Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4rdrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T12:42:52.157Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Human Rights Act: Ambiguity about Parliamentary Sovereignty

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The United Kingdom has long resisted the idea of adopting a judicially reviewable bill of rights, which historically has been considered inconsistent with a core constitutional principle of parliamentary sovereignty. When adopting the Human Rights Act (HRA), the political framers insisted on preserving Parliament's final say on the legality of legislation.

The decision to authorize judicial review, while also constraining the scope of judicial remedies by withholding a power to invalidate inconsistent legislation, has introduced serious ambiguity about the function of the HRA and also about where political legitimacy resides for resolving institutional disagreements about how rights appropriately guide or constrain legislation. The first example of ambiguity is with respect to how institutional actors understand the principal function of the HRA. For example, does rights protection occur primarily through judicial review, either by authorizing the judiciary to engage in interpretive techniques that force legislative compliance, or by identifying rights constraints that parliament is expected to address by enacting remedial measures? Or instead does rights protection occur via altered political practices: by engaging bureaucrats, the executive, and Parliament in a more conscious role of identifying how rights are implicated in proposed legislation, increasing intra-institutional deliberation about justification, and facilitating pressure to implement rights-inspired amendments? The second example of ambiguity occurs with respect to political actors' responsibilities in circumstances where courts disagree that legislation complies with protected rights, as judicially interpreted. Specifically, how does the principle of parliamentary sovereignty relate to the mission of a recently adopted bill of rights? Notwithstanding formal constraints on judicial power, can Parliament's contrary judgment be considered a compelling interpretation of rights and, if so, under what circumstances and according to what criteria?

This paper explores this ambiguity in the context of debate about disenfranchising prisoners.

The United Kingdom has long considered a bill of rights as both unnecessary and inconsistent with the constitutional principle of parliamentary sovereignty. This view of inconsistency arose from the assumption that an effective bill of rights requires a judicial remedial capacity to set aside inconsistent legislation, and thus this judicial power contradicts the idea that parliament has the final say on the legality of duly enacted legislation. Yet a political willingness to experiment with where responsibility resides for remedial action helped overcome reticence to adopt a bill of rights. The HRA came into effect in 2000 and incorporates the European Convention of Human Rights into domestic law. Yet the HRA differs significantly from conventional assumptions about how a bill of rights functions. Instead of conceiving of rights protection in a court-centric manner, as occurring through binding judicial remedies to redress rights infringements that have already occurred, the HRA instead represents a more politically-oriented bill of rights. Such a politically-oriented bill of rights embodies the optimistic ideals of facilitating proactive rights protection through more rights-oriented legislative processes and relying on political willingness to enact remedies if the judiciary subsequently disagrees that legislation is consistent with Convention rights.

The HRA represents an ambitious model for rights protection that envisages rights-based scrutiny occurring at four institutional stages, three of which are oriented around the legislative process. The first of these four stages, pre-legislative review, arises from a new ministerial reporting requirement in section 19 to alert Parliament that a legislative bill is either compatible with Convention rights or that the minister is unable to claim compatibility. This reporting obligation has precipitated regular assessments by government lawyers and relevant policy officials of whether legislative initiatives are consistent with Convention rights before these become legislative bills. The second stage, parliamentary rights review, is facilitated by the creation of a specialized parliamentary rights committee—the Joint Committee on Human Rights—to review legislation from a rights perspective, which provides Parliament regular and often critical reports on the persuasiveness of the minister's earlier claim that a bill is consistent with the Convention rights. Judicial review, the third stage, occurs as a result of a new authority for judges to consider whether legislation is consistent with Convention rights. If judges determine that legislation is inconsistent with Convention rights, judicial censure can take an interpretive form under section 3 of the HRA, by altering the scope or effects of legislation through a judicial interpretation that strives to render legislation compatible with Convention rights, or it can take a more explicit form by declaring that the legislation is not compatible with Convention rights under section 4 of the HRA. The fourth stage arises from a legislative process for implementing remedial legislation in section 10 and reflects the political framers' expectations that Parliament will regularly comply with domestic and European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) rulings of incompatibility.

Yet this highly idealized model of rights protection reflects deep and unresolved ambiguity about the nature of parliament's responsibility to pass remedial measures. This ambiguity is a direct consequence of a political attempt to construct a rights project that emphasizes a juridical approach for interpreting liberal constitutional values and yet also relies on political willingness to enact remedies. The significance of this ambiguity is intensified by the rhetorical dissonance between the claim that a strong expectation of compliance with British and ECtHR rulings exists and the very different claim that parliamentary sovereignty protects parliament's capacity to have the final say on all judgments including those involving rights.

The seriousness of this ambiguity is particularly clear in political responses to judicial rulings that the UK's comprehensive ban on prisoners' voting is inconsistent with ECtHR rulings. The paper examines political reactions to ECtHR rulings on prisoner voting in Part One. Part Two draws on the work of Jeremy Waldron to suggest the benefit of Parliament developing processes or criteria to revisit judicially-impugned legislation in order to reassess the merits of its earlier judgment and/or the justification of political reticence to implement remedial measures. Although some might interpret this argument that Parliament should reassess the justification of legislation from a rights perspective as being in serious tension with ideas associated with political constitutionalism, the author rejects this interpretation. This perception is only valid if the argument for re-evaluation is predicated on the idea that courts alone are capable of, or have legitimacy for, judgments about rights. If one rejects a court-centric position on this issue, as does the author, and yet also takes seriously the idea that a polity's fundamental rights should be respected, it is incumbent upon Parliament to find a way to critically assess and distinguish when its dissenting judgment is justified as a reasonable response to legitimate rights-based concerns, from when Parliament's dissenting opinion can only be explained as an assertion of political and constitutional power.

Type
Part II: The Relationship Between the Courts and Political Institutions
Copyright
Copyright © 2013 by German Law Journal GbR

Footnotes

*

Professor of Political Science, Queen's University, janet.hiebert@queensu.ca. This paper was developed for the workshop “Political Constitutions” held in June 2012 at Caledonian University in London. I would like to thank Christopher McCorkindale and Marco Goldoni for their efforts arranging and organizing such a rich and stimulating event, and acknowledge the lively interventions from workshop participants, from which my paper benefitted. I would also like to acknowledge financial assistance in the form of a grant from the Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada. Finally, I would like to thank Danny Nicol for his critical observations and helpful suggestions. Copyright © German Law Journal, Janet L. Hiebert, 2013.

References

1 Department for Constitutional Affairs, Voting Rights of Convicted Prisoners Detained within the United Kingdom, 2006, CP29/06 (U.K.).Google Scholar

2 White, Isobel, U.K. House of Commons Library, Prisoners’ Voting Rights, 2011, SN/PC/01764.Google Scholar

3 Hirst v. Attorney General, [2001] EWHC (Admin) 239.Google Scholar

4 Department for Constitutional Affairs, supra note 1.Google Scholar

5 Hirst v. United Kingdom (No. 2), ECHR App. No. 74025/01, para. 52 (Mar. 30, 2004), http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/.Google Scholar

6 Id. at para. 85.Google Scholar

7 See id. at para. 82.Google Scholar

8 Id. at para 79.Google Scholar

9 William Smith (AP) v. KD Scott Electoral Registration Officer, [2007] CSIH 9 (Scot.).Google Scholar

10 Mark Harper, House of Commons Debates, Feb. 4, 2011, col 99.Google Scholar

11 See Joint Committee on Human Rights (JCHR), Legislative Scrutiny: Fifth Progress Report, 2005–06, H.L. 115, H.C. 899; JCHR, Implementation of Strasbourg Judgments: First Progress Report, 2005–06, H.L. 133, H.C. 954; JCHR, Monitoring the Government's Response to Court Judgments Finding Breaches of Human Rights, 2006–07, H.L. 128, H.C. 728; JCHR, Monitoring the Government's Response to Human Rights Judgments: Annual Report 2008, 2007–08, H.L. 173, H.C. 1078 [hereinafter JCHR 2008 Annual Report]; JCHR, Legislative Scrutiny: Political Parties and Elections Bill, 2008–09, H.L. 23, H.C. 204 [hereinafter JCHR 2008 Legislative Scrutiny Report]; JCHR, Government replies to the Second, Fourth, Eighth, Ninth and Twelfth Reports of Session 2008–09, 2008–09, H.L. 104, H.C. 592; JCHR, Enhancing Parliament's Role in Relation to Human Rights Judgments, 2009–10, H.L. 85, H.C. 455; JCHR, Legislative Scrutiny: (1) Superannuation Bill; (2) Parliamentary Voting System and Constituencies Bill, 2010–11, H.L. 64, H.C. 640.Google Scholar

12 Department for Constitutional Affairs, supra note 1, at 11.Google Scholar

13 Ministry of Justice, Voting Rights of Convicted Prisoners Detained within the United Kingdom: Second Stage Consultation, 2009, CP6/09 (U.K.).Google Scholar

14 See JCHR 2008 Annual Report, supra note 11, at para. 63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Some Inmates to Get Voting Rights, BBC News, Apr. 9, 2009, http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/uk_news/politics/7992045.stm.Google Scholar

16 Winnett, Robert & Whitehead, Tom, Prisoners to Get Right to Vote after 140 Years Following European Ruling, The Telegraph, Apr. 9, 2009, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/law-and-order/5126647/Prisoners-to-get-right-to-vote-after-140-years-following-European-ruling.html.Google Scholar

17 Most Britons Believe Prisoners Should Not Vote in Elections, Angus Reid Public Opinion, Nov. 22, 2010, http://www.angus-reid.com/wp-content/uploads/2010/11/2010.11.22_Prisoner_BRI.pdf.Google Scholar

18 See JCHR 2008 Legislative Scrutiny Report supra note 11, at para. 1.13.Google Scholar

19 Committee of Ministers Interim Resolution (EC) No. CM/ResDH(2009)160 of Dec. 3, 2009, https://wcd.coe.int/wcd/ViewDoc.jsp?id=1556821&Site=CM.Google Scholar

20 Chair of the Comm. of Ministers to the Parliamentary Assembly (EC), Communication on the Activities of the Committee of Ministers, ¶ 16, CM/AS(2010)7rev (Oct. 4, 2010), https://wcd.coe.int/wcd/ViewDoc.jsp?id=1678647&Site=CM&BackColorInternet=C3C3C3&BackColorIntranet=ED B021&BackColorLogged=F5D383.Google Scholar

21 Doward, Jamie, Europe Pressures Westminster on Votes for Prisoners, The Guardian, May 29, 2010, http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2010/may/30/europe-pressure-westminster-prisoners-vote.Google Scholar

22 Greens & M.T. v. United Kingdom, ECHR App. Nos. 60041/08 & 60054/08, para. 115, 120 (Nov. 23, 2010), http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/.Google Scholar

23 Id. at para. 101.Google Scholar

24 Porter, Andrew, Prisoners to Get the Vote for the First Time, The Telegraph, Nov. 1, 2010, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/law-and-order/8103580/Prisoners-to-get-the-vote-for-the-first-time.html.Google Scholar

25 517, Parl. Deb., H.C. (6th ser.) (2010) 771–72 (U.K.).Google Scholar

26 Prison Votes ‘Will be Kept to a Minimum', BBC News, Jan. 20, 2011, http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-12233938.Google Scholar

27 Porter, supra note 24.Google Scholar

28 Kirkup, James, 30,000 Prisoners Will be Able to Vote, The Telegraph, Jan. 6, 2011, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/law-and-order/8241920/30000-prisoners-will-be-able-to-vote.html.Google Scholar

29 Prison Votes ‘Will be Kept to a Minimum', supra note 26.Google Scholar

31 523 Parl. Deb., H.C. (6th ser.) (2011) 493 (U.K.).Google Scholar

32 Id. The full wording of the motion was: “That this House notes the ruling of the European Court of Human Rights in Hirst v. United Kingdom in which it held that there had been no substantive debate by members of the legislature on the continued justification for maintaining a general restriction on the right of prisoners to vote; acknowledges the treaty obligations of the UK; is of the opinion that legislative decisions should be a matter for democratically elected lawmakers; and supports the current situation in which no prisoner is able to vote except those imprisoned for contempt, default or on remand.”Google Scholar

33 Nicol, Danny, Legitimacy of the Commons Debate on Prisoner Voting, P.L. 681, 683 (2011).Google Scholar

34 Political and Constitutional Reform Committee, Prisoner Voting: Uncorrected Transcript of Oral Evidence, 2010–11, H.C. 776 (U.K.).Google Scholar

35 Hélène Mulholland & Wintour, Patrick, UK will not Defy European Court on Prisoners’ Votes, Says Kenneth Clarke, The Guardian, Feb. 9, 2011, http://www.guardian.co.uk/politics/2011/feb/09/government-defy-european-court-vote-prisoners.Google Scholar

36 No Votes for Jailed Murderers and Rapists—Ken Clarke, BBC News, Feb. 9, 2011, http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-12402704?.Google Scholar

37 Miller, Vaughne, U.K. House of Commons Library, European Court of Human Rights Rulings: Are There Options for Governments?, 2011, SN/IA/5941, at 12.Google Scholar

38 Raab, Dominic, What Happens if We Defy Europe? Nothing, The Telegraph, Feb. 2, 2011, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/politics/8299615/What-happens-if-we-defy-Europe-Nothing.html.Google Scholar

39 Shipman, Tim, Cameron CAN Defy Euro Court Diktats: UK ‘May Deny Votes for Inmates Without Penalty', Daily Mail Online, Feb. 18, 2011, http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-1358199/Cameron-CAN-defy-Euro-court-diktats-UK-deny-votes-inmates-penalty.html.Google Scholar

40 See Coates, Sam, Cameron is Clear to Defy Europe on Human Rights, The Times, Feb. 18 2011, at 1, 9.Google Scholar

41 Miller, supra note 37, at 5.Google Scholar

42 Coates, supra note 40.Google Scholar

43 Tovey and Hydes v. Ministry of Justice, [2011] EWHC (QB) 271, [64] (Eng.).Google Scholar

44 Eur. Consult. Ass., Communication from the Government in the Case of Hirst No. 2 Against the United Kingdom, 1108th Meeting, App. No. 74025/01 (Mar. 1, 2011), available at https://wcd.coe.int/ViewDoc.jsp?id=1753877&Site=CM.Google Scholar

45 Press Release, Eur. Court of Human Rights, Court's Judgment Concerning Blanket Ban on Prisoner Voting in the U.K. Becomes Final (April 12, 2011), available at http://adam1cor.files.wordpress.com/2011/04/referral-to-grand-chamber-rejected-greens-and-m-t-v-the-united-kingdom-12-04-11-2.pdf.Google Scholar

46 Mason, Rowena, Government Tells European Judges No Right to Meddle with UK Prisoner Vote Policy, The Telegraph, Nov. 2, 2011, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/8865204/Government-tells-European-judges-no-right-to-meddle-with-UK-prisoner-vote-policy.html.Google Scholar

47 See Scoppola v. Italy (No. 3), ECHR App. No. 126/05, 868 Eur. Ct. H.R. 23 (2012).Google Scholar

48 See Mason, Rowena & Whitehead, Tom, David Cameron: Britain Will Decide on Votes for Prisoners Not a “Foreign Court,” The Telegraph, May 23, 2012, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/politics/9284892/David-Cameron-Britain-will-decide-on-votes-for-prisoners-not-a-foreign-court.html.Google Scholar

49 PA, David Cameron to Fight Prisoner Voting Plan, The Independent, May 23, 2012, http://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/politics/david-cameron-to-fight-prison-voting-plan-7781521.htm.Google Scholar

50 House of Lords Reform Bill, 2012–13, H.C. Bill [52] explanatory notes.Google Scholar

51 Wintour, Patrick & Sparrow, Andrew, I Won't Give Prisoners the Vote, Says David Cameron, The Guardian, Oct. 24, 2012, http://www.guardian.co.uk/society/2012/oct/24/prisoners-vote-david-cameron.Google Scholar

52 Mason, & Whitehead, , supra note 48, at 3–4.Google Scholar

53 The Voting Eligibility (Prisoners) Draft Bill, 2012–13, CM 8499 (Gr. Brit.).Google Scholar

54 See Helen Fenwick, Civil Liberties and Human Rights 61–162 (4th ed. 2007).Google Scholar

55 See Alison L Young, Parliamentary Sovereignty and the Human Rights Act (2009).Google Scholar

56 Hunt, Murray, Reshaping Constitutionalism, in Judges, Transition, and Human Rights 467, 468–69 (John Morison et al. eds., 2007).Google Scholar

57 Id. at 470.Google Scholar

59 Nicol, supra note 33, at 681–87.Google Scholar

60 See 523 Parl. Deb., H.C. (6th ser.) (2011) 531 (U.K.).Google Scholar

61 Waldron, Jeremy, Compared to What? Judicial Activism and New Zealand's Parliament, N.Z. L.J., 441, 442 (2005).Google Scholar

62 Waldron, Jeremy, Uncorrected Transcript of Oral Evidence Taken Before Joint Committee on Human Rights, Human Rights Judgments 39, 50 (2011) (to be published at H.C. 873-i), available at http://www.parliament.uk/documents/joint-committees/human-rights/HumanRightsJudgments/Transcript150311.pdf.Google Scholar

63 Id. at 47–48.Google Scholar

64 Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement 252 (1999) (emphasis in original).Google Scholar

65 Id. at 254.Google Scholar

66 Id. at 254.Google Scholar

67 Id. at 232. Waldron borrows the phrase “right of rights” from a much earlier discussion by William Cobbett, Advice to Young Men and (incidentally) to Young Women, in the Middle and Higher Ranks of Life: In a Series of Letters, Addressed to a Youth, a Bachelor, a Lover, a Husband, a Father, a Citizen or a Subject (1829).Google Scholar

68 See Waldron, supra note 61, at 49–50.Google Scholar

70 See, e.g., Tom Ginsburg, Judicial Review In New Democracies: Constitutional Courts In Asian Cases (2003); Ran Hirschl, Towards Juristocracy: The Origins And Consequences of the New Constitutionalism (2004).Google Scholar

71 Waldron, supra note 61, at 41.Google Scholar

72 Id. at 45.Google Scholar

73 Id. at 43–45.Google Scholar

74 See, e.g., Christopher P. Manfredi, Judicial Power and the Charter: Canada and the Paradox of Liberal Constitutionalism 181–95 (2000); Janet L. Hiebert, Wrestling with Rights: Judges, Parliament and the Making of Social Policy 30–31 (1999).Google Scholar