Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-kc5xb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-13T13:30:46.416Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Just assassinations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 November 2013

Eamon Aloyo*
Affiliation:
Global Justice Senior Analyst at the Global Governance Institute, Brussels, Belgium

Abstract

I argue that widely accepted just war theory precepts morally allow and require the assassination of politically powerful individuals under some circumstances instead of waging a just war or implementing any other policy such as non-targeted economic sanctions that would very likely severely harm more innocents. While all just war theory precepts permit just assassinations under certain circumstances, proportionality, necessity, and last resort make just assassinations required whenever they would cause severe harm to the fewest innocents. There are several implications of my argument. First, there are fewer circumstances when wars and other policies that foreseeably but unintentionally harm innocents are just than is commonly thought. Second, the realm of morally permissible violent and non-violent action for powerful individuals is more limited than many presume and politicians are more often morally liable to actions that would mitigate or end objectively unjust serious threats for which they are culpable, although this does not always include lethal force.

Type
Original Papers
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Altman, AndrewWellman, Christopher. 2008. “From Humanitarian Intervention to Assassination: Human Rights and Political Violence.” Ethics 118(2):228257.Google Scholar
Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret. 1961. “War and Murder.” In Nuclear Weapons: A Catholic Response, 1st ed., edited by Walter Stein, 4362. New York: Sheed & Ward.Google Scholar
Baker, Deane-PeterPattison, James. 2012. “The Principled Case for Employing Private Military and Security Companies in Interventions for Human Rights Purposes.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 29(1):118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BBC. 2013. “Syria Death Toll Rises Above 100,000.” BBC, July 25, sec. Middle East. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-middle-east-23455760.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 1980. “Nonintervention and Communal Integrity.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9(4):385391.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles 2009. “The Moral Standing of States Revisited.” Ethics & International Affairs 23(4):325347.Google Scholar
Bellamy, Alex. 2008. “The Responsibilities of Victory: Jus Post Bellum and the Just War.” Review of International Studies 34(4):601625.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 1971. “The Question of Machiavelli.” The New York Review of Books, November 4. http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1971/nov/04/a-special-supplement-the-question-of-machiavelli/.Google Scholar
Brown, Chris. 2003. “Selective Humanitarianism: In Defense of Inconsistency.” In Ethics and Foreign Intervention, edited by Deen Chatterjee and Don Scheid, 3150. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, 4th ed.New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Carvin, Stephanie. 2012. “The Trouble with Targeted Killing.” Security Studies 21(3):529555.Google Scholar
Chenoweth, EricaStephan, Maria. 2008. “Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict.” International Security 33(1):744.Google Scholar
Chenoweth, EricaStephan, Maria 2011. Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Church, Frank. 1975. Alleged Assassination Plots Involving Foreign Leaders. Washington: US Government Printing Office. http://archive.org/details/allegedassassina00unit.Google Scholar
Coady, Tony. 2003. “War for Humanity: A Critique.” In Ethics and Foreign Intervention, edited by Deen Chatterjee and Don Scheid, 274295. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, CAJ 2008. Messy Morality: The Challenge of Politics. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cumming-Bruce, Nick. 2013a. “More Than 60,000 Have Died in Syrian Conflict, U.N. Says.” The New York Times, January 2, sec. World/Middle East. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/03/world/middleeast/syria-60000-united-nations.html.Google Scholar
Cumming-Bruce, Nick 2013b. “U.N. Rights Panel on Syria Urges War Crimes Charges.” The New York Times, February 18, sec. World/Middle East. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/02/19/world/middleeast/un-rights-panel-says-violence-in-syria-is-mounting.html.Google Scholar
Dikötter, Frank. 2011. Mao's Great Famine: The History of China's Most Devastating Catastrophe, 1958–1962. New York: Walker & Company.Google Scholar
Dikötter, Frank 2010. “Mao's Great Leap to Famine”. The New York Times, December 15, sec. Opinion. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/12/16/opinion/16iht-eddikotter16.html.Google Scholar
Dinstein, Yoram. 2010. The Conduct of Hostilities Under the Law of International Armed Conflict, 2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael. 2009. “A Few Words on Mill, Walzer, and Nonintervention.” Ethics & International Affairs 23(4):349369.Google Scholar
Ellis, Anthony. 2003. “War, Revolution, and Humanitarian Intervention.” In Humanitarian Intervention: Moral and Philosophical Issues, edited by Aleksandar Jokic, 1734. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2008. “Cosmopolitanism, Just War Theory and Legitimate Authority.” International Affairs 84(5):963976.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cécile 2012. Cosmopolitan War. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finkelstein, Claire, Ohlin, Jens DavidAltman, Andrew. eds. 2012. Targeted Killings: Law and Morality in an Asymmetrical World. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fletcher, George P.Ohlin, Jens David. 2008. Defending Humanity: When Force Is Justified and Why. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fortna, Virginia Page. 2004. “Does Peacekeeping Keep Peace? International Intervention and the Duration of Peace After Civil War.” International Studies Quarterly 48(2):269292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frost, Mervyn. 1996. Ethics in International Relations: A Constitutive Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frowe, Helen. 2010. “A Practical Account of Self-Defence.” Law and Philosophy 29(3):245272.Google Scholar
Frowe, Helen 2011. The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Geneva Convention, Additional Protocol 1. 1977. “Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (Protocol 1)”, June 8. http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf/INTRO/470.Google Scholar
Gladstone, Rick, Schmitt, Eric. 2013. “Syria Faces New Claim on Chemical Arms”. The New York Times, April 18, sec. World/Middle East. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/19/world/middleeast/Syria.html.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Joshua S. 2011. Winning the War on War: The Decline of Armed Conflict Worldwide. New York: Dutton.Google Scholar
Gordon, Joy. 1999. “A Peaceful, Silent, Deadly Remedy: The Ethics of Economic Sanctions.” Ethics & International Affairs 13(1):123142.Google Scholar
Gordon, Joy 2006. “Accountability and Global Governance: The Case of Iraq.” Ethics & International Affairs 20(1):7998.Google Scholar
Gordon, Joy 2010. Invisible War: The United States and the Iraq Sanctions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gross, Michael L. 2003. “Fighting by Other Means in the Mideast: a Critical Analysis of Israel's Assassination Policy.” Political Studies 51(2):350368.Google Scholar
Gross, Michael L. 2006. “Assassination and Targeted Killing: Law Enforcement, Execution or Self-Defence?Journal of Applied Philosophy 23(3):323335.Google Scholar
Gross, Michael. 2010. Moral Dilemmas of Modern War: Torture, Assassination, and Blackmail in an Age of Asymmetric Conflict, 1st ed. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hafner-Burton, Emilie M.Tsutsui, Kiyoteru. 2007. “Justice Lost! The Failure of International Human Rights Law to Matter Where Needed Most.” Journal of Peace Research 44(4):407425.Google Scholar
Hill, Daniel W. Jr. 2010. “Estimating the Effects of Human Rights Treaties on State Behavior.” The Journal of Politics 72(4):11611174.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2005. “Proportionality in the Morality of War.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33(1):3466.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas 2008. “Proportionality and Necessity.” In War: Essays in Political Philosophy, edited by Larry May, 127144. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
ICISS. 2001. The Responsibility to Protect: The Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty. Ontario, Canada: IDRC Books.Google Scholar
Johnston, Patrick B. 2012. “Does Decapitation Work? Assessing the Effectiveness of Leadership Targeting in Counterinsurgency Campaigns.” International Security 36(4):4779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, BenjaminOlken, Benjamin. 2009. “Hit or Miss? The Effect of Assassinations on Institutions and War.” American Economic Journal: Macroeconomics 5587.Google Scholar
Kahler, Miles. 2011. “Legitimacy, Humanitarian Intervention, and International Institutions.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 10(1):2045.Google Scholar
Kathman, Jacob D.Wood, Reed M.. 2011. “Managing Threat, Cost, and Incentive to Kill The Short- and Long-Term Effects of Intervention in Mass Killings.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 55(5):735760.Google Scholar
Keith, L. Camp, C. Neal, TateC. Poe, Steven. 2009. “Is The Law a Mere Parchment Barrier to Human Rights Abuse?The Journal of Politics 71(2):644660.Google Scholar
Kim, HunjoonSikkink, Kathryn. 2010. “Explaining the Deterrence Effect of Human Rights Prosecutions for Transitional Countries.” International Studies Quarterly 54(4):939963.Google Scholar
Krain, Matthew. 2005. “International Intervention and the Severity of Genocides and Politicides.” International Studies Quarterly 49(3):363388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2010. “The Responsibility Dilemma for Killing in War: A Review Essay.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 38(2):180213.Google Scholar
Luban, David. 1980a.Just War and Human Rights.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9(2):160181.Google Scholar
Luban, David 1980b.The Romance of the Nation-State.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9(4):392397.Google Scholar
Lucas, George Jr. 2003. “From Jus Ad Bellum to Jus Ad Pacem: Re-thinking Just War Criteria for the Use of Military Force for Humanitarian Ends.” In Ethics and Foreign Intervention, edited by Deen Chatterjee and Don Scheid, 72–96, Chapter 5. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1513. The Prince, 1st ed. New York: Everyman's Library.Google Scholar
Mapel, David R. 1998. “Coerced Moral Agents? Individual Responsibility for Military Service.” Journal of Political Philosophy 6(2):171189.Google Scholar
Mapel, David R. 2010. “Moral Liability to Defensive Killing and Symmetrical Self-defense.” Journal of Political Philosophy 18(2):198217.Google Scholar
May, Larry. 2008. “The Principle of Just Cause.” In War: Essays in Political Philosophy, edited by Larry May, 4966. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2005a.Just Cause for War.” Ethics & International Affairs 19(3):121.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2005b.The Basis of Moral Liability to Defensive Killing.” Philosophical Issues 15(1):386405.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2009. Killing in War, 1st ed. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2010. “Humanitarian Intervention, Consent, and Proportionality.” In Ethics and Humanity: Themes from the Philosophy of Jonathan Glover, edited by Ann Davis, Richard Keshen, and Jeff McMahan, 4472. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mellow, David. 2006. “Counterfactuals and the Proportionality Criterion.” Ethics & International Affairs 20(4):439454.Google Scholar
Melzer, Nils. 2008. Targeted Killing in International Law. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Meredith, Martin. 2005. The Fate of Africa: A History of Fifty Years of Independence. New York: Public Affairs.Google Scholar
More, Thomas. 1516. Utopia Translated by Paul Turner. 1st ed. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Murdie, AmandaDavis, David R.. 2010. “Problematic Potential: The Human Rights Consequences of Peacekeeping Interventions in Civil Wars.” Human Rights Quarterly 32(1):4972.Google Scholar
Nardin, Terry. 2006. “Introduction.” In Humanitarian Intervention: NOMOS XLVII, edited by Terry Nardin and Melissa S. Williams, 128. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Orend, Brian. 2002. “Justice after War.” Ethics & International Affairs 16(1):4356.Google Scholar
Otto, Roland. 2012. Targeted Killings and International Law with Special Regard to Human Rights and International Humanitarian Law. Berlin, New York: Springer, http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-24858-0.Google Scholar
Patterson, Eric. ed. 2012. Ethics Beyond War's End. USA: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Pattison, James. 2010a. Humanitarian Intervention and the Responsibility to Protect: Who Should Intervene?. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pattison, James 2010b.Outsourcing the Responsibility to Protect: Humanitarian Intervention and Private Military and Security Companies.” International Theory 2(1):131.Google Scholar
Peksen, Dursun. 2012. “Does Foreign Military Intervention Help Human Rights?Political Research Quarterly 65(3):558571.Google Scholar
Pierce, Albert C. 1996. “Just War Principles and Economic Sanctions.” Ethics & International Affairs 10:99113.Google Scholar
Pinker, Steven. 2011. The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined. New York, NY: Viking Adult.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2003. “Preempting Humanitarian Interventions.” In Humanitarian Intervention: Moral and Philosophical Issues, edited by Aleksandar Jokic, 93108. Peterborough: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
Power, Samantha. 2002. A Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Quong, Jonathan. 2012. “Liability to Defensive Harm.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 40(1):4577.Google Scholar
Raines, Joshua. 2002. “Osama, Augustine, and Assassination: The Just War Doctrine and Targeted Killings.” Transnational Law & Contemporary Problems 12:217.Google Scholar
Reitberger, Magnus. 2013. “License to Kill: Is Legitimate Authority a Requirement for Just War?International Theory 5(1):6493.Google Scholar
Rodin, David. 2002. War and Self-Defense. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rudoren, Jodi, Sanger, David E.. 2013. “Syria Has Used Chemical Arms Repeatedly, Israel Asserts” The New York Times, April 23, sec. World/Middle East. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/24/world/middleeast/israel-says-syria-has-used-chemical-weapons.htmlGoogle Scholar
Scheffer, David. 2010. “Aggression is Now a Crime.” The New York Times, July 1, sec. Opinion. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/07/02/opinion/02iht-edscheffer.htmlGoogle Scholar
Shane, Scott. 2013. “Debating a Court to Vet Drone Strikes.” The New York Times, February 8, sec. World. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/02/09/world/a-court-to-vet-kill-lists.html.Google Scholar
Statman, Daniel. 2003. “The Morality of Assassination: A Response to Gross.” Political Studies 51(4):775779.Google Scholar
Statman, Daniel 2011. “Can Wars Be Fought Justly? The Necessity Condition Put to the Test.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8(3):435451.Google Scholar
Statman, Daniel 2012. “Can Just War Theory Justify Targeted Killing? Three Possible Models.” In Targeted Killings: Law and Morality in an Asymmetrical World, edited by Claire Finkelstein, Jens David Ohlin, and Andrew Altman, 90111. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steinhoff, Uwe. 2009. “What Is War – And Can a Lone Individual Wage One?International Journal of Applied Philosophy 23(1):133150.Google Scholar
Tesón, Fernando. 2012. “Targeted Killings in War and Peace: A Philosophical Analysis.” In Targeted Killings: Law and Morality in an Asymmetrical World, edited by Claire Finkelstein, Jens David Ohlin, and Andrew Altman, 403433. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomas, Ward. 2000. “Norms and Security: The Case of International Assassination.” International Security 25(1):105133.Google Scholar
Thomas, Ward 2001. The Ethics of Destruction: Norms and Force in International Relations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1991. “Self-Defense.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 20(4):283310.Google Scholar
United Nations News Service. 2012. “Syrian Government and Opposition Forces Responsible for War Crimes.” UN News Service Section, August 15. http://www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=42687#.URbrouhZ_dAGoogle Scholar
Waal, Alex de. 1997. Famine Crimes: Politics & the Disaster Relief Industry in Africa. London: Indiana University Press and International African Institute.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael 1973. “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 2(2):160180.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael 1977. Just And Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations, 3rd ed. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael 1980. “The Moral Standing of States: A Response to Four Critics.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9(3):209229.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael 2007. “The Argument About Humanitarian Intervention.” In Thinking Politically: Essays in Political Theory, edited by David Miller, 237–250. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael 2013. “Targeted Killing and Drone Warfare.” Dissent Magazine, January 11, 2013. http://www.dissentmagazine.org/online_articles/targeted-killing-and-drone-warfareGoogle Scholar
Wellman, Christopher. 2012. “Debate: Taking Human Rights Seriously.” Journal of Political Philosophy 20(1):119130.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Nicholas J. 2000. Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society. USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Robert E.Caldwell, Dan. 2006. “Jus Post Bellum: Just War Theory and the Principles of Just Peace.” International Studies Perspectives 7(4):309320.Google Scholar