Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-pt5lt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-09T19:34:12.988Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hegel and Naturalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

Alexis Papazoglou*
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge, ajp83@cam.ac.uk
Get access

Abstract

In the recent Hegel literature there has been an effort to portray Hegel's philosophy as compatible with naturalism, or even as a form of naturalism (see for example Pippin 2008 and Pinkard 2012). Despite the attractions of such a project, there is, it seems to me, another, and potentially more interesting way of looking at the relationship of Hegel to naturalism. Instead of showing how Hegel's philosophy can be compatible with naturalism, I propose to show how Hegel's philosophy offers a challenge to naturalism. Naturalism has become the dominant ideology in much of contemporary analytic philosophy (Kim 2003: 84), but also within other disciplines. Evolutionary psychology and behavioral genetics, which attract a lot of media attention, attempt to explain the human mind and human behavior in purely naturalistic terms, usually in terms of the biological past and makeup of humans (Pinker 2002). Philosophy's task is, among other things, to examine the assumptions of human practices including its own. In that vein I am interested in showing how Hegel can be seen as someone offering a challenge to our contemporary philosophical culture and its underlying naturalist premise.

Of course that Hegel never explicitly talks about naturalism in his writings already presents us with the problem of risking anachronism. The other great problem is the fact that naturalism is an elusive philosophical position. There are a few different versions of the key theses of naturalism, so that if our aim is to diagnose Hegel's philosophy as naturalist or anti-naturalist it would seem we have to pick which version of naturalism we are going to work with.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arie, A. (2008) ‘Teleology’, in Hull, David L. and Ruse, Michael (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beiser, F. (2005), Hegel, New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Caro, M., Macarthur, D. (2004), “Introduction: The Nature of Naturalism” in De Caro, Mario and Macarthur, David (eds.), Naturalism in Question. Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press Google Scholar
Ferrarin, A. (2001), Hegel and Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrini, C. (2007), ‘Hegel's Confrontation With The Sciences In ‘Observing Reason’: Notes For A Discussion’, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, vol. 55/56:127.Google Scholar
Fink, H. (2008), ‘Three Sorts of Naturalism’, in Lindgaard, Jakob (ed.), John McDowell: Experience, Norm and Nature. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gubeljic, M., Link, S., Muller, P. and Osburg, G. (1999), ‘Nature and Second Nature in McDowell's Mind and World’ in Willaschek, Marcus (eds.) John McDowell: Reason and Nature, Lecture and Colloquium in Münster. Münster: LIT – Verlag.Google Scholar
Halbig, C. (2008), ‘Varieties of Nature in Hegel and McDowell’ in Lindgaard, Jakob (ed), John McDowell: Experience, Norm and Nature. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1969), Science of Logic, trans. Miller, A.V.. Amherst, New York: Humanity Books.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1970), Philosophy of Nature: Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. Miller, A.V. from Nicolin, and Poggeler's, edition (1959) and from the Zusatze in Michelet's text (1847). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1971), Philosophy of Mind: Part Three of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. Wallace, William, together with the Zusatze in Boumann's text (1845), trans. Miller, A.V.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1974), Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume I, trans. Haldane, E.S., Simson, F. H. (ed). New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1977 A), Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Miller, A.V.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. (1977 B), The Difference between Fichte's and Schelling's System of Philosophy, trans. Cerfand, W. and Harris, H.S., Albany: State University of New York.Google Scholar
Kreines, J. (2004), ‘Hegel's Critique of Pure Mechansim and the Philosophical Appeal of the Logic Project’, European Journal of Philosophy 12 (1): 38–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macarthur, D. and DeCaro, M. (2010), ‘Introduction: Science, Naturalism and the Problem of Normativity’ in DeCaro, M and Macarthur, D (eds.), Naturalism and Normativity. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Macdonald, G. (2006), ‘The Two Natures: Another Dogma?’ in Macdonald, Cynthia and Macdonald, Graham (eds.), McDowell and his Critiques. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1996), Mind and World. Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1998), ‘Two Sorts of Naturalism’ in Mind, Value and Reality. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1999), ‘Responses’ in Willaschek, Marcus (ed.) John McDowell: Reason and Nature, Lecture and Colloquium in Münster. Munster: LIT Verlag.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2006), ‘Response to Graham Macdonald’, Macdonald, Cynthia and Macdonald, Graham (eds.), McDowell and his Critiques. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (2009), ‘Naturalism’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.),Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2005), ‘Speculative Naturphilosophie and the Development of the Empirical Sciences: Hegel's Perspective.’ In Gutting, Gary (ed.), Continental Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2012), Hegel's Naturalism: Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S. (2002), The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2008), Hegel's Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency as Ethical Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato, (1997), ‘Phaedo’. Grube, G.M.A. (trans.), in Cooper, J.M. (ed.), Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett.Google Scholar
Price, H. (2011), Naturalism Without Mirrors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (2007), ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’ in Sharp, Kevin and Brandom, Robert (eds.), In the Space of reasons: Selected Essays of Wilfrid Sellars. Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Stone, A. (2005), Petrified Intelligence: Nature in Hegel's Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C. (1975), Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Testa, I. (2010), ‘The Universal Form of Spirit: Hegel on Habit and Sociality’ in Arndt, Andreas, Cruysberghs, Paul and Przylebski, Andrzej (eds.) Hegel-Jahrbuch 2010: Geist? Erster Teil. Berlin: Academie Verlag.Google Scholar