Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T14:53:37.226Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Answers at Gunpoint: On Livengood and Sytsma’s Revolver Case

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2022

Alexander Max Bauer*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Oldenburg, Ammerländer Heerstraße, Oldenburg, Germany
Jan Romann
Affiliation:
SOCIUM Research Center on Inequality and Social Policy, University of Bremen, Bremen, Germany
*
*Corresponding author: Email: alexander.max.bauer@uni-oldenburg.de
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Jonathan Livengood and Justin Sytsma have published a series of studies on “Actual Causation and Compositionality,” in which they investigate causal attributions of laypeople. We use one of their vignettes to follow up on their research. Our findings cast doubt on their conclusion that ordinary causal attributions tend to violate the compositionality constraint if one looks at cases in which someone is responsible for an effect by way of an intermediary that does not share in the responsibility.

Type
Discussion Note
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

Jonathan Livengood and Justin Sytsma have published a series of studies in “Actual Causation and Compositionality.” Theories of actual causation, they argue, often at least implicitly endorse a so-called compositionality constraint: Imagine that someone, let’s name him Alrik, set up a row of domino tiles. He gave the first tile a flick, and as the result of a chain reaction, all the other tiles were knocked over, too. The first tile’s falling over was directly caused by Alrik’s flick. Since subsequently all the other tiles tumbled over, too, Alrik’s flick did also cause the last tile in the chain to fall. It was not directly but indirectly caused by Alrik’s flick. Here, the flick caused some intermediary tiles to fall, which in turn caused the last tile to fall. This can be expressed in a more abstract way: If we look at some individual events, henceforth denoted as c, d, and e, the compositionality constraint states that, if the event c caused the event e, then it did so either directly, or it did so indirectly via one or more intermediaries d. In this case, every intermediary d is itself an effect of c and a cause of e (Livengood and Sytsma Reference Livengood and Justin2020, 44).

This compositionality constraint intuitively seems to be a reasonable desideratum for any adequate theory of actual causation. However, whether it is indeed correct, Livengood and Sytsma argue, is a different kettle of fish. Arguably, it is not enough to solely rely on the intuitions of a single philosopher or of a small, relatively homogeneous group of thinkers.Footnote 1 Here, the folk attribution desideratum (Livengood, Sytsma, and Rose Reference Livengood, Sytsma and Rose2017) comes into play. This condition of adequacy demands “that what a theory of actual causation says about concrete, everyday cases [has to] accord with ordinary causal attributions” (Livengood and Sytsma Reference Livengood and Justin2020, 48). This in mind, Livengood and Sytsma set out to find answers regarding the question of whether or not causal attributions of laypeople comply with the compositionality constraint. Previous research has already shown that laypeople’s causal attributions are influenced by normative judgements about what someone ought to do. In light of this, Livengood and Sytsma (Reference Sytsma2020, 48) formulate their main hypothesis:

[O]rdinary causal attributions will tend to violate the compositionality constraint for cases in which someone or something is responsible for an effect by way of an intermediary that does not share in the responsibility.

To test this hypothesis, they set up a number of vignette studies, each introducing a short story that contains information on certain agents and their intentions, as well as a causal sequence of events, containing some intermediaries. Subsequent to each vignette, they asked participants to rate their agreement or disagreement with certain statements about causation in the given story. Their first vignette (Livengood and Sytsma Reference Livengood and Justin2020, 49), for example, states:

Amy wants to kill her daughter, Jessica, but she doesn’t want to go to prison for murder. As such, Amy hatches a plan. She arranges for a baby sitter, Courtney, to take care of Jessica while she is out of town on business. Before leaving, Amy laces one of Jessica’s sippy cups with a deadly poison that is very difficult to detect. That evening, Courtney gives Jessica juice in the poisoned sippy cup. Jessica drinks the juice and dies two hours later.

Subsequent to reading this story, subjects were asked to rate their level of agreement or disagreement with the two statements “Amy caused Jessica’s death” and “Courtney caused Jessica’s death” on a seven-point scale from 1 (“strongly disagree”) to 7 (“strongly agree”).

If the causal attributions of laypeople comply with the compositionality constraint, one would expect subjects to agree that intermediaries—in this case, Courtney—also cause the effect in question. Surprisingly, though, subjects tended to rate statements about the causal impact of intermediaries as rather low: For the example above, the responses suggested that the compositionality constraint was clearly violated, since subjects by and large agreed that Amy caused Jessica’s death, but most of them denied that Courtney, too, caused Jessica’s death. Similar results were obtained in the other studies Livengood and Sytsma report on. They found that most causal attributions by laypeople seem to violate the compositionality constraint across the vignettes they tested. Do these surprising results adequately depict laypeople’s idea of actual causation? Or could it be the case that subjects had moral responsibility or blameworthiness in mind—either unconsciously or consciously—rather than the concept of actual causation? These findings, after all, might be in part the result of the way subjects were asked in the first place: Asking about the causal role of involved agents (either at the beginning or at the end of the causal chain) might have led subjects to misinterpret the questions in terms of responsibility. And the only (morally) accountable subject, in this case, would arguably be Amy. Of course, Livengood and Sytsma were well aware of this possibility, which is why they did not settle with those results but conducted a number of subsequent studies. In one of those studies, they introduced two human agents and a number of intermediaries that were mechanical instead of human. Yet, they obtained similar results. Again, it might be the case that subjects focused on the question of responsibility instead of causation. To give some first indications on this, we replicate this study with an altered set of questions to test the robustness of the original findings. In section 2 of this discussion note, we will first introduce Livengood and Sytsma’s study and findings briefly before outlining our own study and findings in section 3. Section 4 concludes the note.

2. Livengood and Sytsma’s Revolver Case

Since this is a discussion note rather than a full-blown replication study, we focus on only one of the vignettes used by Livengood and Sytsma. Clearly, further research has to extend this focus. Here, we limit ourselves to their eighth case. It includes an agent (and thus someone being accountable), but in contrast to their previous studies, it presents a rather long chain of intermediaries that are not themselves human agents. This allows us to adopt the vignette while being able to easily alter the questions asked. Their vignette (Livengood and Sytsma Reference Sytsma2020, 59) reads:

Trent has decided to kill his father, Brad. He aims his loaded revolver at Brad and pulls the trigger, releasing the hammer. The hammer strikes the cartridge, igniting the gun powder. The gun powder explodes, driving the bullet from the gun. The bullet hits Brad in the head. He dies instantly.

Livengood and Sytsma asked 51 subjects to rate their level of agreement or disagreement on a seven-point scale from 1 (“strongly disagree”) to 7 (“strongly agree”) with four statements on causal attribution, namely: (1) “Trent caused Brad’s death,” (2) “The hammer caused Brad’s death,” (3) “The gun powder caused Brad’s death,” and (4) “The bullet caused Brad’s death.” Again, if laypeople’s causal attributions comply with the compositionality constraint and subjects say that Trent caused Brad’s death, then they should also state that the hammer, the gun powder, and the bullet caused Brad’s death as well.

As can be seen in Figure 1, which compares the results from Livengood and Sytsma’s study to ours, a majority of their subjects completely or strongly agreed with the first statement that Trent caused Brad’s death. Here, the central tendency of the responses was statistically above 4. For the second and third statements, though, the central tendency of the responses was statistically below 4, indicating that subjects did not ascribe causation to the intermediaries in question. For the last statement, answers were bimodal. Here, the central tendency was not statistically different from 4. Livengood and Sytsma conclude that their findings suggest that the compositionality constraint is violated.

Figure 1. Bar charts for the cases from Livengood and Sytsma versus our analogous cases. Note: White bars represent the data from Livengood and Sytsma (1 = “Trent caused Brad’s death,” 2 = “The hammer caused Brad’s death,” 3 = “The gun powder caused Brad’s death,” 4 = “The bullet caused Brad’s death”), black bars represent our data (A/H = “Pulling the trigger caused the death of Brad,” B/H = “Releasing the hammer caused the death of Brad,” D/H = “Igniting the gun powder caused the death of Brad,” E/H = “The explosion of the gun powder caused the death of Brad,” F/H = “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the death of Brad,” G/H = “The bullet hitting Brad in the head caused the death of Brad”). We assume that cases 1 and A/H, 2 and B/H, 3 and D/H, 3 and E/H, 4 and F/H, as well as 4 and G/H are analogous.

3. The Revolver Case reconsidered

To test whether or not there might be some first indications that subjects from Livengood and Sytsma’s studies understood the questions in terms of responsibility instead of actual causation, we repeat the study introduced above. To do so, we use the same vignette as they did but alter the set of questions. It is striking that every statement in the original version—that is, “Trent caused Brad’s death,” “The hammer caused Brad’s death,” “The gun powder caused Brad’s death,” and “The bullet caused Brad’s death”—only asks for the causal attribution regarding the outcome, Brad’s death. In this case, we assume, the focus on Brad’s death could easily lead subjects to misinterpret causation as responsibility. This might be less the case, we presume, when subjects are additionally asked about statements that refer not to Brad’s death but to other steps of the causal chain that do not include human agents. We think that this could make the framing of actual causation more salient. To achieve this, we divide the vignette up into a number of events as follows:

  • Event A: “pulling the trigger”

  • Event B: “releasing the hammer”

  • Event C: “striking the cartridge”

  • Event D: “igniting the gun powder”

  • Event E: “the gun powder exploding”

  • Event F: “driving the bullet from the gun”

  • Event G: “the bullet hitting Brad in the head”

  • Event H: “the death of Brad”

Next, we combine those events to statements of the form “X caused Y,” resulting in 28 different items that include all reasonable combinations of events to be made therefrom, for example, “Pulling the trigger caused the release of the hammer,” “Striking the cartridge caused the ignition of the gun powder,” or “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head” (see Appendix A for a full list of items).

As in the original study by Livengood and Sytsma, subjects were asked to state their level of agreement or disagreement with each of those 28 items on a seven-point scale from 1 (“strongly disagree”) to 7 (“strongly agree”.) If the results of Livengood and Sytsma are robust, we should get similar responses not only for their first item but also for their second, third, and fourth item when comparing them to a similar event in our causal chain. Due to our method of constructing the statements, the formulations are slightly different in our study; nonetheless, we consider the following items to be analogous:

  • The first statement from Livengood and Sytsma, “Trent caused Brad’s death,” is similar to our item “Pulling the trigger caused the death of Brad” (A/H in Appendix A).

  • The second statement, “The hammer caused Brad’s death,” is similar to our item “Releasing the hammer caused the death of Brad” (B/H in Appendix A).

  • The third statement, “The gun powder caused Brad’s death,” is similar to our items “Igniting the gun powder caused the death of Brad” and “The explosion of the gun powder caused the death of Brad” (D/H and E/H in Appendix A).

  • The fourth statement, “The bullet caused Brad’s death,” is similar to our items “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the death of Brad” and “The bullet hitting Brad in the head caused the death of Brad” (F/H and G/H in Appendix A). Footnote 2

Our study was programmed in LimeSurvey (2020) and was conducted online in April 2020. Subjects were students from the University of Oldenburg, recruited with the help of the Graduate School for Social Sciences and Humanities. A book voucher worth 20 euros was raffled off between all participants. No approval was sought from the ethics commission since this is a survey using hypothetical vignettes and assessing uncritical opinions. Altogether, there were 52 nonnative English speakers, of whom 22 identified as female, 3 as diverse, and 26 as male (one missing value). The mean age was 27.58 (median: 25), with two participants not indicating their age. Footnote 3

On the first page, subjects were greeted with a welcome screen (see Appendix B). Subsequently, they were shown the vignette together with instructions and the first set of items (see Appendix C and D). Items were presented in an ordered sequence, split into seven groups (as depicted in Appendix A; see also Appendix D) that were presented on separate screens.

Figure 1 displays the evaluations for the cases identified as analogues to those presented by Livengood and Sytsma. Our first statement is evaluated similarly to the one presented by them. The majority of our subjects strongly agrees that “Pulling the trigger caused the death of Brad.” Here, the central tendency of the responses is significantly above 4 (A/H: $V = 876.5,\,p \lt 0.001,\Delta = 0.404$ [ $0.145,$ $0.611$ ]). Footnote 4 There is a striking difference between our results and those from Livengood and Sytsma, though, when we turn to the second statement. Here, the majority of our subjects continues to strongly agree that “Releasing the hammer caused the death of Brad” (B/H: $V = 869,p \lt 0.001,\Delta = 0.481\left[ {0.228,0.673} \right]$ ). The same holds true for the statements “Igniting the gun powder caused the death of Brad” (D/H: $V = 756,p = 0.01,\Delta = 0.289\left[ {0.032,0.509} \right]$ ), “The explosion of the gun powder caused the death of Brad” (E/H: $V = 780,p = 0.02,\Delta = 0.327\left[ {0.065,0.547} \right]$ ), “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the death of Brad” (F/H: $V = 772,p \lt 0.001$ , $\Delta = 0.288\left[ {0.032,0.509} \right]$ ), and “The bullet hitting Brad in the head caused the death of Brad” (G/H: $V = 1053,p \lt 0.001,\Delta = 0.712\left[ {0.495,0.845} \right]$ ). This is in stark contrast to the results of Livengood and Sytsma. Where their subjects did not attribute causation or the picture was not clear, our subjects continued to ascribe causation.

Not only for the cases above, but for every single item of ours, an (oftentimes overwhelming) majority of subjects chose to “strongly agree” that “X caused Y”. Moreover, Wilcoxon matched-pairs signed-rank tests reject the hypothesis that the central tendency for any of the 28 combinations is smaller than or equal to the “neutral” answer of 4 (see Table 1 and Table 2 in Appendix E for summary statistics and test results).

4. Conclusion

Our findings allow for the conjecture that it might indeed be a confusion of actual causation and responsibility that lies behind the surprising findings of Livengood and Sytsma. Instead of showing what subjects think about actual causation, their data might more or less show what their subjects think about responsibility. In this case, their results would not adequately depict laypeople’s idea of actual causation. This might be the case, we suspect, because they oftentimes prominently feature human agents, as we have seen with the two studies presented above: First, the vignettes introduced human agents alongside their morally questionable intentions (“Amy wants to kill her daughter” or “Trent has decided to kill his father”). Second, subjects were asked to indicate their agreement with statements focusing on the causation of a morally undesired outcome (e.g., “Courtney caused Jessica’s death” or “The hammer caused Brad’s death”). Taken together, this might have triggered a desire to blame. Footnote 5 If this is the driving force, then our design might have had a debiasing effect, making considerations of causation more salient than considerations of responsibility. While Livengood and Sytsma only asked about the causal relation between very few domino tiles, so to speak, we asked subjects to evaluate the broader picture. Presenting a large number of statements that mostly refer to mechanical actions rather than human agents and that additionally point out all the possible causal relations they have might have led subjects to actually have causation in mind rather than responsibility since they were forced to reflect on a number of causal relations that clearly had nothing to do with responsibility. This might have shifted the focus away from the blameworthy agent and reduced the effect of subjects’ desire to blame. Footnote 6

This in mind, our findings cast doubt on the conclusion of Livengood and Sytsma that ordinary causal attributions tend to violate the compositionality constraint if we look at cases in which someone is responsible for an effect by way of an intermediary that does not share in the responsibility. Said cases, we assume from our data, fail to make a convincing case against the constraint, as long as the differences between our results and those from Livengood and Sytsma are not explained sufficiently. This opens up a number of questions: Might our results be generalizable in that people always or mostly conform to the compositionality constraint, but recent studies failed to make the question of causality salient? This could have widespread consequences. Should our results turn out to be robust, they might suggest that there is—at least in this regard—no gap between theoretical constructs and folk ideas of actual causation after all. Livengood and Sytsma (Reference Livengood and Justin2020, 64f.) state that “even philosophers, such as Lewis and Menzies, explicitly giving analyses of the ordinary concept of causation have offered theories that entail the compositionality constraint,” and then continue asking: “How could they have gotten things so wrong?” It turns out that they might not have been wrong after all. For now, it seems, they can uphold their theoretical assumptions.

Of course, we only tested one of the many studies from Livengood and Sytsma. Since they mainly varied the vignettes and not the way they asked their subjects, we suspect that similar effects would occur. This needs further testing, though, which is beyond the scope of this discussion note.

Moreover, there is a vast number of possible follow-up questions: Does close proximity of events (say, A/B, B/C, C/D, and so forth) entail a higher rating of causation compared to other combinations of events? Or does human agency have such an effect (as in A/B, A/C, A/D, and so forth; see also Rose Reference Rose2017)? And how do evaluations differ when—as was the case for most studies by Livengood and Sytsma—we look at interpersonal relations (as in A/H)?

Lastly, it has to be noted that the ontological category of the causal relata could make a difference. Livengood and Sytsma asked for the objects (“the hammer,” “the gun powder,” and “the bullet”), we asked for the related events (e.g., “releasing the hammer” or “igniting the gun powder”). As noted above, Livengood, Sytsma, and Rose (Reference Rose2017) did not find differences when emphasising actions as opposed to agents, similar to Livengood and Sytsma (Reference Sytsma2020) when emphasising objects as opposed to agents. Whether or not our different findings are also influenced by this ontological difference needs to be addressed in further studies.

As can be seen from these questions, there is much to be done.

Acknowledgements

First and foremost, we thank Jonathan Livengood and Justin Sytsma for interesting impulses and exciting exchanges, as well as for sharing their data and R files with us. Malte Ingo Meyerhuber, Stephan Kornmesser, and Mark Siebel provided insightful comments. Rea Kodalle kindly helped to find participants for our study. Ewgenia Baraboj carefully proofread this discussion note. We are indebted to them all. We also thank four anonymous reviewers who provided helpful comments to this discussion note.

Appendix A. Items

Group A

  • Combination A/B: “Pulling the trigger caused the release of the hammer.”

  • Combination A/C: “Pulling the trigger caused the hammer to strike the cartridge.”

  • Combination A/D: “Pulling the trigger caused the ignition of the gun powder.”

  • Combination A/E: “Pulling the trigger caused the explosion of the gun powder.”

  • Combination A/F: “Pulling the trigger caused the bullet to be driven from the gun.”

  • Combination A/G: “Pulling the trigger caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination A/H: “Pulling the trigger caused the death of Brad.”

Group B

  • Combination B/C: “Releasing the hammer caused the hammer to strike the cartridge.”

  • Combination B/D: “Releasing the hammer caused the ignition of the gun powder.”

  • Combination B/E: “Releasing the hammer caused the explosion of the gun powder.”

  • Combination B/F: “Releasing the hammer caused the bullet to be driven from the gun.”

  • Combination B/G: “Releasing the hammer caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination B/H: “Releasing the hammer caused the death of Brad.”

Group C

  • Combination C/D: “Striking the cartridge caused the ignition of the gun powder.”

  • Combination C/E: “Striking the cartridge caused the explosion of the gun powder.”

  • Combination C/F: “Striking the cartridge caused the bullet to be driven from the gun.”

  • Combination C/G: “Striking the cartridge caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination C/H: “Striking the cartridge caused the death of Brad.”

Group D

  • Combination D/E: “Igniting the gun powder caused the explosion of the gun powder.”

  • Combination D/F: “Igniting the gun powder caused the bullet to be driven from the gun.”

  • Combination D/G: “Igniting the gun powder caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination D/H: “Igniting the gun powder caused the death of Brad.”

Group E

  • Combination E/F: “The explosion of the gun powder caused the bullet to be driven from the gun.”

  • Combination E/G: “The explosion of the gun powder caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination E/H: “The explosion of the gun powder caused the death of Brad.”

Group F

  • Combination F/G: “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the bullet to hit Brad in the head.”

  • Combination F/H: “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the death of Brad.”

Group G

  • Combination G/H: “The bullet hitting Brad in the head caused the death of Brad.”

Appendix B. Welcome Message

Welcome to this short survey. You won’t need more than fifteen minutes to complete it.

Among all participants who answer this survey by Saturday, April 19, an Amazon voucher worth 20 euros will be raffled off.

On the following pages, we will present you with a scenario and ask you to assess your agreement or disagreement with different statements that are made about this scenario.

Please read both the scenario’s description and the task carefully.

Thank you for participating!

Appendix C. Vignette and Instructions

Trent has decided to kill his father, Brad. He aims his loaded revolver at Brad and pulls the trigger, releasing the hammer. The hammer strikes the cartridge, igniting the gun powder. The gun powder explodes, driving the bullet from the gun. The bullet hits Brad in the head. He dies instantly. Please rate your level of agreement or disagreement with the following statements below. 1 represents “strongly disagree,” 4 is “neutral,” and 7 represents “strongly agree.”

Appendix D. Example Screens

Figure 2. Example of the first screen with questions shown to subjects.

Figure 3. Example of the second screen with questions shown to subjects.

Appendix E. Tables

Table 1. Summary Table for All Statements

Statement Mean Standard Error 95% Confidence Interval Variance
A/B 5.89 0.26 [5.37, 6.40] 3.48
A/C 5.56 0.27 [5.02, 6.10] 3.74
A/D 5.33 0.28 [4.77, 5.88] 4.00
A/E 5.12 0.29 [4.54, 5.70] 4.34
A/F 5.19 0.28 [4.63, 5.75] 4.08
A/G 4.92 0.31 [4.31, 5.54] 4.86
A/H 5.17 0.33 [4.51, 5.83] 5.64
B/C 5.90 0.27 [5.37, 6.44] 3.70
B/D 5.67 0.25 [5.17, 6.18] 3.28
B/E 5.25 0.27 [4.71, 5.79] 3.80
B/F 5.17 0.28 [4.62, 5.73] 4.00
B/G 4.90 0.30 [4.31, 5.50] 4.56
B/H 5.21 0.31 [4.59, 5.84] 5.07
C/D 5.75 0.28 [5.18, 6.32] 4.19
C/E 5.54 0.26 [5.02, 6.05] 3.43
C/F 5.21 0.28 [4.65, 5.77] 4.01
C/G 4.69 0.32 [4.06, 5.32] 5.16
C/H 4.94 0.32 [4.29, 5.59] 5.47
D/E 5.94 0.27 [5.41, 6.48] 3.70
D/F 5.58 0.25 [5.07, 6.08] 3.27
D/G 4.94 0.30 [4.35, 5.53] 4.53
D/H 4.88 0.32 [4.24, 5.53] 5.32
E/F 5.92 0.26 [5.41, 6.44] 3.41
E/G 4.88 0.30 [4.28, 5.49] 4.70
E/H 4.79 0.31 [4.16, 5.42] 5.15
F/G 5.19 0.30 [4.59, 5.79] 4.63
F/H 4.96 0.32 [4.33, 5.60] 5.21
G/H 6 0.24 [5.53, 6.47] 2.86

Table 2. Two-tailed Wilcoxon Signed-Rank Tests for All Statements. p-values were corrected using the false discovery rate method by Benjamini and Hochberg (Reference Benjamini and Hochberg1995)

Case V p
A/B 1079.00 <0.001***
A/C 1058.50 < 0.001***
A/D 998.00 < 0.001***
A/E 842.00 0.001**
A/F 792.00 < 0.001***
A/G 872.00 0.004**
A/H 876.50 < 0.001***
B/C 1067.50 < 0.001***
B/D 978.50 < 0.001***
B/E 915.50 < 0.001***
B/F 794.00 < 0.001***
B/G 806.50 0.004**
B/H 869.00 0.001**
C/D 1152.50 < 0.001***
C/E 880.00 < 0.001***
C/F 891.50 < 0.001***
C/G 699.00 0.035*
C/H 697.50 0.005**
D/E 1134.00 < 0.001***
D/F 986.00 < 0.001***
D/G 905.00 0.004**
D/H 756.00 0.006**
E/F 1108.00 < 0.001***
E/G 722.50 0.007**
E/H 780.00 0.02*
F/G 849.00 < 0.001***
F/H 772.00 0.004**
G/H 1053.00 < 0.001***

*p < 0.05, **p <0.01, ***p <0.001.

Footnotes

2 One might notice that in doing so, we assume that people make judgements about agents or objects on the one hand and actions or events on the other hand in analogous ways. While this is something research has to explore more deeply in the future, we can, for now, note that Livengood, Sytsma, and Rose (Reference Rose2017) did not find differences when emphasising actions as opposed to agents, similar to Livengood and Sytsma (Reference Sytsma2020) when emphasising objects as opposed to agents.

4 We use Wilcoxon matched-pairs signed-rank tests to reject the hypothesis that the central tendency for each statement is less than or equal to the “neutral” value of 4, as did Livengood and Sytsma. The R package effsize, authored by Torchiano (Reference Torchiano2020), was used to calculate Cliff’s delta for our comparisons.

5 The assumption of blame as a driving factor behind causal judgements is well established in the literature (see, e.g., Alicke and Rose Reference Alicke and David2010; Alicke, Rose, and Bloom Reference Alicke, Rose and Bloom2011; Alicke and Rose Reference Alicke and David2012; Danks, Rose, and Machery Reference Danks, Rose and Machery2014; Rose Reference Rose2017; Sytsma Reference Sytsma2020).

6 This could also be understood loosely as a framing effect: The same vignette and the analogue items are perceived differently given the context of the other items.

References

Alicke, Mark David, and David, Rose. 2010. “Culpable Control or Moral Concepts?Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4):330–1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, Mark David, and David, Rose. 2012. “Culpable Control and Causal Deviance.Social and Personality Psychology Compass 6 (10):723–35.Google Scholar
Alicke, Mark David, Rose, David, and Bloom, Dori. 2011. “Causation, Norm Violation, and Culpable Control.” The Journal of Philosophy 108 (12):670–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bauer, Alexander Max, and Malte, Ingo Meyerhuber. 2019. “Zwei Welten am Rande der Kollision: Zum Verhältnis von empirischer Forschung und normativer Theorie, insbesondere vor dem Hintergrund der Ethik.” In Philosophie zwischen Sein und Sollen: Normative Theorie und empirische Forschung im Spannungsfeld, edited by Alexander Max Bauer and Malte Ingo Meyerhuber, 1337. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bauer, Alexander Max, and Malte, Ingo Meyerhuber. 2020. “Two Worlds on the Brink of Colliding: On the Relationship Between Empirical Research and Normative Theory.” In Empirical Research and Normative Theory: Transdisciplinary Perspectives on Two Methodical Traditions Between Separation and Interdependence, edited by Alexander Max Bauer and Malte Ingo Meyerhuber, 11–33. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benjamini, Yoav, and Hochberg, Yosef. 1995. “Controlling the False Discovery Rate: A Practical and Powerful Approach to Multiple Testing.Journal of the Royal Statistical Society: Series B (Statistical Methodology) 57 (1):289300.Google Scholar
Danks, David, Rose, David, and Machery, Edouard. 2014. “Demoralizing Causation.” Philosophical Studies 171 (2):251–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LimeSurvey. 2020. Limesurvey: An Open Source Survey Tool. Manual. https://www.limesurvey.org. Hamburg, Germany: LimeSurvey Project.Google Scholar
Livengood, Jonathan, and Justin, Sytsma. 2020. “Actual Causation and Compositionality.Philosophy of Science 87 (1):4369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Livengood, Jonathan, Sytsma, Justin, and Rose, David. 2017. “Following the FAD: Folk Attributions and Theories of Actual Causation.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 8 (2):273–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, David. 2017. “Folk Intuitions of Actual Causation: A Two-Pronged Debunking Explanation.Philosophical Studies 174 (5):1323–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sytsma, Justin. 2021. “Causation, Responsibility, and Typicality.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 12 (233):699–719.Google Scholar
Torchiano, Marco. 2020. Effsize: Effcient Effect Size Computation. Version 0.8.0. Manual. https://cran.r-project.org/package=effsize.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Bar charts for the cases from Livengood and Sytsma versus our analogous cases. Note: White bars represent the data from Livengood and Sytsma (1 = “Trent caused Brad’s death,” 2 = “The hammer caused Brad’s death,” 3 = “The gun powder caused Brad’s death,” 4 = “The bullet caused Brad’s death”), black bars represent our data (A/H = “Pulling the trigger caused the death of Brad,” B/H = “Releasing the hammer caused the death of Brad,” D/H = “Igniting the gun powder caused the death of Brad,” E/H = “The explosion of the gun powder caused the death of Brad,” F/H = “The bullet being driven from the gun caused the death of Brad,” G/H = “The bullet hitting Brad in the head caused the death of Brad”). We assume that cases 1 and A/H, 2 and B/H, 3 and D/H, 3 and E/H, 4 and F/H, as well as 4 and G/H are analogous.

Figure 1

Figure 2. Example of the first screen with questions shown to subjects.

Figure 2

Figure 3. Example of the second screen with questions shown to subjects.

Figure 3

Table 1. Summary Table for All Statements

Figure 4

Table 2. Two-tailed Wilcoxon Signed-Rank Tests for All Statements. p-values were corrected using the false discovery rate method by Benjamini and Hochberg (1995)