Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T12:16:32.412Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Measuring the Success of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Ilkka Niiniluoto*
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki

Extract

While most philosophers of science agree that science is, perhaps in many ways, a highly successful enterprise, there is no consensus about the best way of defining and measuring this success. Philosophers are also divided in their views about two further issues: What does the success of a scientific theory indicate? What is the best way of explaining this success?

After some remarks about institutional and pragmatic measures of success, this paper concentrates on rival ways of defining cognitive success. Four realist measures of epistemic credit are discussed: probability, confirmation (corroboration), expected verisimilitude, and probable verisimilitude. Laudan’s non-realist concept of the problem-solving effectiveness of a theory is compared to Hempel’s notion of systematic power. I argue that such truth-independent concepts alone are insufficient to characterize scientific advance. But if they are used as truth-dependent epistemic utilities, they serve as fallible indicators of the truth or truthlikeness of a theory.

Type
Part VIII. Theory and Hypothesis
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carnap, R. (1962), The Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd ed., Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elkana, Y. et al. (eds.) (1978), Toward a Metric of Science: The Advent of Science Indicators, New York: Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science”, Mind 95: 149179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, M.H., and Martin, M.L. (eds.) (1966), Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity, New York: The Odyssey Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1968), “The Varieties of Information and Scientific Explanation”, in van Rootselar, B., and Staal, J.E. (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science III. Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 151171.Google Scholar
Kaila, E. (1939), Inhimillinen tieto, Helsinki: Otava.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984), Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Leplin, J. (ed.) (1984), Scientific Realism, Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I., Gambling With Truth: An Essay on Induction and the Aims of Science, New York: Harper & Row, 1967; 2nd ed. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1973.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1984), Is Science Progressive?, Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1985), “The Significance of Verisimilitude”, in Asquith, P.D., and Kitcher, P. (eds.), PSA 1984, vol. 2, East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 591613.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1986), “Theories, Approximations, Idealizations”, in Barcan Marcus, R., Dorn, G.J.W., and Weingartner, P. (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science VII, Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 255 – 289.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1987), Truthlikeness, Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1989), “Corroboration, Verisimilitude, and the Success of Science”, in Gavroglu, K. et al. (eds.), Imre Lakatos and Theories of Scientific Change, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 229 – 243.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. and Tuomela, R. (1973), Theoretical Concepts and Hypothetico-Inductive Inference, Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pietarinen, J. (1970), “Quantitative Tools for Evaluating Scientific Systematizations”, in Hintikka, J. and Suppes, P. (eds.), Information and Inference, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 123147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. (1988), Scientific Realism: A Critical Reappraisal, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Sintonen, M. (1984), The Pragmatics of Scientific Explanation, Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica 37.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Wright, G.H. (1963), Norm and Action, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar