Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-wpx69 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T23:58:15.922Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume's “Is‐Ought” Problem: a solution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

David Hume first raised the “is-ought” problem in this famous passage from A Treatise of Human Nature:

I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation which may, perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark’d, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs, when of a sudden I am surpriz’d to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible, but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation ‘tis necessary that it shou’d be observ’d and explain’d, and at the same time that a reason should be given for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention wou’d subvert all the vulgar system of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by reason.

Behind Hume’s quietly persuasive comments lie at least two questionable assumptions. The first is that the way language is ordinarily used is wrong; rather than take note, in an empirical fashion, of how moral discourse is normally conducted, Hume chooses to be negatively prescriptive in respect of “all the vulgar system of morality”.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2000 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

References

1 David Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, Selby‐Bigge edition, p 467–70.

2 I wrote about these previously in New Blackfriars. See ‘Lonergan and Hume ‐ Epistemology’ in New Blackfriars March and May 1982.

3 For a clear account by Lonergan of the notion of the four levels of consciousness, see his article The Subject’ in A Second Collection, Darton, Longman and Todd 1972, p 69 fGoogle Scholar.

4 L. Wittgenstein, ‘Lecture on Ethics’, edited by Rush Rhees, in Philosophy Today, edited by Hall, Jerry, Macmillan 1968Google Scholar.

5 See for example, Method in Theology by Lonergan, Bernard SJ, Darton, Longman and Todd 1972. p 121–2Google Scholar.

6 ‘Does Finnis get natural rights for everyone?’ by Mark R. Discher, New Blackfriars January 1999, p 29.