Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T08:44:15.526Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rationality and Religious Belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Louis P. Pojman
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Indiana

Extract

In debate on faith and reason two opposing positions have dominated the field. The first position asserts that faith and reason are commensurable and the second position denies that assertion. Those holding to the first position differ among themselves as to the extent of the compatibility between faith and reason, most adherents relegating the compatibility to the ‘preambles of faith’ (e.g. the existence of God and his nature) over against the ‘articles of faith’ (e.g. the doctrine of the incarnation). Few have maintained complete harmony between reason and faith, i.e. a religious belief within the realm of reason alone. The second position divides into two sub-positions: (1) that which asserts that faith is opposed to reason (which includes such unlikely bedfellows as Hume and Kierkegaard), placing faith in the area of irrationality; and (2) that which asserts that faith is higher than reason, is transrational. Calvin and Barth assert that a natural theology is inappropriate because it seeks to meet unbelief on its own ground (ordinary human reason). Revelation, however, is ‘self-authenticating’, ‘carrying with it its own evidence’.1 We may call this position the ‘transrationalist’ view of faith. Faith is not so much against reason as above it and beyond its proper domain. Actually, Kierkegaard shows that the two sub-positions are compatible. He holds both that faith is above reason (superior to it) and against reason (because reason has been affected by sin). The irrationalist and transrationalist positions are sometimes hard to separate in the incommensurabilist's arguments. At least, it seems that faith gets such a high value that reason comes off looking not simply inadequate but culpable. To use reason where faith claims the field is not only inappropriate but irreverent or faithless.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1979

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 159 note 1 Calvin, , Institutes, Book 1, ch. 7.Google Scholar

page 160 note 1 Clifford, W. K., ‘The Ethics of Belief’.Google Scholar

page 160 note 2 Hard-perspectivists include Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein, Winch, Barth, Bultmann as well as Reinhold Niebuhr. Soft-perspectivists include Mitchell, Swinburne and John King-Farlow, all of whom have influenced my views. This position has an analogue in philosophy of science, where philosophers such as Sellers and Hesse recognize that all science emerges within conceptual frame-works but that there is still the possibility of communication between frameworks.

page 161 note 1 I follow McClendon, and Smith's, definition of a conviction here as ‘a persistent belief such that if X has a conviction it will not easily be relinquished without making X a significantly different person than before’. Understanding Religous Convictions (Notre Dame, 1975), p. 7.Google Scholar

page 161 note 2 McClendon, Even and make, Smith this mistake in their usually reliable work, op. cit. p. 108.Google Scholar

page 165 note 1 Cf. Mitchell, Basil, ‘Faith and Reason: a False Antithesis?’, an unpublished manuscriptGoogle Scholar; Lakotos, I., ‘Falsification and Methodology of Scientific Research Programs’ in Criticism and the Groztth of Knowledge, ed. Lakatos, and Musgrave, (Cambridge, 1970), pp. 91196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 166 note 1 Mitchell, , op. cit.Google Scholar

page 166 note 2 Lakatos, , op. cit. p. 118.Google Scholar

page 168 note 1 Norman Malcolm, ‘The Groundlessness of Belief’, an address delivered at Lancaster University, England, under the Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series, September 1976.

page 168 note 2 Ibid.

page 172 note 1 Quoted inMacquarrie, John, Twentieth Century Religious Thought, p. 334.Google Scholar