Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T14:50:58.720Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A revitalized biopsychosocial model: core theory, research paradigms, and clinical implications

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 September 2023

Derek Bolton*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Institute of Psychiatry, Psychology and Neuroscience, King's College London, London, UK
*
Corresponding author: Derek Bolton Email: derek.bolton@kcl.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The biopsychosocial model (BPSM) was proposed by George Engel in 1977 as an improvement to the biomedical model (BMM), to take account of psychological and social as well as biological factors relevant to health and disease. Since then the BPSM has had a mixed reputation, as the overarching framework for psychiatry, perhaps for medicine generally, while also being criticized for being theoretically and empirically vacuous. Over the past few decades, substantial evidence has accumulated supporting the BPSM but its theory remains less clear. The first part of this paper reviews recent well-known, general theories in the relevant sciences that can provide a theoretical framework of the model, constituting a revitalized BPSM capable of theorizing causal interactions within and between biological, psychological, and social domains. Fundamental concepts in this new framework include causation as regulation and dysfunction as dysregulation. Associated research paradigms are outlined in Part 2. Research in psychological therapies and social epidemiology are major examples of programs that have produced results anomalous for the BMM and consistent with the BPSM. Theorized models of causal mechanisms enrich empirical data and two biopsychosocial examples are models of chronic stress and pain perception. Clinical implications are reviewed in Part 3. The BPSM accommodates psychological and social as well as biological treatment effects evident in the clinical trials literature. Personal, interpersonal, and institutional aspects of clinical care are out of the scope of the BMM, assigned to the art of healthcare rather than the science, but can be accommodated and theorized in the BPSM.

Type
Review Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction: the problem area and a proposal

The biopsychosocial model (BPSM) was proposed by George Engel in 1977 as an improvement to the biomedical model (BMM), necessary to account for psychological and social factors in health and disease as well as biological (Engel, Reference Engel1977). This proposal remains critical in science and in service planning (Wade & Halligan, Reference Wade and Halligan2017). However, the BPSM has a mixed reputation: it has been regarded as the overarching, dominant framework for psychiatry, perhaps for medicine generally, while on the other hand, and often at the same time, it has been roundly criticized for being scientifically, theoretically vacuous (Ghaemi, Reference Ghaemi2009; McManus, Reference McManus2005). This is the problem area to be addressed in this paper: what is the science of the BPSM?

At the level of the empirical data, there is reason to think now that this supports the broad BPSM. Over the past few decades, substantial evidence has accumulated that psychosocial as well as biological factors are implicated in the etiology and course of a wide range of health conditions, supporting the BPSM, reviewed, for example, in Novack et al. (Reference Novack, Cameron, Epel, Ader, Waldstein, Levenstein and Wainer2007), Bolton and Gillett (Reference Bolton and Gillett2019), and in a recent edited volume on biopsychosocial psychiatry (Savulescu, Roache, Davies, & Loebel, Reference Savulescu, Roache, Davies and Loebel2020). There remains, however, the problem of theory, identified by authoritative critics as cited above: the BPSM seems to have no clear scientific theoretical content. Put another way, the criticisms of the BPSM are typically not reviews of the evidence base, but are doubts about whether the ‘model’ really has anything to say – any content.

Drawing on previous work (Bolton & Gillett, Reference Bolton and Gillett2019), I will present a case that Engel's main idea – that a BPSM was required to replace the BMM – was visionary but programmatic. It was visionary in anticipating radical changes in the ways that health and disease were becoming theorized and researched, but programmatic because the radical changes were in their early stages, still in progress and not yet widely implemented. However, I suggest, the position has changed by now, and theories that can underpin a broader BPSM are well-known and can be drawn upon to revitalize the model.

To explain the background and the proposal further, Engel's Reference Engel1977 paper implicates two foundational underpinnings of the BMM, the model for biomedicine as conceived at that time: one is that biology, as physiology, is reducible to physics and chemistry, and the other is the assumption of mind/body dualism (Engel, Reference Engel1977, p. 379). Dualism notoriously offers no scientific account of how immaterial mental processes can causally influence the material body, and, with this assumption, there is no role for psychological causes in the scientific explanation of behavior unless they are somehow reducible to biological causes. Engel implies that these two foundational underpinnings of the BMM will be abandoned. As to what the replacements are and how they work in a new BPSM, Engel refers to von Bertallanfy's then relatively new General System Theory (Engel, Reference Engel1977, pp. 391–392; Von Bertalanffy, Reference Von Bertalanffy1968), but there is no detailed account. However, there were paradigm shifts underway in the biological and psychological sciences at around that time, the emergence of information-based models in biology and the so-called cognitive revolution in psychology, which subsequently have become mainstream science. I will present a case that these new paradigms changed the reductionist assumptions that Engel attributed to the BMM, paving the way for theoretical content for the BPSM.

A defining feature of the BPSM is its interdisciplinarity. High levels of interdisciplinarity require a unified theoretical perspective and integration around shared themes and questions (Boden, Reference Boden and Cunningham1999; Committee on Facilitating Interdisciplinary Research, 2004; Strijbos, Reference Strijbos, Frodeman and Mitcham2010). For the BPSM, shared themes and questions are straightforwardly specifiable about the causes and cures of illness. The substantial task for the BPSM is to explicate a unified theoretical perspective and integration across the three relevant sciences. It turns out, I will propose in what follows, that the required shared theoretical perspectives is systems theoretic, as Engel anticipated, in which concepts such as regulation and control, information and communication, function and dysfunction, play critical roles across the whole biopsychosocial domain.

To make the case for the proposal that the BPSM can be revitalized in terms of current scientific theory I will review, in Part 1, well-known general theories in the three relevant sciences, associated with many research groups, which can provide theoretical content to the model. None of these well-known general theories are, I believe, currently controversial; their competitors are not so much in the current science but in the paradigms being replaced, particularly versions of biological reductionism. In this sense, the revitalized version of the BPSM outlined here is, I suggest, a plausible representation of an overarching model currently in the health sciences. Research paradigms and examples of research programs that implicate the broad range of biopsychosocial factors and which are consistent with the BPSM (regardless whether or not they explicitly invoke the model), are considered in Part 2, and clinical implications will be considered in Part 3.

BPSM core theory

The new biology

Engel supposed that the BMM supposed biology was or was reducible to physics and chemistry (Engel, Reference Engel1977). This reductionist supposition was pretty much orthodoxy at that time, but is now history. Biology (as physiology) has transformed itself in the last few decades, in a revolution largely driven in fact by biomedicine. Biology (as physiology), with biomedicine, is now a closely integrated combination of two kinds of science: one is the physics and chemistry of energy exchanges and transformations (quantified in enthalpy change equations, for example), but there is in addition something new: models of mechanisms for the regulation and control of the physics and chemistry, and of other systems, maintaining functions, typically using feedback by information-transfer. The new ‘regulatory’ paradigm, also known as the ‘information-processing’ revolution, appeared clearly in molecular biology in the 1960s and 1970s, such as Jacob and Monod's ground-breaking work on genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins (Jacob & Monod, Reference Jacob and Monod1961; Lewis, Reference Lewis2013).

The new paradigm in biology can be dated to the physicist Ernst Schrödinger (Reference Schrödinger1944) ground-breaking definition of life as local areas in which the overall direction of the 2nd law of thermodynamics is reversed – life decreases entropy, temporarily (Morange, Reference Morange2020; Schrödinger, Reference Schrödinger1944). Schrödinger saw that this would have to involve control of energy production, and he further hypothesized that this was done by genes. An intellectual pathway can be traced from Schrödinger's new conceptualization of biological systems to von Bertalanffy's general system theory (Von Bertalanffy, Reference Von Bertalanffy1968) to Engel's Reference Engel1997 paper. Von Bertalanffy proposed that negative entropy was achieved in open systems, in biology and in wider domains including the psychological and the social, and Engel refers to von Bertalanffy's general system theory as a key theoretical driver for the new BPSM, anticipating impacts on healthcare science and practice (Engel, Reference Engel1977, pp. 391–392). The paradigm shift was, however, still in the early stages in the 1970s – the detailed work in theory development and new associated research paradigms has been underway in the decades since and continues.

The regulatory mechanisms that are central in the new biology have several core features that change the theoretical foundations of the life sciences in ways critical to explicating the BPSM. First, they are causal, but they are not, and are not reducible to, the energy-related equations of physics and chemistry. Second, and connected, regulatory mechanisms can break down, allowing foundational distinctions between life and death, health and disease, that are unavailable in physics and chemistry. Third, the same kind of theoretical apparatus used in biology (function, organization, regulation and dysregulation, information, production, and distribution) is also used in the psychological and social sciences – as reviewed below.

The new psychology

As noted in the Introduction, Engel supposed that the BMM assumed body/mind dualism and that this was an obstacle to accounting for psychological factors in health and disease. I outline in this section two general ways in which post-dualist, cross-disciplinary theories have been developed over recent decades, critical to formulating a biopsychological model.

Post-dualist models can be characterized as having two working assumptions: one is that mental processes regulate behavior and the other is that mental processing is a function of brain processing. The first point underpins cognitive psychology, while the second merges psychology with neuroscience. Both points are connected with the theoretical innovations in biology in the 1960s and 1970s outlined in the previous section: biology, psychology, and neuroscience all shared interests in new information-based models of the regulation of biological systems and behavior – the paradigm shift went across the life sciences.

The clearest expression of dualist assumptions in psychology was in behaviorism, which explicitly excluded mental processes from explanations of behavior – a position much like Engel attributed to the BMM. From around the 1960s onwards, however, behaviorism was swept away in the cognitive revolution (Miller, Reference Miller2003; Xiong & Proctor, Reference Xiong and Proctor2018).

The cognitive revolution influenced many specialties in psychology, not only learning theory. Cognitive models in clinical psychology emphasized the causal role of personal beliefs in the regulation of affect and behavior, such as Beck's cognitive model of depression (Beck, Rush, Shaw, & Emery, Reference Beck, Rush, Shaw and Emery1979). Further, there emerged around this period a class of psychological models focused on the role of expectancies and beliefs about personal control over events – or personal agency – and their implications for well-being. Main examples include Julian Rotter's locus of control theory (Rotter, Reference Rotter1966), Martin Seligman and colleagues’ learned helplessness theory (Seligman & Maier, Reference Seligman and Maier1967) and associated model of depression (Miller & Seligman, Reference Miller and Seligman1975), Albert Bandura's self-efficacy theory (Bandura, Reference Bandura1982, Reference Bandura2006), and Richard Lazarus and Susan Folkman's work on stress, appraisal, and coping (Lazarus & Folkman, Reference Lazarus and Folkman1984).

Importantly, this class of models spanned many psychology specialty areas, across many domains – physiology, learning, personality, and social – and interactions between them. In this sense, they already constituted a theorized BPSM within the broad psychological tent.

The appearance of personal processes in the new psychological science – beliefs, about the world and our agency, personal goals, emotions, and behavior – has substantial relevance to the question whether a broader BPSM is needed in health science and healthcare. Engel gave a long list of important issues the BMM could not account for, and top of the list was ‘the person who has the illness’ (Engel, Reference Engel1977, p. 131). Here the point is, at least, that biomedicine can theorize diseased or otherwise dysfunctional organs or systems, but has nothing to say, over and above that, about the person who has the illness. Equally, it can be added, cognitive psychological models of specific systems such as memory and attention, need a wider, person-level framework to theorize how lowered function affects the person, for example, or typically, by compromising agency.

To sum up, the cognitive revolution in psychology endorsed the relevance of mind to science by constructing causal explanatory models of behavior in terms of mental (or cognitive-affective) states. Within that overall framework, diverse psychology specialty areas focused on personal processes – beliefs, about the world and their own agency, personal goals, emotions, and behavior – in interaction with biological and social processes. These developments in psychology have wide implications and they surface again when considering biopsychosocial models, such as of impacts of social disadvantages on health, and of pain and service use, considered in Part 2, and models of clinical care, in Part 3.

The second aspect of post-dualism models mentioned above is that psychological processing is regarded as a function of, or implemented by, brain processing, hence merging psychology with neuroscience. Cognitive (or cognitive-affective) neuroscience (as the merger can be called) has developed alongside cognitive psychology (Albright, Kandel, & Posner, Reference Albright, Kandel and Posner2000).

The new post-dualist constructs of mind and body, further, accommodate crosstalk between neuroscience/psychology and biomedicine, in both directions. This is evident in the new fields of psychoneuroendocrinology (Fink, Pfaff, & Levine, Reference Fink, Pfaff and Levine2012) and psychoneuroimmunology (Moraes, Miranda, Loures, Mainieri, & Mármora, Reference Moraes, Miranda, Loures, Mainieri and Mármora2018), as well as in specific models such as of chronic stress and pain to be considered later. These interdisciplinary research programs, involving neuroscience, psychology, and biomedicine, were inconceivable in mind–body dualism. They are examples of the rationale for expanding the BMM to the BPSM, in effect contributing content to the concept of ‘biopsychology’ or ‘psychological medicine’ within the BPSM.

A relatively new class of theories known as ‘embodied mind’, ‘embodied cognition’, or ‘4E cognition’, explicitly overturns dualism and are, therefore, potentially relevant to a revitalized BPSM. They are less familiar than theories discussed above, however, and for reasons of space I do not consider them here – for details of the theories and controversies, see e.g. Newen, Gallagher, and De Bruin (Reference Newen, Gallagher, De Bruin, Newen, Bruin and Gallagher2018), Carney (Reference Carney2020), and for current applications in clinical psychology and psychiatry (e.g. Allen & Friston, Reference Allen and Friston2018; Gjelsvik, Lovric, & Williams, Reference Gjelsvik, Lovric and Williams2018).

Social determinants of health

Social factors can be accommodated within the conceptual framework of the new biopsychology because the social sciences have always employed comparable concepts, such as organization, rules and regulations, control (power), communication, and production and distribution of resources (e.g. Lasswell, Reference Lasswell1936). In this sense, it is psychology and biology that made the theory changes critical to the BPSM, thereby becoming more aligned with concepts familiar in the social sciences.

The concept of socioeconomic status is closely connected to an individual's or group's access to resources, and the immediate relevance to health is that resources include what promotes good health (Bickel, Moody, Quisenberry, Ramey, & Sheffer, Reference Bickel, Moody, Quisenberry, Ramey and Sheffer2014; McGowan & Shahab, Reference McGowan, Shahab, Llewellyn, McManus, Weinman, Petrie, Newman, Ayers and Revenson2019). Over the past few decades, a substantial range of epidemiological studies have established that there are social determinants of health, that is, a positive correlation between higher social status and better health, the so-called social gradient in health, which underpins health inequalities (Marmot, Reference Marmot2006). This applies to both physical health and mental health (Bell & Marmot, Reference Bell, Marmot, Dinesh Bhugra and Craig2022).

The resources that we need for biological health are well-known. Consistent with Schrödinger's insight into what life is, they include conditions of biological energy production. What we need for good psychological health is less well understood, probably because mind/body dualism never provided a useful definition of psychological life. In the new conceptualization of psychological life reviewed in the previous section, its conditions may be framed in terms of having sufficient agency (or autonomy). The extent of agency, like access to the conditions of physical well-being, depends on socioeconomic status. As Michael Marmot puts it: ‘The lower individuals are in the social hierarchy, the less likely it is that their fundamental human needs for autonomy and to be integrated into society will be met’ (Marmot, Reference Marmot2006, p. 1304). Autonomy is facilitated by social integration especially into dominant power structures, and conversely is downgraded by exclusion, by denial of voice, civil rights and protections, and other means of oppression. These issues have been explored mainly in and across feminist (Biana, Reference Biana2020), postcolonial (Fanon, Reference Fanon1968), critical race theory (Delgado & Stefancic, Reference Delgado and Stefancic2001), and increasingly in Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Trans, and Queer (LGBTQ) literatures (Lee & Brotman, Reference Lee and Brotman2013). Possible pathways linking social factors to health outcomes will be reviewed below as examples of models of biopsychosocial causal mechanisms.

BPSM research paradigms

Investigating psychological and social impacts on health

Research designs relevant to the BPSM are those that examine the effects of psychological and social, as well as biological factors, on health outcomes (e.g. Lacombe, Armstrong, Wright, & Foster, Reference Lacombe, Armstrong, Wright and Foster2019). Immediate findings are typically of correlations or associations, and control conditions of varying levels of stringency increase confidence in inference to causation. Large-scale group studies are necessary to identify small effects, and the methodology relies on statistical analytic methods such as regression that can estimate the effects of one or more variables on a health condition-dependent variable, estimating independent effects, and interactions moderating the effects of one independent variable by another. Multivariable regression models are applicable within the BMM, including biological variables only, but the expanded BPSM framework also accommodates inclusion of psychological and social variables, estimating their independent, additive, and interaction effects (e.g. Guloksuz et al., Reference Guloksuz, Pries, Delespaul, Kenis, Luykx, Lin and van Os2019).

BPSM compatible research studies were barely available when Engel proposed the new model in 1977. In fact, they began to appear at around the same time. The first clinical trials of psychological therapies appeared in the 1970s, heralding what has become a very large-scale research program of developing and evaluating psychological interventions for a wide range of health conditions and their complications. The early finding that cognitive therapy for depression was effective, and moreover, more effective than an antidepressant medication (Rush, Beck, Kovacs, & Hollon, Reference Rush, Beck, Kovacs and Hollon1977), reinforced the signal that the BMM was not enough, at least not for modeling and treating depression. At the same time, there was another major anomaly for the BMM, the emerging findings of social epidemiology, noted in the previous section, that social status affects a wide range of physical health and mental health outcomes, in the Whitehall Studies by Michael Marmot and colleagues (Marmot, Rose, Shipley, & Hamilton, Reference Marmot, Rose, Shipley and Hamilton1978; Marmot et al., Reference Marmot, Stansfeld, Patel, North, Head, White and Davey Smith1991).

The findings that are anomalous for the BMM but consistent with the BPSM are empirical data, related to specific influences on specific conditions at specific stages. There is nothing a priori in the empirical data. It is possible that a specific health condition at a particular stage may turn out to be primarily caused by only one kind of factor – biological, psychological, or social – and of course biomedical models of infectious diseases have had stunning successes in exactly this way. Such findings may be called a scientific-explanatory reduction to biological processes. This type of ‘reduction’ is different from theory-reduction of, for example, biology to physics and chemistry. Both types of ‘reduction’ are relevant to the relation between the BMM and the BPSM and both are in play in Engel's Reference Engel1977 paper. The BMM would predict scientific-explanatory reduction to primary biological causes only across the whole of health, like the biomedical models of infectious diseases (or of effects of lesions or of genes of major effect). But this is an empirical, not a theoretical matter, and the emerging picture across health is that, especially for the noncommunicable diseases, and including all or practically all mental health conditions, the etiological picture is of at most a ‘patchy’ reductionism, and is more typically diverse, with multiple causal factors (Kendler, Reference Kendler2005, Reference Kendler2012).

Notwithstanding evidence of influence of psychological and social factors on health and disease, there remains a tendency, possibly attributable to long-standing reductionist assumptions in the science, to roll everything up into the biological. There are several examples of this option in the theoretical psychiatry literature. Samuel Guze's highly influential paper over 30 years ago, ‘Biological psychiatry – is there any other kind?’ (Guze, Reference Guze1989) is an example, as indicated by the rhetorical nature of the title question. More recently, Peter White and colleagues proposed that mental disorders are brain disorders, without for a moment being unaware of the research showing the influence of psychosocial factors in the onset and course of many psychiatric conditions (White, Rickards, & Zeman, Reference White, Rickards and Zeman2012). Likewise National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH's) Research Domains Criteria framework, which regards psychiatric conditions as disorders of brain circuitry (Insel et al., Reference Insel, Cuthbert, Garvey, Heinssen, Pine, Quinn and Wang2010).

To the extent that biology, neurology, and neuroscience are being broadly conceived to acknowledge the causal role psychosocial factors in some conditions, in etiology and course, and in prevention and intervention, these theoretical proposals are not reductionist and, albeit unhelpfully expressed, they are compatible with a broad biopsychosocial framework. However, proposals to roll the psychosocial up into the biological appear to be, in name, a kind of reductionism, so far by-passing the need to theorize the acknowledged causal role of psychosocial factors or biopsychosocial causal mechanisms.

Theorized models of causal mechanisms

As well as findings of correlations (or associations) in well-controlled studies, the scientific picture benefits from also having a plausible theory that would explain apparent causal connections. Empiricism in science, relying on observation alone, controlled or otherwise, is well-known to be so far theory-free. In the present case of determining psychological and social causal connections, however, the problem has long been at exactly this point: the absence of a plausible theory of either psychological or social causation, still less theory as to how either could have material effects on biological processes, which were assumed determined by physics and chemistry alone. The assumed impossibility of psychological and social causation and the resulting downwards reductionist pressure inevitably encouraged skepticism toward any apparent empirical demonstration of the impossible. So while empirical evidence for psychosocial causes may accumulate, still, the theory problem is not yet solved and skepticism can persist.

Theory is necessary as well as data, of the sort outlined in the first part of the paper. In brief, psychological causation, implemented in brain processes, involves regulation of behavioral functioning toward attaining or maintaining some state. Social factors can causally interact with psychological processes, for example by regulating task demands and available resources. Psychological and social causal processes are both causal in the sense of regulatory, as is one kind of causation in biology, the other being energy transformations and exchanges covered by physicochemical laws. As to dysfunction, this has to involve disruption to regulation (however caused), because physicochemical laws cannot be disrupted. Models in which regulation/dysregulation are prominent are now to be found not only in biomedicine, but also in clinical psychology and psychiatry (Kendler & Woodward, Reference Kendler and Woodward2021; Liu, Chua, Chong, Subramaniam, & Mahendran, Reference Liu, Chua, Chong, Subramaniam and Mahendran2020). Two well-known illustrations of theorized biopsychosocial causal mechanisms are given below.

The first example is a set of models of chronic stress, applied to epidemiological findings on the social determinants of health, aiming to explain pathways between unfavorable social status and unfavorable health outcomes. The key point for the present context is that the hypothesized causal mechanisms are biopsychosocial, indeed they have to be because the pathways implicated by the epidemiological research run across the three domains. Common hypothesized causal mechanisms and pathways include the following: low levels of social resources (e.g. working poverty and other forms of social exclusion) lead to chronic lack of control over salient outcomes, leading to chronic psychological stress, raising risk of anxiety and depression, while the chronic physiological arousal associated with chronic psychological stress raises the risk of dysregulation and damage across multiple biological systems and hence poor health outcomes. There is not space here nor is it the intention to review the large literature on chronic stress models (O'Connor, Thayer, & Vedhara, Reference O'Connor, Thayer and Vedhara2021; Roberts & Karatsoreos, Reference Roberts and Karatsoreos2021), but simply to give an illustration of a substantial research program on biopsychosocial causal mechanisms.

The second example of a new causal explanatory biopsychosocial theory with wide application comprises new models of pain perception, implicating neurobiological–psychological processing as well as peripheral physiological or structural damage. The new models implicate the person's negative appraisals of the meaning of pain and expected adverse effects on their lives and task demands, and associated Central Nervous System (CNS) pain-processing mechanisms (Garland, Reference Garland2012; Ong, Stohler, & Herr, Reference Ong, Stohler and Herr2019).

This new understanding of pain perception is directly relevant to conditions dominated by pain, but there is a broader point that is relevant to the health sector as a whole, specifically to drivers of service use. The complex of pain, distress about pain, with associated impairment of functioning, is close to ‘feeling unwell’ and is a main driver of referral and service use. It is increasingly recognized that significant proportions of patients with such presentations turn out to have medically unexplained symptoms. ‘Medically unexplained’ here actually means biomedically unexplained, and biomedically orientated clinics typically have no biopsychosocial management protocols in place; consequently needs are not met, and the patient journey can be potentially long and costly; for example, in general practice and medical clinics (Jadhakhan, Lindner, Blakemore, & Guthrie, Reference Jadhakhan, Lindner, Blakemore and Guthrie2019), cardiology (Lenderink & Balkestein, Reference Lenderink and Balkestein2019), neurology (Carson et al., Reference Carson, Best, Postma, Stone, Warlow and Sharpe2003), and surgery for some pain presentations (Louw, Diener, Fernández-de-Las-Peñas, & Puentedura, Reference Louw, Diener, Fernández-de-Las-Peñas and Puentedura2017).

Neuroscience and genetics are biopsychosocial

This overview of BPSM research paradigms with examples of major research programs has to briefly mention that the two life sciences that have accelerated the most in recent decades – genetics and neuroscience – are suited to a biopsychosocial theoretical framework. Indeed, it's more than that; they have been instrumental in making the new BPSM compatible core theory reviewed in Part 1.

It was advanced in genetics that introduced into biology theoretical ideas of a new kind of science involving coding, information-transfer, error, regulation and control, additional to energy-transfer and -exchanges covered by physical–chemical laws (equations). Further, theories of genetics have always been thoroughly interactional across domains, in evolutionary theory, and recently in the new field of epigenetics, including in psychiatry (Campanile, Fanelli, Fabbri, Serretti, & Mendlewicz, Reference Campanile, Fanelli, Fabbri, Serretti, Mendlewicz, Bhugra, Moussaoui, Craig, Bhugra, Moussaoui and Craig2022; Cecil, Reference Cecil, Savulescu, Roache, Davies and Loebel2020).

The same theory-shift that transformed biology also transformed neuroscience and cognitive psychology, enabling a coherent biopsychology. As to the domain of social interactions, there is no shortage of research programs on its major importance to our biopsychology in phylogenesis (Barrett, Henzi, & Barton, Reference Barrett, Henzi and Barton2022) and ontogenesis (Blakemore, Reference Blakemore2008).

Clinical implications

Clinical trials and guidelines

The clearest clinical implications of the BPSM, in contrast as always with the narrower BMM, is accommodation of psychological and social factors as well as biological factors relevant to clinical management and treatment. The importance of this broader scope has been substantially supported in the clinical trials literature, appearing mainly after Engel wrote his 1977 main paper. Large-scale clinical therapeutics research programs in the decades since have studied and shown the effectiveness of some psychological therapies for a large range of health conditions (Barkham & Lambert, Reference Barkham, Lambert, Barkham, Lutz and Castonguay2021), of combination therapy, medication plus psychotherapy, for some conditions such as depression (Breedvelt et al., Reference Breedvelt, Brouwer, Harrer, Semkovska, Ebert, Cuijpers and Bockting2021), and of social treatments such as social support (Brown et al., Reference Brown, Luderowski, Namusisi-Riley, Moore-Shelley, Bolton and Bolton2020; Wang, Mann, Lloyd-Evans, Ma, & Johnson, Reference Wang, Mann, Lloyd-Evans, Ma and Johnson2018). The details of exactly what helps what are always specific to details of treatment, condition(s) and stage, but the overall picture that has emerged from the clinical trials literature is consistent with the broad biopsychosocial framework, in the precise sense that any narrower framework – envisaging treatments that are biological only, psychological only, or social only – omits some effective treatments for some health conditions at particular stages.

Now that there is a substantial clinical trials literature, summarized and adapted in clinical guidelines, it is of major importance in clinical decision making. And the broad message, as above, is that the broad biopsychosocial framework is required to accommodate it.

Like the BMM, the BPSM covers not only causes of onset (etiology) and treatments, but also post-onset maintaining causes that adversely affect prognosis. The models of chronic stress and of pain outlined above are examples of maintaining mechanisms across the biopsychosocial domains. Social determinants of health associated with chronic stress, for example, are typically on-going, affecting not only illness onset but also prognosis, for example, by adversely affecting access to treatment (Schneider, Roots, & Rathmann, Reference Schneider, Roots, Rathmann, Immergut, Anderson, Devitt and Popic2021).

Theorizing personal, interpersonal, and institutional factors in clinical care

A lot more is going on in clinical care than decisions as to what treatments to recommend, including personal, interpersonal, and institutional processes. Specific issues include the role of the person as patient – in determining what is wrong, whether anything is wrong, in collaborating on a treatment plan – the imperative of ‘compassionate’ care (Hodges, Paech, & Bennett, Reference Hodges, Paech and Bennett2020), and institutional/professional factors supporting or jeopardizing good clinical care (Mannion et al., Reference Mannion, Davies, Powell, Blenkinsopp, Millar, McHale and Snowden2019). Engel says a lot of interesting things about all these things in his 1997 paper and others around that time (Engel, Reference Engel1980, Reference Engel1982), and they can be considered as part of what is covered by the BPSM.

While persons, interpersonal relations, and institutions can be accommodated within the BPSM, the contrast with the BMM is, as always, clear. These matters are simply out of the scope of the narrower BMM: they are not in its ontology, and therefore, it has no idea of them at all, still less their causes and effects. Therefore, adherence to the BMM (or to any model or line of thought, by whatever name, which regards biological processes alone as being causally relevant to health and disease) will have to construe these other matters in another way, broadly not as science, but as ‘art’. There is of course a grand tradition of this approach in medical theorizing – see, for example, Nassir Ghaemi (Ghaemi, Reference Ghaemi2010) – and Engel argued against it, favoring rather a broadly scientific-investigatory approach to understanding and improving, for example, receptive and expressive clinical communication skills, and institutional supports of clinical professional care (Bolton, Reference Bolton2020; Engel, Reference Engel1978, Reference Engel1980).

The revitalized, cross-disciplinary BPSM proposed here can be used to theorize personal and institutional factors relevant to clinical care and highlight their role as critical and not merely discretionary considerations. For example, the fundamental importance of personal agency in psychology is consistent with the central role of the person as patient, and the fundamental importance of socio-political factors in regulating recognition and access to resources can help theorize and highlight interpersonal, institutional, and wider political processes that affect clinical care.

The key added value of the BPSM, in contrast with BMM, is that it accommodates personal, interpersonal, and institutional factors in clinical care within the causal systems affecting health and disease. That said, it should be noted that these issues have been most theorized by other models of care, for example patient or person-centered models (Epstein & Street, Reference Epstein and Street2011; Nolte, Reference Nolte2017), and the more recent Recovery Model (Hare-Duke, Ng, & Slade, Reference Hare-Duke, Ng, Slade, Bhugra, Moussaoui and Craig2022), and in reports and studies on healthcare institutional failure (Reader & Gillespie, Reference Reader and Gillespie2013). There is the further important point that the increasing voice of the person as patient has been substantially a consequence of activism and wider socio-political movements, not a matter of healthcare theory and research (Brown, Reference Brown1981; Rashed, Reference Rashed2019).

Conclusion

Engel's proposal in the late 1970s that a new model was needed to take account of not only biological factors affecting health and disease, but also psychological and social factors, was made at a time when the theoretical and empirical backing for it was not established but was rather in construction. The proposed new BPSM can be regarded as being, at the time in the late 1970s, a general empirical hypothesis that psychosocial as well as biological factors are implicated in the causes and cures of illness, and as such, it could have turned out false. As things have turned out, however, the model as a general empirical hypothesis has been confirmed. The determination of relevant evidence in the intervening decades has required the development of new research methodologies capable of determining multifactorial influences on onset, course, complications, and treatments. The overall picture of causes and cures that has emerged, comprising specifics on many particular health conditions and treatments, is broadly biopsychosocial rather than narrowly biological, which is why the terms ‘biopsychosocial’ or ‘biopsychosocial model’ have established extensive application in the clinical literature and in healthcare classrooms. Regarding theory and mechanisms, Engel recognized that reductionism of various sorts in the basic sciences of biology and psychology stood in the way of conceptualizing biopsychosocial causation, and that radical new nonreductive theories were required. As outlined in this paper, these radical changes required to theorize the BPSM were in fact already in their early stages by the late 1970s and are now standard science. Empirical findings, new research paradigms, and theories developed in the last few decades effectively update and revitalize the BPSM.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors

Competing interests

None.

References

Albright, T. D., Kandel, E. R., & Posner, M. I. (2000). Cognitive neuroscience. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 10(5), 612624. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0959-4388(00)00132-X.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Allen, M., & Friston, K. J. (2018). From cognitivism to autopoiesis: Towards a computational framework for the embodied mind. Synthese, 195(6), 24592482. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1288-5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bandura, A. (1982). Self-efficacy mechanism in human agency. American Psychologist, 37(2), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bandura, A. (2006). Toward a psychology of human agency. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1(2), 164180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barkham, M., & Lambert, M. J. (2021). The efficacy and effectiveness of psychological therapies. In Barkham, M., Lutz, W., & Castonguay, L. (Eds.), Bergin and Garfield's handbook of psychotherapy and behavior change (pp. 225262). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
Barrett, L., Henzi, S. P., & Barton, R. A. (2022). Experts in action: Why we need an embodied social brain hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 377(1844), 20200533. doi:10.1098/rstb.2020.0533.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beck, A. T., Rush, A. J., Shaw, B. F., & Emery, G (1979). Cognitive therapy of depression. New York, NY: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Bell, R., & Marmot, M. (2022). Social determinants and mental health. In Dinesh Bhugra, D. M. & Craig, Tom J. (Eds.), Oxford textbook of social psychiatry (pp. 171180). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Biana, H. T. (2020). Extending bell hooks' feminist theory. Journal of International Women's Studies, 21(1), 1329.Google Scholar
Bickel, W. K., Moody, L., Quisenberry, A. J., Ramey, C. T., & Sheffer, C. (2014). A competing neurobehavioral decision systems model of SES-related health and behavioral disparities. Preventive Medicine, 68, 3743.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blakemore, S.-J. (2008). The social brain in adolescence. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9(4), 267277. doi:10.1038/nrn2353.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boden, M. (1999). What is interdisciplinarity? In Cunningham, R. (Ed.), Interdisciplinarity and the organisation of knowledge in Europe (pp. 1324). Luxembourg: Office for the Official Publications of the European Communities.Google Scholar
Bolton, D. (2020). The biopsychosocial model and the new medical humanism. Archives de Philosophie, 83(4), 1340. Retrieved from https://www.cairn-int.info/article-E_APHI_834_0013--.htm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, D., & Gillett, G. (2019). The biopsychosocial model of health and disease: New philosophical and scientific developments. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Breedvelt, J. J. F., Brouwer, M. E., Harrer, M., Semkovska, M., Ebert, D. D., Cuijpers, P., & Bockting, C. L. H. (2021). Psychological interventions as an alternative and add-on to antidepressant medication to prevent depressive relapse: Systematic review and meta-analysis. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 219(4), 538545. doi:10.1192/bjp.2020.198.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brown, J., Luderowski, A., Namusisi-Riley, J., Moore-Shelley, I., Bolton, M., & Bolton, D. (2020). Can a community-led intervention offering social support and health education improve maternal health? A repeated measures evaluation of the PACT project run in a socially deprived London borough. International Journal of Environmental Research and Public Health, 17(8), 2795.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, P. (1981). The mental patients' rights movement and mental health institutional change. International Journal of Health Services, 11(4), 523540. doi:10.2190/cu8g-d0rj-yy54-uc3f.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Campanile, G., Fanelli, G., Fabbri, C., Serretti, A., & Mendlewicz, J. (2022). Epigenetics and aetiology of mental illness. In Bhugra, D., Moussaoui, D., Craig, T. J., Bhugra, D., Moussaoui, D., & Craig, T. J. (Eds.), Oxford textbook of social psychiatry (pp. 4148). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carney, J. (2020). Thinking avant la lettre: A review of 4E cognition. Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture, 4(1), 7790.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carson, A. J., Best, S., Postma, K., Stone, J., Warlow, C., & Sharpe, M. (2003). The outcome of neurology outpatients with medically unexplained symptoms: A prospective cohort study. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 74(7), 897900. doi:10.1136/jnnp.74.7.897.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cecil, C. A. M. (2020). Biopsychosocial pathways to mental health and disease across the lifespan: The emerging role of epigenetics. In Savulescu, J., Roache, R., Davies, W., & Loebel, J. P. (Eds.), Psychiatry reborn: Biopsychosocial psychiatry in modern medicine (pp. 190206). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Committee on Facilitating Interdisciplinary Research (2004). Facilitating interdisciplinary research. Washington, DC: The National Academy Press.Google Scholar
Delgado, R., & Stefancic, J. (2001). Critical race theory. An introduction. New York & London: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Engel, G. L. (1977). The need for a new medical model: A challenge for biomedicine. Science (New York, N.Y.), 196(4286), 129136. doi:10.1126/science.847460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engel, G. L. (1978). The biopsychosocial model and the education of health professionals. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 310, 169181. https://doi.org/10.1016/0163-8343(79)90062-8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Engel, G. L. (1980). The clinical application of the biopsychosocial model. American Journal of Psychiatry, 137(5), 535544. doi:10.1176/ajp.137.5.535.Google ScholarPubMed
Engel, G. L. (1982). The biopsychosocial model and medical education. New England Journal of Medicine, 306(13), 802805. doi:10.1056/nejm198204013061311.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Epstein, R. M., & Street, R. L. Jr. (2011). The values and value of patient-centered care. Annals of Family Medicine, 9(2), 100103. doi:10.1370/afm.1239.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fanon, F. (1968). Black skin, white masks. Trans. Charles Lam Markmann. London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Fink, G., Pfaff, D., & Levine, J. (Eds.). (2012). Handbook of neuroendocrinology. Amsterdam: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Garland, E. L. (2012). Pain processing in the human nervous system: A selective review of nociceptive and biobehavioral pathways. Primary Care, 39(3), 561571.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ghaemi, S. N. (2009). The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 195(1), 34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ghaemi, S. N. (2010). The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model: Reconciling art and science in psychiatry. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Gjelsvik, B., Lovric, D., & Williams, J. M. G. (2018). Embodied cognition and emotional disorders: Embodiment and abstraction in understanding depression. Journal of Experimental Psychopathology, 9(3), pr.035714. doi:10.5127/pr.035714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guloksuz, S., Pries, L.-K., Delespaul, P., Kenis, G., Luykx, J. J., Lin, B. D., … van Os, J. (2019). Examining the independent and joint effects of molecular genetic liability and environmental exposures in schizophrenia: Results from the EUGEI study. World Psychiatry, 18(2), 173182. https://doi.org/10.1002/wps.20629.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Guze, S. B. (1989). Biological psychiatry: Is there any other kind? Psychological Medicine, 19(2), 315323.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare-Duke, L., Ng, F., & Slade, M. (2022). Recovery and the mental health system. In Bhugra, D., Moussaoui, D., & Craig, T. J. (Eds.), Oxford textbook of social psychiatry (pp. 557566). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hodges, B. D., Paech, G., & Bennett, J. (Eds.). (2020). Without compassion, there is no healthcare: Leading with care in a technological age. Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Insel, T., Cuthbert, B., Garvey, M., Heinssen, R., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K., … Wang, P. (2010). Research domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification framework for research on mental disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry, 167(7), 748751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology, 3(3), 318356.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jadhakhan, F., Lindner, O. C., Blakemore, A., & Guthrie, E. (2019). Prevalence of medically unexplained symptoms in adults who are high users of health care services: A systematic review and meta-analysis protocol. BMJ Open, 9(7), e027922.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S. (2005). Toward a philosophical structure for psychiatry. American Journal of Psychiatry, 162(3), 433440. doi:10.1176/appi.ajp.162.3.433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2012). The dappled nature of causes of psychiatric illness: Replacing the organic-functional/hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based pluralism. Molecular Psychiatry, 17(4), 377388. doi:10.1038/mp.2011.182.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S., & Woodward, J. (2021). Top-down causation in psychiatric disorders: A clinical-philosophical inquiry. Psychological Medicine, 51(11), 17831788. doi:10.1017/S0033291721001811.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lacombe, J., Armstrong, M. E. G., Wright, F. L., & Foster, C. (2019). The impact of physical activity and an additional behavioural risk factor on cardiovascular disease, cancer and all-cause mortality: A systematic review. BMC Public Health, 19(1), 900. doi:10.1186/s12889-019-7030-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasswell, H. D. (1936). Politics: Who gets what, when, how. New York: Whittlesey House.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. S., & Folkman, S. (1984). Stress, appraisal, and coping. New York, NY: Springer Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Lee, E. O. J., & Brotman, S. (2013). SPEAK OUT! Structural intersectionality and anti-oppressive practice with LGBTQ refugees in Canada. Canadian Social Work Review/Revue Canadienne de Service Social, 30(2), 157183. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/43486768.Google Scholar
Lenderink, T., & Balkestein, E. J. M. (2019). First time referral reasons, diagnoses and 10-year follow-up of patients seen at a Dutch fast lane outpatient cardiology clinic. Netherlands Heart Journal, 27(7–8), 354361. doi:10.1007/s12471-019-1266-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, M. (2013). Allostery and the lac Operon. Journal of Molecular Biology, 425(13), 23092316. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jmb.2013.03.003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liu, J., Chua, J. J.-X., Chong, S. A., Subramaniam, M., & Mahendran, R. (2020). The impact of emotion dysregulation on positive and negative symptoms in schizophrenia spectrum disorders: A systematic review. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 76(4), 612624. https://doi.org/10.1002/jclp.22915.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Louw, A., Diener, I., Fernández-de-Las-Peñas, C., & Puentedura, E. J. (2017). Sham surgery in orthopedics: A systematic review of the literature. Pain Medicine, 18(4), 736750. doi:10.1093/pm/pnw164.Google ScholarPubMed
Mannion, R., Davies, H., Powell, M., Blenkinsopp, J., Millar, R., McHale, J., & Snowden, N. (2019). Healthcare scandals and the failings of doctors. Journal of Health Organization and Management, 33(2), 221240. doi:10.1108/JHOM-04-2018-0126.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marmot, M. (2006). Status syndrome: A challenge to medicine. JAMA, 295(11), 13041307.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marmot, M., Rose, G., Shipley, M., & Hamilton, P. J. (1978). Employment grade and coronary heart disease in British civil servants. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 32, 244249. doi:10.1136/jech.32.4.244.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marmot, M., Stansfeld, S., Patel, C., North, F., Head, J., White, I., … Davey Smith, G. (1991). Health inequalities among British civil servants: The Whitehall II study. The Lancet, 337(8754), 13871393. https://doi.org/10.1016/0140-6736(91)93068-K.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGowan, J., & Shahab, L. (2019). Socioeconomic status and health. In Llewellyn, C. D., McManus, C., Weinman, J., Petrie, K. J., Newman, S., Ayers, S., & Revenson, T. A. (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of psychology, health and medicine (3rd ed., pp. 4145). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McManus, C. (2005). Engel, Engels, and the side of the angels. The Lancet, 365(9478), 21692170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, G. A. (2003). The cognitive revolution: A historical perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 141144.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Miller, W. R., & Seligman, M. E. (1975). Depression and learned helplessness in man. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 84, 228238. doi:10.1037/h0076720.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moraes, L. J., Miranda, M. B., Loures, L. F., Mainieri, A. G., & Mármora, C. H. C. (2018). A systematic review of psychoneuroimmunology-based interventions. Psychology, Health & Medicine, 23(6), 635652. doi:10.1080/13548506.2017.1417607.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morange, M. (2020). The black box of biology: A history of the molecular revolution (M. Cobb, Trans.). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newen, A., Gallagher, S., & De Bruin, L. (2018). 4E Cognition: Historical roots, key concepts, and central issues. In Newen, A., Bruin, L. d., & Gallagher, S. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 318). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolte, E. (2017). Implementing person centred approaches. BMJ, 358, j4126. doi:10.1136/bmj.j4126.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Novack, D. H., Cameron, O., Epel, E., Ader, R., Waldstein, S. R., Levenstein, S., … Wainer, A. R. (2007). Psychosomatic medicine: The scientific foundation of the biopsychosocial model. Academic Psychiatry, 31(5), 388401. doi:10.1176/appi.ap.31.5.388.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O'Connor, D. B., Thayer, J. F., & Vedhara, K. (2021). Stress and health: A review of psychobiological processes. Annual Review of Psychology, 72(1), 663688. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-062520-122331.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ong, W.-Y., Stohler, C. S., & Herr, D. R. (2019). Role of the prefrontal cortex in pain processing. Molecular Neurobiology, 56(2), 11371166. Retrieved from https://doi.org/10.1007/s12035-018-1130-9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rashed, M. A. (2019). Madness and the demand for recognition: A philosophical inquiry into identity and mental health activism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reader, T. W., & Gillespie, A. (2013). Patient neglect in healthcare institutions: A systematic review and conceptual model. BMC Health Services Research, 13(1), 156. doi:10.1186/1472-6963-13-156.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Roberts, B. L., & Karatsoreos, I. N. (2021). Brain-body responses to chronic stress: A brief review. Faculty Reviews, 10, 83. doi:10.12703/r/10-83.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rotter, J. B. (1966). Generalized expectancies for internal versus external control of reinforcement. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 80, 128. doi:10.1037/h0092976.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rush, A. J., Beck, A. T., Kovacs, M., & Hollon, S. (1977). Comparative efficacy of cognitive therapy and pharmacotherapy in the treatment of depressed outpatients. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 1(1), 1737. doi:10.1007/BF01173502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savulescu, J., Roache, R., Davies, W., & Loebel, J. P. (Eds.). (2020). Psychiatry reborn: Biopsychosocial psychiatry in modern medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneider, S. M., Roots, A., & Rathmann, K. (2021). Health outcomes and health inequalities. In Immergut, E. M., Anderson, K. M., Devitt, C., & Popic, T. (Eds.), Health politics in Europe: A handbook (pp. 3248). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is life? The physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Seligman, M. E., & Maier, S. F. (1967). Failure to escape traumatic shock. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 74(1), 1.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strijbos, S. (2010). Systems thinking. In Frodeman, K. J. T. R. & Mitcham, C. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of interdisciplinarity (pp. 453470). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Von Bertalanffy, L. (1968). General system theory: Foundations, development, applications. New York: George Braziller.Google Scholar
Wade, D. T., & Halligan, P. W. (2017). The biopsychosocial model of illness: A model whose time has come. Clinical Rehabilitation, 31(8), 9951004. doi:10.1177/0269215517709890.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, J., Mann, F., Lloyd-Evans, B., Ma, R., & Johnson, S. (2018). Associations between loneliness and perceived social support and outcomes of mental health problems: A systematic review. BMC Psychiatry, 18(1), 156. doi:10.1186/s12888-018-1736-5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, P., Rickards, H., & Zeman, A. (2012). Time to end the distinction between mental and neurological illnesses. BMJ, 344, e3454.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Xiong, A., & Proctor, R. W. (2018). Information processing: The language and analytical tools for cognitive psychology in the information age. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1270.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed