Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T07:30:40.842Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Proportion dominance in valuing lives: The role of deliberative thinking

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

André Mata*
Affiliation:
William James Center for Research, ISPA — Instituto Universitário, Rua Jardim do Tabaco 41, 1149-041 Lisboa, Portugal
*
* E-mail: amata@ispa.pt
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Proportion responding (PR) is the preference for proportionally higher gains, such that the same absolute quantity is valued more as the reference group decreases. This research investigated this kind of proportion PR in decisions about saving lives (e.g., saving 10/10 lives is preferred to saving 10/100 lives). The results of two studies suggest that PR does not stem from an overall tendency to choose higher proportions, but rather from faulty deliberative reasoning. In particular, people who display PR are less likely to engage in deliberative reflection as measured by response time, the Process Dissociation Procedure, the Cognitive Reflection Test, a numeracy test, and a task assessing denominator neglect. This association between faulty deliberation and PR was observed only when choosing the highest proportion was non-normative because it came at the expense of absolute gains (e.g., saving 10/10 lives is preferred to saving 11/100 lives). These results help to make sense of discrepant findings in previous research, pertaining to how PR relates to biased reasoning and decision making.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2016] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

People evaluate a program that can save 2 out of 4 people more favorably than a program that can save 2 out of 112 (Reference Jenni and LoewensteinJenni & Loewenstein, 1997) because the proportion of the reference group that is saved is higher in the first case than in the second. This preference for the higher proportion can be so strong as to lead people to forego an option with the higher absolute number of gains. For instance, people have been shown to prefer saving 225 of 300 people rather than saving 230 of 920 (Reference BartelsBartels, 2006). This sensitivity to relative savings even when absolute savings are reduced has been termed proportion dominance (Reference BartelsBartels, 2006; Reference Finucane, Peters and SlovicFinucane, Peters & Slovic, 2003), the reference group effect (Reference Jenni and LoewensteinJenni & Loewenstein, 1997), drop-in-the-bucket thinking (Reference Bartels and BurnettBartels & Burnett, 2011), or psychophysical numbing (Reference Friedrich, Barnes, Chapin, Dawson, Garst and KerrFriedrich et al., 1999; Reference SlovicSlovic, 2007), and it is widely replicated (Reference BaronBaron, 1997; Reference Bartels and BurnettBartels & Burnett, 2011; Erlandsson, Björklund & Bäckström, 2014, 2015; Reference Fetherstonhaugh, Slovic, Johnson and FriedrichFetherstonhaugh, Slovic, Johnson & Friedrich, 1997; Reference Friedrich, Barnes, Chapin, Dawson, Garst and KerrFriedrich et al., 1999; Reference Kleber, Dickert, Peters and FlorackKleber, Dickert, Peters & Florack, 2013; Reference Kogut and Beyth-MaromKogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008).

This kind of proportion responding (PR) has been discussed as a case that violates normative tenets of judgment and decision making, as the value of a life should not change as a function of the size of the reference group (Reference BaronBaron, 1997; Reference BartelsBartels, 2006; Reference Fetherstonhaugh, Slovic, Johnson and FriedrichFetherstonhaugh et al., 1997; Reference Friedrich, Barnes, Chapin, Dawson, Garst and KerrFriedrich et al., 1999; Reference Jenni and LoewensteinJenni & Loewenstein, 1997; Reference Peters, Slovic, Västfjäll and MertzPeters, Slovic, Västfjäll & Mertz, 2008; Reference SlovicSlovic, 2007), and especially not to the point of justifying foregoing the chance to save more lives. Bartels (2006) found PR even when decision makers were in a joint evaluation mode (Reference HseeHsee, 1996), and it was therefore clear that PR leads to saving fewer lives. Furthermore, Bartels found that, even though people recognize that PR is wrong in these cases when they are retrospectively asked to judge what weight should absolute vs. relative numbers have for their judgments, these retrospective judgments do not reflect people’s actual PR-biased judgments (as also found by Kogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008). In this paper, I use PR to refer to attention to proportion, and I distinguish between non-normative and normative types of PR, depending on whether PR leads to a worse outcome or not, respectively.

The present studies test whether PR stems from faulty thinking, that is, a failure to engage in deliberative thinking, or whether it originates in a general tendency to engage in proportional reasoning and prefer proportional gains over absolute ones.

1.1 Is PR related to faulty deliberation?

The findings from extant research are mixed in this regard. On the one hand, Bartels (2006) showed that PR correlates with a low disposition to think in a reflective manner (though those studies did not assess subjects’ actual ability to think reflectively, but rather relied only on a self-report measure of thinking style: the Rational-Experiential Inventory of Epstein, Pacini, Denes-Raj & Heier, 1996). On the other hand, Kleber et al. (2013) showed that PR is associated with having higher numerical reasoning skills. Adding to the mixed pile of findings, Peters et al. (2008) found that numeracy was not related to PR, although the precision of numerical representation influenced choices, albeit in a negative way: more precision was associated with choosing the proportionally superior but normatively incorrect option. Finally, Stanovich and West (2008) also found that PR is unrelated to cognitive ability as measured by subjects’ SAT scores.

One possible reason for these seemingly discrepant findings is that previous research has sometimes investigated PR when it clearly violates normativity, whereas in other studies this is not the case. Indeed, in many studies, PR does not necessarily constitute a violation of normativity, because both options are equal in absolute numbers and only vary in proportions, and therefore PR does not come at the expense of sacrificing a greater absolute number of lives (Jenni & Lowenstein, 1997; see also Erlandsson et al., 2014, 2015; Fetherstonhaugh et al., 1997, Studies 1 & 2; Friedrich et al., 1999; Kleber et al., 2013, Study 2). However, in other studies, PR is clearly non-normative: the option with the highest value of relative savings has the lowest value in absolute savings (Reference BartelsBartels, 2006; Reference Fetherstonhaugh, Slovic, Johnson and FriedrichFetherstonhaugh et al., 1997, Study 3; Kleber et al., 2013, Studies 1 & 3; Reference Peters, Slovic, Västfjäll and MertzPeters et al., 2008).

The present research tested whether the preference for higher proportions relates to intuitive thinking, as a function of whether it violates normative standards or not. Rather than expecting preference for higher proportions to be associated with intuitive reasoning overall, we expect that to be the case only when it is non-normative. This is because, in that case, the proportionally superior option should still be compelling, but people should realize that it is not correct (Reference BartelsBartels, 2006; Reference Kogut and Beyth-MaromKogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008).

The present studies provide an exhaustive set of tests of how PR relates to intuitive thinking vs. careful deliberative reasoning. First, they test whether PR correlates with poor performance in other reasoning tasks: a choice task assessing denominator neglect (Reference Bonner and NewellBonner & Newell, 2010; Reference Denes-Raj and EpsteinDenes-Raj & Epstein, 1994), the Cognitive Reflection Test (CRT; Reference FrederickFrederick, 2005), and numeracy (Reference Lipkus, Samsa and RimerLipkus, Samsa & Rimer, 2001). Furthermore, these studies examine response times and test whether non-normative PR is based on hastier responses, another indicator that careful reflection was not used in the decision-making process. In addition, the present research applies the Process Dissociation Procedure (Reference JacobyJacoby, 1991; Reference Jacoby, Toth and YonelinasJacoby, Toth & Yonelinas, 1993) to assess to what extent controlled/deliberative thought processes (or a lack thereof) contribute to PR.

1.2 Is PR related to a tendency to think proportionally?

An alternative to the faulty deliberation hypothesis (though not mutually exclusive) is that PR stems from an overall tendency to think proportionally and always choose the higher proportion, regardless of whether that is the normatively correct option or not.

Studies on the development of mathematical reasoning reveal situations where people over-apply proportional reasoning: Van Dooren, De Bock, Hessels, Janssens, and Verschaffel (2005) found that 1) at early ages, students are not capable of reasoning proportionally; 2) later on, students become more capable of proportional reasoning, but they also start to over-apply it to situations where it is not called for, as in the following problem: “Ellen and Kim are running around a track. They run equally fast but Ellen started later. When Ellen has run 4 laps, Kim has run 12 laps. When Ellen has run 24 laps, how many has Kim run?” So, with increasing numerical reasoning capacity, students engage in more proportional reasoning, but they do so both when it is correct and when it is not. And 3) only at a later developmental stage do most people acquire the ability to judge whether they should use proportional reasoning or not.

That research further suggests that the proportional response might be so extensively practiced in school that it becomes the prepotent heuristic or intuitive response (Reference Gillard, Van Dooren, Schaeken and VerschaffelGillard, Van Dooren, Schaeken & Verschaffel, 2009), which must be overridden by effortful and time-consuming reflective thinking (see also Kogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008). Consistent with this hypothesis, Gillard et al. showed that constraining response time or imposing cognitive load on reasoners had little influence on their ability to answer correctly to problems where proportional thinking is appropriate, but it made them more likely to over-apply proportional thinking to problems where that kind of thinking is not appropriate (problems like the aforementioned one, about the two runners).

Therefore, it might be that PR results from a tendency to over-apply proportional reasoning. If that is the case, then we should find that the same people who are prone to PR also show a preference for proportionally superior options in other choice domains. In this regard, the denominator neglect task that is used in Study 1 provides an important test.

Denominator neglect can be instantiated in the following example: When people are asked to choose an urn from which to draw a ball that might grant them a prize, and they can choose from either a small urn with 1 prized ball out of 10 balls in total or a large urn with 9 prized balls out of 100, many people go for the option with the highest number of prized balls even though the odds of winning are lower (Reference Bonner and NewellBonner & Newell, 2010; Reference Denes-Raj and EpsteinDenes-Raj & Epstein, 1994). Avoiding this bias takes time (Reference Bonner and NewellBonner & Newell, 2010; Reference Ferreira, Mata, Donkin, Sherman and IhmelsFerreira et al., 2016) and working memory resources (Reference Ferreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman and ShermanFerreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman & Sherman, 2006), which are characteristics of reflection/deliberation in dual-process theories.

In Study 1, subjects completed different tasks that assessed PR and denominator neglect. This offers a strong test of whether biased reasoning contributes to PR or not, given that PR and denominator neglect are opposite biases: PR consists of valuing the higher proportion and neglecting absolute frequencies, whereas denominator neglect consists of choosing the highest absolute frequency even when that does not correspond to the highest proportion. Therefore, if PR results from an overall tendency to engage in proportional reasoning, then it should even help to prevent denominator neglect. But if PR comes from a tendency to engage in a biased tendency to unreflectively follow the more compelling or intuitive answer, particularly when PR is not normative, then it should be associated with a tendency for denominator neglect. Indeed, Ayal, Hochman, and Zakay (2011) showed that people with a low disposition to engage in rational thinking (as measured by the Rational-Experiential Inventory) tend to commit such opposite biases.

2 Study 1

This first study tests whether PR is associated with quick response times, denominator neglect (an indicator of poor reflection but greater attention to proportions; Reference Pacini and EpsteinPacini & Epstein, 1999; Reference Toplak, West and StanovichToplak, West & Stanovich, 2011), and lower scores on the controlled parameter of the Process Dissociation Procedure, depending on whether PR is normative or not.

The denominator neglect task was adapted so as to use the Process Dissociation Procedure, which has proven apt to dissect judgment and decision making biases and examine the extent to which automatic vs. controlled thought processes underlie them (Ferreira et al., 2006, 2016; Reference Mata, Ferreira and ReisMata, Ferreira & Reis, 2013; Reference Mata, Fiedler, Ferreira and AlmeidaMata, Fiedler, Ferreira & Almeida, 2013). The logic of this procedure requires having harmony trials, where automatic and controlled processes suggest the same response, and conflict trials, where the different kinds of processes lead to different responses. The conflict trials are those that are typically used in this task, whereby the option with the higher numerator is different from the option with the higher proportion (e.g., 1/10 vs. 9/100). In harmony trials, on the other hand, the option with the higher numerator is the same as the option with the higher proportion (e.g., 1/10 vs. 11/100). Comparing performance in harmony and conflict allows for independent estimates of automatic and controlled processing in people’s reasoning (see Method section below). Therefore, the inclusion of the denominator neglect task enabled us to calculate the strength of subjects’ controlled and automatic thought processes in an independent task and then assess how well each of these predicts PR. It is expected that the estimate of automatic processing does not vary as a function of whether people show PR in their choices or not, suggesting that the proportion dominant choice is equally compelling for all responders regardless of whether they end up overriding that response tendency or not. Rather, PR should relate to lower controlled processing, especially when PR is non-normative and people should therefore override the tendency to choose the higher proportion.

The Process Dissociation Procedure enables a fine-grained distinction of the kinds of processes that contribute to PR. In previous research using self-report measures (Reference BartelsBartels, 2006), PR was examined in relation to a relative measure of the degree to which the rational subscale score outweighed the intuitive score. Therefore, it is not clear from that research whether PR is due to more rational/deliberative thinking or less intuitive thinking. Kogut and Beyth-Marom (2008) make the specific prediction that PR is a bias that results from “the intuitive, automatic system (…) which failed to be corrected by the analytical, rational system” (p. 604). Given that the Process Dissociation Procedure aims to assess the independent contribution of these kinds of thought processes, the procedure can provide a test of the association between PR and reduced deliberation.

Finally, this study assesses response time, as yet another measure of reflection. As with the other indicators of reflection, it is expected that response time relates to PR (i.e., PR should be associated with quicker responses), but only when PR is non-normative.

2.1 Method

Subjects.

One hundred Psychology undergraduates participated for partial course credit.

Procedure and design.

Subjects were given three scenarios to read (presented in a different random order for each subject) involving decisions to save the lives of people or animals (see Appendix A). As an example, in one of the scenarios, subjects were asked to imagine that two houses were on fire, and that they had to decide whether to save either all 10 people that were in a small house, or another 10 people from a total of 100 that were in a big house. In the non-normative condition, the second option involved saving 11 out of 100, such that it represented the lower proportion but the higher absolute number.

There were two conditions, counterbalanced between-subjects, which varied on whether PR was non-normative or not. Subjects were randomly assigned to either the non-normative PR condition (the scenarios were about saving 10/10 or 11/100) or the condition where PR did not violate normativity (the scenarios were about saving 10/10 or 10/100).

For the denominator neglect task, subjects were asked to imagine that they were playing a game where they could draw one ball from one of two trays containing red balls and white balls. To win this game, subjects were told that they would have to draw a red ball. They could choose to draw a random ball from a small tray (e.g., containing 1 red ball out of 10 balls in total) or from a large tray (e.g., containing 9 red balls out of 100 balls in total; see instructions in Appendix A).

Unlike the instructions for the proportion dominance task, which required reading detailed trial-specific scenarios, the instructions for the denominator neglect task were simple and constant across trials, which enabled subjects to quickly perform this task over many trials. We wished to have a high quantity and diversity of trials so that we could have reliable Process Dissociation estimates. Specifically, having many trials, and trials of different sorts, was meant to make it more tempting for subjects to go with their gut feeling in some trials and not always decide in a calculating fashion. Indeed, it is sometimes hard to obtain biased responses in this task with a small number of trials (e.g., Reference Pacini and EpsteinPacini & Epstein, 1999), and an invariant correct performance makes it difficult to estimate the automatic/heuristic parameter of the Process Dissociation Procedure (Reference Ferreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman and ShermanFerreira et al., 2006).

There were several kinds of trials in the denominator neglect task (adapted from Reference Bonner and NewellBonner & Newell, 2010). The small tray had between 1 and 3 red balls out of 10 balls in total (i.e., 1/10, 2/10 or 3/10), and the large tray had a number of red balls out of a total of 100 such that the proportion of winning was 4% lower, 1% lower, equal, 1% higher, or 4% higher as compared to the small tray (e.g., 1/10 vs. 6/100, 1/10 vs. 9/100, 1/10 vs. 10/100, 1/10 vs. 11/100, 1/10 vs. 14/100). Crossing these factors produced 15 different trials: 6 harmony trials where the option with the larger numerator also corresponded to the larger proportion; 3 equal trials where the proportion was the same for both options; and 6 conflict trials where the option with the larger numerator was not the one with the larger proportion. Each trial was presented 17 times throughout the task. The resulting 255 trials were divided into 4 blocks, in the middle of which each of the 3 problems assessing proportion dominance was presented (i.e., 1 PR problem in each interval between blocks of the denominator neglect trials).

The A and C parameters of the Process Dissociation Procedure (referring to “automatic” and “controlled” processing, respectively) were calculated according to the following analytical procedure (Reference Ferreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman and ShermanFerreira et al., 2006): In harmony trials, because automatic/intuitive and controlled/deliberative thought processes concur on the choice, the probability of choosing the option with both the larger numerator and the larger proportion is C + A (1 − C). In conflict trials, where intuitive and deliberative thought suggest different responses, the option with the larger numerator will be selected only if deliberative thought fails (as the proportion is smaller in this case), as a consequence of intuitive thought, and therefore the probability of choosing the larger numerator is A (1 − C). Based on the previous equations, it is possible to calculate C as the difference of probabilities of choosing the larger numerator in harmony versus conflict trials (i.e., p largenumerator/harmonyp largenumerator/conflict), and A as p largenumerator/conflict/(1 − C).

2.2 Results and discussion

The proportion of problems in which subjects chose the PR option was higher when PR did not violate normativity than when it was non-normative, M = .62, SD = .29 vs. M = .35, SD = .38, t(90.61) = 3.94, p < .001. One-sample t tests comparing the number of PR choices against 50/50 revealed that most subjects preferred the PR option when it did not violate normativity, but chose against it when it was non-normative, ps ≤ .009.

Table 1 shows the correlations of normative and non-normative PR with the proportion of denominator-neglect trials where the subjects chose the option with the higher numerator across the three kinds of trials, the process dissociation parameters, and the average response times on PR problems (response times were log-transformed; see Reference RatcliffRatcliff, 1993).

Table 1: Correlations of number of PR choices with other measures by normativity (p levels in parentheses).

Subjects who made more non-normative PR choices were also more likely to make more non-normative choices in the denominator neglect problems (i.e., choosing the higher numerator but lower proportion in conflict trials, and choosing the lower numerator and lower proportion in harmony trials). They also scored lower on the C parameter of the Process Dissociation Procedure. (The equivalent analysis for the A parameter revealed no significant effect.) And they took less time to make their choices in the PR task. In contrast, when PR was not against normativity, choices did not correlate with any of the other measures.

The results of Study 1 suggest that PR seems to result not from a general preference for higher proportions, but rather from faulty deliberative reasoning. That is, non-normative responding in one task correlates with non-normative responding in another task, whereas there was no evidence for a correlation based on differences in the tendency to respond in terms of proportions regardless of the task. Study 2 provides further tests of the deliberation-failure hypothesis.

3 Study 2

Whereas in Study 1 the normativity of PR was manipulated between subjects, in Study 2 all subjects solved PR problems where the PR option meant saving fewer lives or more lives overall. Respectively, these two kinds of problems constitute conflict vs. harmony trials, and comparing choices across them makes it possible to compute Process Dissociation estimates. Moreover, this is a better way to manipulate normativity than the normative condition used in Study 1, where, even though PR did not entail sacrificing more lives (i.e., both options involved the same absolute number, only the proportions varied), it was not clear what the correct option was, as there was not an option with a higher absolute number. Subjects also completed the CRT and a numeracy scale.

Several hypotheses were tested: First, if people recognize the non-normativity of PR in conflict trials, where PR implies saving fewer lives, then PR should be lower in those trials than in harmony trials. This would replicate the between-conditions difference that was found in Study 1. Second, as the CRT and the numeracy scale measure the tendency to think deliberatively about the problem at hand, scores on these tests should relate negatively to PR in conflict trials (i.e., non-normative PR) and positively to the C scores of the Process Dissociation Procedure (i.e., the ability to choose PR depending on whether it is normative or not). Finally, in terms of response times, in harmony trials, deciding quickly or deliberatively should both lead to the same decision: choosing the PR-option. However, in conflict trials, one should take longer to reflect on whether or not the PR-option is correct and give the other response. Therefore, just as in Study 1, decision time should not predict choices in harmony trials, but it should do so in conflict trials, with normative responses (to not choose the PR option) taking more time than non-normative ones.

3.1 Method

Subjects.

One hundred subjects were recruited through Amazon’s Mechanical Turk (104 ended up participating, as 4 subjects did not sign up for compensation and were therefore not registered on Mechanical Turk as having taken part in the study). Subjects were located in the United States and were required to have an approval rate in previous assignments of at least 95%.

Procedure and design.

Subjects were given ten scenarios to read, involving decisions to save the lives of people or other species (some of these were adapted from Bartels, 2006; see Appendix B). For half of them – the conflict trials – the PR option was different from the option where the highest absolute number of lives could be saved. For the other half – the harmony trials – the PR option was also the option where the highest absolute number of lives could be saved. The different scenarios were presented in random order.

After the scenarios, subjects responded to an adapted version of the CRT and to the Lipkus et al. (2001) Numeracy Scale (Appendix B).

3.2 Results and discussion

In harmony trials, where PR was the normative option, the proportion of PR choices was higher than in conflict trials, where PR violated normativity, M = .92, SD = .17 vs. M = .52, SD = .38, paired t(104) = 10.05, p < . 001.

Table 2 shows the correlations of CRT, numeracy and average (log-transformed) response times with normative and non-normative PR.

Table 2: Correlations of number of PR choices with other measures by normativity (p levels in parentheses).

Note. The mean response time in the top rows is specific to type of trial (non-normative or normative PR). In the bottom rows it is averaged across trials.

Subjects who made more non-normative PR choices scored lower on both the CRT and the numeracy test, and they also took less time to make their choices. In contrast, in harmony trials, PR choices correlate only with numeracy, and not with CRT score, nor with response time. Sinayev and Peters’ (2015) indices of calculation (i.e., number of correct responses) and reflection (i.e., number of non-intuitive responses, both correct and incorrect) do not differ in terms of the correlations between CRT and the other measures.

Additionally, having higher C Process-Dissociation scores correlated with taking longer to decide on the PR scenarios overall, whereas the A scores did not (see Table 2).

4 General discussion

This research investigated people’s preference for relative gains (i.e., PR) in decisions about saving lives. Even though many people refrained from showing PR when it came at the expense of absolute gains – in this particular case, at the expense of lives – a large percentage of subjects showed PR even when that was the case (35% in Study 1, and 52% in Study 2). Corroborating the non-normative nature of PR in this case, subjects who chose higher proportions when that meant saving fewer lives overall were also more likely to display biased decision making in another domain (denominator neglect; Study 1); they manifested lower engagement in deliberative reflection, as measured by response times (Studies 1 and 2), the C score of the Process Dissociation Procedure (Study 1), the CRT and a numeracy scale (Study 2). Furthermore, the ability to choose for or against PR depending on whether it is normative or not (as measured by the C parameter of the Process Dissociation Procedure) correlated positively with measures of deliberative reasoning, such as taking longer to respond and scoring higher on the CRT and numeracy (Study 2).

These results, together with the fact that most people prefer the PR option when it does not violate normativity (e.g., preferring to save 10/10 instead of 10/100 in Study 1), support the notion that PR is a compelling prepotent response tendency, and that deliberative reasoning is required in order to judge its appropriateness and override it, if need be (Reference Gillard, Van Dooren, Schaeken and VerschaffelGillard et al., 2009; Reference Kogut and Beyth-MaromKogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008; Reference Van Dooren, De Bock, Hessels, Janssens and VerschaffelVan Dooren et al., 2005).

This deliberation-failure hypothesis seems to account better for PR than an overall preference for higher proportions. Indeed, if it were the case that PR comes from an overall tendency to think proportionally, then those subjects who displayed PR in Study 1 should be less likely to show denominator neglect, but the opposite was the case.

These results help to make sense of some seemingly discrepant findings in previous research, with regard to whether PR relates to biased reasoning and decision making. Those studies considered only scenarios where PR was normative or scenarios where it was not normative. Results were therefore mixed (cf. Bartels, 2006; Reference Kleber, Dickert, Peters and FlorackKleber et al., 2013; Reference Peters, Slovic, Västfjäll and MertzPeters et al., 2008; Reference Stanovich and WestStanovich & West, 2008). The present studies systematically investigated the role of deliberative thinking in PR depending on whether PR is normative or not. The results form a consistent picture. To summarize: PR is a compelling prepotent response option (Reference Gillard, Van Dooren, Schaeken and VerschaffelGillard et al., 2009; Reference Kogut and Beyth-MaromKogut & Beyth-Marom, 2008). People can override this tendency and forego PR when it is not normative, but this requires the ability to engage in careful deliberation.

Appendix A: Tasks used in Study 1

Proportion Dominance: People Scenario

Imagine that in a town two houses are on fire: a big house with 100 people inside and a small house with 10 people inside. In this town there is only one fire engine, so you have to decide which of the two houses you will send the fire engine to. You only have time to save one of the houses.

If you choose to send the fire engine to the small house, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 10 people in that house.

If you choose to send the fire engine to the big house, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 100 people in that house.

What house would you send the fire engine to?

Proportion Dominance: Pandas Scenario

Imagine that in a forest there are two wild life reserves where panda bears live: a small reserve with 10 pandas and a big one with 100 pandas. A fire is burning in this forest and will eventually consume all of it. The two reserves are located far from each other, so you have time to try to save only one of the reserves.

If you choose to go to the small reserve, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 10 pandas in that reserve.

If you choose to go to the big reserve, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 100 pandas in that reserve.

Which reserve would you choose to go to?

Proportion Dominance: Horses Scenario

Imagine that a train is running lose and it is going so fast that it is impossible to stop it. All you can do is direct it to one of two tracks: track A where there are 10 horses or track B where there are 100 horses.

If the train goes down track A, all 10 horses in that track will die; but all the horses in track B will live.

If the train goes down track B, 10 out of the 100 horses in that track will die; but all the horses in track A will live.

Which track would you direct the train to?

Denominator Neglect

We want you to imagine that you are playing a game.

In this game you are presented with two trays: a small tray with 10 balls and a large tray with 100 balls.

Each tray contains a certain number of red balls and white balls.

Imagine that in this game you get a prize if you draw a red ball.

You can only draw one ball from one of the two trays to try and draw the winning red ball. Your task is to choose which of the two trays - the small or the large - you want to draw a ball from.

Throughout the experiment you will play this game a great number of times. Your task in every game is the same: choose which tray you would like to draw a ball from.

Appendix B: Tasks used in Study 2

Proportion Dominance / Conflict Trial 1

Imagine that in a town, two houses are on fire: a big house with 100 people inside and a small house with 10 people inside. In this town there is only one fire engine, so you have to decide which of the two houses you will send the fire engine to. You only have time to save one of the houses.

If you choose to send the fire engine to the small house, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 10 people in that house.

If you choose to send the fire engine to the big house, you are certain to save exactly 11 out of the 100 people in that house.

What house would you send the fire engine to?

Proportion Dominance / Harmony Trial 1

Imagine that in a forest there are two wild life reserves where panda bears live: a small reserve with 10 pandas and a big one with 100 pandas. A fire is burning in this forest and will eventually consume all of it. The two reserves are located far from each other, so you have time to try to save only one of the reserves.

If you choose to go to the small reserve, you are certain to save exactly 10 out of the 10 pandas in that reserve.

If you choose to go to the big reserve, you are certain to save exactly 9 out of the 100 pandas in that reserve.

Which reserve would you choose to go to?

Proportion Dominance / Conflict Trial 2

An amusement park is nearing the final stages of planning before construction when it is found that construction will destroy some trees where an endangered species of songbird nests. The planners are willing to adopt one of two proposed solutions to the problem.

Program A saves 19 of the 25 birds that nest in Area A.

Program B saves 20 of the 400 birds that nest in Area B.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Harmony Trial 2

A species of plant found only in a remote area of New Guinea is threatened with extinction by a recently introduced species of vine. You have access to two treatments that kill the vines and save the plants, but you only have enough money to fund one program.

If you implement Program A, you will save 19 of the 25 plants located in Quadrant A.

If you implement Program B, you will save 18 of the 400 plants located in Quadrant B.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Conflict Trial 3

The current recession has forced companies to cut jobs. Your office provides financial support to struggling businesses in the local economy, but limited resources force you to choose which businesses to assist.

Program A saves 54 of the 60 jobs that would have otherwise been lost at Factory A.

Program B saves 56 of the 560 jobs that would have otherwise been lost at Factory B.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Harmony Trial 3

The city council is auctioning off two former nature preserves for commercial development. The corporations that buy the land will bulldoze the land and erect office buildings. Your organization protects public spaces by purchasing lots like these and preserving them. There is only enough money to purchase a portion of the land up for auction.

If you implement Program A, you can purchase 54 of the 60 acres in Plot A, saving them from development.

If you implement Program B, you can purchase 52 of the 560 acres in Plot B, saving them from development.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Conflict Trial 4

An oil spill around Puget Sound is threatening the sea otter populations in two areas of the bay. Two cleanup plans are proposed, but there is only enough money to support one plan. So, there are only enough resources to save otters in one of these areas of the bay.

Program A will save 120 of the 150 otters near the north end of the bay.

Program B will save 124 of the 800 otters near the south end of the bay.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Harmony Trial 4

Two areas off the southeast coast of Florida are heavily populated with dolphins and tuna. Tuna fishermen accidentally catch a number of dolphins in these areas every year. Dolphins that get caught in the tuna nets drown, because they cannot surface to breathe. To combat this problem, new nets have been designed that will save a number of dolphins. The tuna fishing industry has agreed to fish with the new nets in only one of these two areas.

Program A would require boats in Area A to use a different type of net, which would save 120 of the 150 dolphins that die in that area each year.

Program B would require boats in Area B to use a different type of net, which would save 116 of the 800 dolphins that die in that area each year.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Conflict Trial 5

You are on a committee at a major paper company with two factories on a mid-sized river. These factories use water from the river to cool their machines. Once used, the water is exhausted back into the stream. This polluted water causes a number of fish to die every year near the factory from which it is exhausted. Filters can be installed that will save a number of fish, but filter installation is expensive, and there is only enough money in the budget to install filters at one factory.

Program A filters the water exhausted from Factory A, resulting in the prevention of 245 of the annual 350 fish deaths due to pollution.

Program B filters the water exhausted from Factory B, preventing 251 of the annual 980 fish deaths due to pollution.

These programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

Proportion Dominance / Harmony Trial 5

Emergency medical aid is needed at two different sites in a war-torn country. You are the head of the only medical convoy in the area. There is only enough time, and there are only enough supplies, to visit one camp.

Treating Camp A will save the lives of 245 of the 350 patients who would otherwise die.

Treating Camp B will save the lives of 239 of the 980 patients who would otherwise die.

These treatment programs are mutually exclusive and the only two options available. Which would you choose?

CRT-Type Problems

A TV and a DVD together cost 88 dollars. The TV costs 80 dollars more than the DVD. How much does the DVD cost?

If it takes 10 hens 10 days to lay 10 eggs, how long would it take 100 hens to lay 100 eggs?

A computer virus is spreading through the system of a computer. Every minute, the number of infected files doubles. If it takes 100 minutes for the virus to infect all of the system, how long would it take for the virus to infect half of the system?

Numeracy Scale

  1. 1) Imagine that we rolled a fair, six-sided die 1,000 times. Out of 1,000 rolls, how many times do you think the die would come up even (2, 4, or 6)?

  2. 2) In the BIG BUCKS LOTTERY, the chances of winning a $10.00 prize is 1%. What is your best guess about how many people would win a $10.00 prize if 1,000 people each buy a single ticket to BIG BUCKS?

  3. 3) In the ACME PUBLISHING SWEEPSTAKES, the chance of winning a car is 1 in 1,000. What percent of tickets to ACME PUBLISHING SWEEPSTAKES win a car?

  4. 4) Which of the following numbers represents the biggest risk of getting a disease: 1 in 100, 1 in 1000, or 1 in 10?

  5. 5) Which of the following numbers represents the biggest risk of getting a disease? 1% _____ 10% _____ 5% _____

  6. 6) If Person A’s risk of getting a disease is 1% in ten years, and person B’s risk is double that of A’s, what is B’s risk?

  7. 7) If Person A’s chance of getting a disease is 1 in 100 in ten years, and person B’s risk is double that of A’s, what is B’s risk?

  8. 8) If the chance of getting a disease is 10%, how many people would be expected to get the disease: 8A) Out of 100? ________ 8B) Out of 1000? ________

  9. 9) If the chance of getting a disease is 20 out of 100, this would be the same as having a ____% chance of getting the disease.

  10. 10) The chance of getting a viral infection is .0005. Out of 10,000 people, about how many of them are expected to get infected?

Footnotes

*

The author gratefully acknowledges the financial support provided by the Portuguese Science Foundation under the following grants: UID/PSI/04810/2013; IF/01612/2014. The author is also thankful to Cristina Mendonça for helping with the data collection for Study 2. Part of the data collected in Study 1 were used in Ferreira, Mata, Donkin, Sherman and Ihmels (2016).

References

Ayal, S., Hochman, G., & Zakay, D. (2011). Two sides of the same coin: Information processing style and reverse biases. Judgment and Decision Making, 6, 295306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, J. (1997). Confusion of relative and absolute risk in valuation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 301309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, D. M. (2006). Proportion dominance: The generality and variability of favoring relative savings over absolute savings. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 100, 7695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, D. M., & Burnett, R. C. (2011). A group construal account of drop-in-the-bucket thinking in policy preference and moral judgment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 5057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonner, C., & Newell, B. R. (2010). In conflict with ourselves? An investigation of heuristic and analytic processes in decision making. Memory & Cognition, 38, 186196.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Denes-Raj, V., & Epstein, S. (1994). Conflict between intuitive and rational processing: when people behave against their better judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 819829.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Epstein, S., Pacini, R., Denes-Raj, V., & Heier, H. (1996). Individual differences in intuitive–experiential and analytical–rational thinking styles. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 390405.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Erlandsson, A., Björklund, F., & Bäckström, M. (2014). Perceived utility (not sympathy) mediates the proportion dominance effect in helping decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 27, 3747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erlandsson, A., Björklund, F., & Bäckström, M. (2015). Emotional reactions, perceived impact and perceived responsibility mediate the identifiable victim effect, proportion dominance effect and in-group effect respectively. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 127, 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferreira, M. B., Garcia-Marques, L., Sherman, S. J., & Sherman, J. W. (2006). Automatic and controlled components of judgment and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 797813.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ferreira, M. B., Mata, A., Donkin, C., Sherman, S. J., & Ihmels, M. (2016). Analytic and heuristic processes in the detection and resolution of conflict. Memory & Cognition, in press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fetherstonhaugh, D., Slovic, P., Johnson, S., & Friedrich, J. (1997). Insensitivity to the value of human life: A study of psychophysical numbing. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 283300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finucane, M. L., Peters, E., & Slovic, P. (2003). Judgment and decision making: The dance of affect and reason. In S. L. Schneider & J. Shanteau (Eds.), Emerging perspectives on judgment and decision research (pp. 327364). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19, 2542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedrich, J., Barnes, P., Chapin, K., Dawson, I., Garst, V., & Kerr, D. (1999). Psychophysical numbing: When lives are valued less as the lives at risk increase. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 8, 277299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillard, E., Van Dooren, W., Schaeken, W., & Verschaffel, L. (2009). Proportional reasoning as a heuristic-based process: Time constraint and dual task considerations. Experimental Psychology, 56, 9299.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hsee, C. K. (1996). The evaluability hypothesis: An explanation for preference reversals between joint and separate evaluations of alternatives. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 67, 247257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacoby, L. L. (1991). A process dissociation framework: Separating automatic from intentional uses of memory. Journal of Memory and Language, 30, 513541.Google Scholar
Jacoby, L. L., Toth, J. P., & Yonelinas, A. P. (1993). Separating conscious and unconscious influences of memory: Measuring recollection. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 122, 139154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jenni, K. E., & Loewenstein, G. F. (1997). Explaining the “identifiable victim effect”. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 235257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleber, J., Dickert, S., Peters, E., & Florack, A. (2013). Same numbers, different meanings: How numeracy influences the importance of numbers for pro-social behavior. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 699705.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kogut, T., & Beyth-Marom, R. (2008). Who helps more? How self-other discrepancies influence decisions in helping situations. Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 595606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipkus, I. M., Samsa, G., & Rimer, B. K. (2001). General performance on a numeracy scale among highly educated samples. Medical Decision Making, 21, 3744.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mata, A., Ferreira, M. B., & Reis, J. (2013). A process-dissociation analysis of semantic illusions. Acta Psychologica, 144, 433443.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mata, A., Fiedler, K., Ferreira, M. B., & Almeida, T. (2013). Reasoning about others’ reasoning. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 486491.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pacini, R., & Epstein, S. (1999). The relation of rational and experiential information processing styles to personality, basic beliefs, and the ratio-bias phenomenon. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 972987.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peters, E., Slovic, P., Västfjäll, D., & Mertz, C. K. (2008). Intuitive numbers guide decisions. Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 619635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ratcliff, R. (1993). Methods for dealing with reaction time outliers. Psychological Bulletin, 114, 510532.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sinayev, A. & Peters, E. (2015). Cognitive reflection vs. calculation in decision making. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 532.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slovic, P. (2007). If I look at the mass I will never act”: Psychic numbing and genocide. Judgment and Decision Making, 2, 7995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2008). On the relative independence of thinking biases and cognitive ability. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 672695.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Toplak, M. E., West, R. F., & Stanovich, K. E. (2011). The Cognitive Reflection Test as a predictor of performance on heuristics-and-biases tasks. Memory & Cognition, 39, 12751289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Dooren, W., De Bock, D., Hessels, A., Janssens, D., & Verschaffel, L., (2005). Not everything is proportional: Effects of age and problem type on propensities for overgeneralization. Cognition and Instruction, 23, 5786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Correlations of number of PR choices with other measures by normativity (p levels in parentheses).

Figure 1

Table 2: Correlations of number of PR choices with other measures by normativity (p levels in parentheses).

Supplementary material: File

Mata supplementary material

Mata supplementary material 1
Download Mata supplementary material(File)
File 7.6 KB
Supplementary material: File

Mata supplementary material

Mata supplementary material 2
Download Mata supplementary material(File)
File 13.3 KB