hegel to Existentialism (New York: Oxford, 1988).Google Scholar

15 Miller, William has suggested that disgust is the most basic moral emotion. See his The Anatomy of Disgust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996).Google Scholar

16 E.g. Arthur Kroker to take one example of many, in The Postmodern Scene: Excremental Culture and Hyper-aesthetics (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1986).Google Scholar

17 Kant has been turned into an ‘agent-based’ virtue ethicist, for example, by Darwall, Steve (see his The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’ 1640–1740 (Cambridge University Press, 1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Mill, John Stuart betrays his Aristotelian secrets in chapter V of Utilitarianism (Indiannapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1979).Google Scholar

18 I owe this insight into the nature of early Greek morality to Julius Moravscik.

19 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Antichrist in The Portable Nietzsche, trans and ed. by Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Viking, 1954), §11.Google Scholar

20 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Twilight of the Idols in The Portable Nietzsche, trans and ed. by kaufmann, Walter (New York: Viking, 1954)Google Scholar, ‘The Problem of Socrates’, §3.

21 Nietzsche, , TwilightGermans’, §2.Google Scholar

22 Nietzsche, Friedrich, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans by Kaufmann, Walter and Hollingdale, R. J. (New York: Vintage, 1967), Book I, §10.Google Scholar

23 Sluga, Hans, Heidegger's Crisis (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994).Google Scholar

24 Again, the opposite of vice is not a virtue. Gossiping is a vice. Not gossiping is not a virtue. Indeed, one might argue, it is itself another type of vice.Google Scholar

25 Monk, Ray, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (New York: Free Press, 1990).Google Scholar

26 No one is more pithy on this point than Nehamas, who works out the Nietzsche-Socrates connection in great detail.Google Scholar

27 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Beyond Good and Evil, trans by Kaufmann, Walter. (New York: Vintage, 1966).Google Scholar

28 Gregory Vlastos would certainly disagree. But for a brilliant semi-scholarlys reply see Stone's, I. F.Trial of Socrates. (Boston: Little, Brown, 1988).Google Scholar

29 Maclntyre, Alasdair, in Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988)Google Scholar is far from praising of his Scots countryman.

30 Heine's account of a clockwork Kant, for instance, may make the man charming but hardly a hero. (Religion and Philosophy in Germany, trans by Snodgrass, John.) (Boston: Beacon Press, 1959).Google Scholar

31 One does not have to believe Bertrand Russell here, but Schopenhauer's grumpy hedonism is indeed at odds with the pessimism of his philosophy. Nietzsche is much more insightful than Russell on this matter, needless to say. Whereas Russell simply dismissed Schopenhauer, Nietzsche had once idolised him. Accordingly, Nietzsche is also, at times, more scathing.Google Scholar

32 But see, for a more subtle account, Hans Sluga's admirable Heidegger's Crisis (op. cit.).Google Scholar

33 The Monk book makes perfectly clear the unenviable sense in which Wittgenstein was an exemplar of his philosophy, aphilosophy of tortured selfdoubts (rather than the mere gestures which are taken up by his students).Google Scholar

34 Russell, , My Autobiography (Boston: Little Brown, 1967–1969).Google Scholar

35 Sartre, , Les mots (The Words). Translated by Bernard Frechtman (Greenwich, CT: Fawcett, 1966).Google Scholar

36 Quine, W. V. O., The Time of My Life: An Autobiography (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985).Google Scholar

37 Scharfstein, Ben-Ami, The Philosophers: Their Lives and the Nature of Their Thought (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980).Google Scholar

38 Here is an example of a typical anti-Nietzsche ad hominem argument, from a logic textbook, no less: ‘Don't waste your time studying the philosophy of Nietzsche. Not only was he an atheist but he ended his days in an insane asylum’. (Halverson, William H.A Concise Introduction to Philosophy (New York: Random House, 1967) p. 58.Google Scholar

39 Dionysus, as Nietzsche well knew, was also considered the great seducer (e.g. Euripides Bacchus).

40 Cf. the Marie von Bradke quote at the beginning of this section, ‘his pathologically delicate soul, overflowing with pity’, (op. cit.).

41 Nehamas, Alexander, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985).Google Scholar

42 See my comment on Nehamas, ‘Nietzsche and Nehamas's Nietzsche’, International Studies in Philosophy (Nietzsche issue) Vol. xxi, no. 2 (Summer, 1989).Google Scholar

43 Danto, , Nietzsche as Philosopher (New York: Macmillan, 1963)Google Scholar. I do not mean to deny for a moment of course, that Danto's book was one of the most important events in recent Nietzsche scholarship. Following Walter Kaufmann's equally important de-Nazification of Nietzsche a few years earlier, Danto captured Nietzsche's ideas in a form that made Nietzsche ‘respectable’ in the then overwhelmingly analytic world of American professional philosophy. His recognition of the limits of this approach can be found in several places, among them his presidential address to the American Philosophical Association in 1983 (‘Philosophy as/and/of Literature’, reprinted in The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art New York: Columbia University Press, 1986)Google Scholar and in his essay ‘Some Remarks on the Genealogy of Morals’ in Higgins and Solomon, Reading Nietzsche (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988).Google Scholar

44 It is the demand for integration of philosopher and philosophy that distinguishes philosophy from most other disciplines, and it is what makes it so odd when we meet ‘philosophers’ (almost always philosophy professors) who keep their philosophical interests wholly compartmentalised and isolated from the rest of their lives - no matter how exciting or boring, no matter how admirable or loathsome. This is also what drives the ‘Heidegger crisis’. (See Sluga, op. cit.).

45 Here I backtrack from my objection to Nehamas's reconstruction of Nietzsche as ‘Nietzsche’ in his Nietzsche: Life as Literature and my ‘Nietzsche and Nehamas's Nietzsche’, {op. cit.) The issue now seems to me much more complicated.Google Scholar

46 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality. Translated by Hollingdale, R. J. (Cambridge University Press, 1982), §556Google Scholar, Nietzsche, , Beyond Good and Evil §284.Google Scholar

47 Slote, Michael, From Morality to Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).Google Scholar

48 Swanton, Christine ‘Profiles of the Virtues’ (unpublished paper).Google Scholar

49 Maclntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (Notre Dame University Press, 1981).Google Scholar

50 Nussbaum, Martha et al. , ‘Non-Relative Virtue’ in French, Ethics and Character: Midwest Studies XIII (Notre Dame University Press, 1988).Google Scholar

51 But cf. Nietzsche, , Daybreak §277 on the ‘hot and cold virtues’.Google Scholar

52 Homer, , The Iliad, xv. 348512Google Scholar, Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics Trans. Ross, W. D. (London: Oxford University Press, 1925)Google Scholar, Book III, Ch. 8 (1116). Ross points out that the quotation more likely resembles Agamemnon than Hector (op. cit. p. 68), but cf. Aristotle (Ibid. 1117) where he considers: ‘passion is sometimes reckoned as courage… for passion above all things is eager to rush on danger… Hence Homer's “put strength into his passion”’. Aristotle goes on to say that men who act from passion are not truly brave but more akin to beasts. They do not act ‘for honor's sake nor as the rule directs’, (Ibid.) Nevertheless, he adds, ‘they have something akin to courage’.

53 Tanner, Michael, Nietzsche (Oxford University Press, 1994).Google Scholar

54 cf Nozick, Robert on people with an ‘aura’ (emphatically not the New Age sense) in his Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981).Google Scholar

55 Quoted in Mistry, Freny, Nietzsche and Buddhism (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1981), p. 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

56 As in Ayn Rand's derivative ‘virtue of selfishness’ (in The Virtue of Selfishness, New York: American Library, 1964).

57 This piece will appear in slightly different form in a book edited by Richard Schacht, also for Cambridge University Press, of essays on Nietzsche for Nietzsche's 150th birthday.