Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T18:12:03.371Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Note on the Epistemological Value of Pretense Imagination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2021

Tom Schoonen*
Affiliation:
Institute for Logic, Language, and Computation, the Netherlands and Arché, University of St Andrews, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Pretense imagination is imagination understood as the ability to recreate rational belief revision. This kind of imagination is used in pretend-play, risk-assessment, etc. Some even claim that this kind of hypothetical belief revision can be grounds to justify new beliefs in conditionals, in particular conditionals that play a foundational role in the epistemology of modality. In this paper, I will argue that it cannot. I will first provide a very general theory of pretense imagination, which I formalise using tools from dynamic epistemic logic. As a result, we can clearly see that pretense imagination episodes are build up out of two kinds of imaginative stages, so I will present an argument by cases. This argument shows that pretense imagination might indeed provide us with justification for believing certain conditionals. Despite this, I will argue that these are not the kind of conditionals that allow pretense imagination to play a foundational role in the epistemology of modality.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Evaluating non-actual possibilities is crucial for our decision making and general survival when going around the world (Byrne Reference Byrne2005). It is an interesting and pressing question how we come to know whether such non-actual possibilities are true. Many have suggested that imagination plays a crucial role here (e.g., Byrne Reference Byrne2005; Williamson Reference Williamson2007, Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016; Kind and Kung Reference Kind and Kung2016). The question thus arises, under what conditions can imagination justify beliefs in non-actual possibilities? These kinds of questions are at the centre of recent debates in the epistemology of imagination. One thing that most agree on is that in order for imagination to be epistemically useful in this way, it has to be restricted (cf. Kind Reference Kind, Kind and Kung2016; Kind and Kung Reference Kind and Kung2016; Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016).Footnote 1 However, it also has been argued that not all kinds of restrictions work (Balcerak Jackson Reference Balcerak Jackson, Macpherson and Dorsch2018). In order for imagination to be epistemically useful, the restrictions should (i) not be ‘up to us’ and (ii) not rely on prior justifications that beg the question. One account of imagination that seems to be inherently restricted in the right way is imagination as recreation: imagination understood as the ‘off-line counterpart’ of certain cognitive functions (cf. Goldman Reference Goldman and Nichols2006).

In this paper, I will evaluate the claim that imagination understood as a recreative capacity can provide us with justification for beliefs in non-actual possibilities. In particular, I argue that imagination, understood as the recreation of rational belief revision, cannot do so. I provide a general account of such imagination and formalise this in order to carefully evaluate the claim that this kind of imagination can be epistemically useful.Footnote 2

1. Epistemology of imagination

Intuitively, imagination can be a guide to what is possible. When deciding to move a heavy couch through the door, we might first imagine how to rotate the couch in order to get it through, before coming to believe that it possibly fits. Similarly, when giving feedback to colleagues, I might imagine how my comments would affect their feelings. However, this seems to clash with another intuitive feature of imagination: it is both under our voluntary control and not restricted by what is actually the case. So, how can it be that if we decide what to imagine, that we gain justification from it?

One way out of this problem, researchers agree, is to restrict imagination (cf. Kind Reference Kind, Kind and Kung2016; Kind and Kung Reference Kind and Kung2016; Balcerak Jackson Reference Balcerak Jackson, Macpherson and Dorsch2018). The rough idea is that when we are concerned with epistemically useful imagination (in the sense that it is a guide to what is possible), we focus on the restricted instances, whereas when we want to account for our ability to imagine impossibilities, we consider the unrestricted instances.

Recently, Balcerak Jackson (Reference Balcerak Jackson, Macpherson and Dorsch2018) has forcefully argued that we should focus on a recreativist account of imagination in order to explain the justification we get from imagination.Footnote 3 Imagination, on such a recreativist account, “is a matter of creating or trying to create in one's own mind a selected mental state, or at least a rough facsimile of such a state” (Goldman Reference Goldman and Nichols2006: 42). That is, imagination simulates the having of mental states without the, otherwise needed, external input or stimuli. This means that imagination is inherently restricted by whatever (neuro)physiological (or other) restrictions constrain the ‘online’ cognitive faculty that imagination is recreating.

In this paper, I focus on one particular kind of recreativist account of imagination, namely imagination as the recreation of rational belief revision. This is the kind of imagination that we use when we engage with pretense (e.g., Leslie Reference Leslie1994; Nichols and Stich Reference Nichols and Stich2003; Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan2012), but also when we engage in planning and risk assessment (e.g., Byrne Reference Byrne2005). Call it pretense imagination.

In what follows, I will first spell out what I take pretense imagination to be (section 2), after which I will present a formal account of it in section 3. This is all meant to give a very general, yet precise account of pretense imagination that we can evaluate for its epistemological merits. As it has been argued recently that one can present an epistemology of modality based on imagination's ability to justify our beliefs in certain conditionals, I will evaluate the claim that this kind of imagination can justify our beliefs in conditionals throughout sections 4–6. Even though pretense imagination can justify our beliefs in certain conditions, I argue in section 7 that it cannot play a foundational role in the epistemology of possibility.

2. Pretense imagination

Consider the following famous example of a pretense tea-party:

The child is encouraged to ‘fill’ two toy cups with ‘juice’ or ‘tea’ or whatever the child designated the pretend contents of the bottle to be. The experimenter then says, ‘Watch this!’, picks up one of the cups, turns it upside down, shakes it for a second, then replaces it alongside the other cup. The child is then asked to point at the ‘full cup’ and at the ‘empty cup’ (both cups are, of course, really empty throughout). (Leslie Reference Leslie1994: 223)

Children from a very young age already consistently point to the cup that has been turned upside down when asked to point at the ‘empty cup’ (cf. Leslie Reference Leslie1994; Nichols and Stich Reference Nichols and Stich2003). This indicates that children are able to engage in pretense even if it goes against what they believe the world to actually be like. Yet, they imagine this non-actual scenario in a reality-oriented way. For example, when asked, in the pretense, where there is a puddle of tea after a full cup is held upside-down, we take it to be odd if the subject answers ‘the ceiling’, whereas it seems very natural to answer that there is a puddle on the floor.

This example illustrates that pretense imagination is restricted in important ways by belief: pretense imagination seems to follow belief-like patterns, which explains the rational, reality-oriented behaviour with respect to which cups are full, and background beliefs seem to be imported into the imaginative episode, which explains the beliefs about the workings of gravity in the pretense.Footnote 4 Let's elaborate on both these relations between pretense and belief in turn.

The most prominent theories of pretense – e.g., that of Nichols and Stich (Reference Nichols and Stich2003) and Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan2012) – suggest that pretense reasoning is a cognitive capacity closely related to rational belief revisions. To capture this in our formalisation, we focus on belief and belief revision, where the latter is of hypothetical nature hinting at real belief changes were the pretend scenario to be actual. In this sense, it is sufficient to use models and operators that describe a situation where the objective facts of the world do not change, but only the belief state of the imagining agent changes. This belief revision process follows, roughly, Ramsey's (Reference Ramsey and Braithwaite1929 [2013]) famous pattern:

First, add the antecedent (hypothetically) to your stock of beliefs; second, make whatever adjustments are required to maintain consistency (without modifying the hypothetical belief in the antecedent).

(Stalnaker Reference Stalnaker, Harper, Stalnaker and Pearce1968: 44)

Another important factor that restricts pretense imagination is the agent's background beliefs about the actual world. Or, as Williamson notes, “[o]ne's imagination should not be completely independent of one's knowledge of what the world is like” (Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016: 114). For example, in the above pretense scenario, the subjects continue the pretense with the imagining that tea falls downwards as opposed to upwards because they import their background beliefs about gravitational forces – that unsupported objects fall towards the centre of the Earth – into the pretense.

In section 3, we will resort to the rich literature in (dynamic) epistemic logic and belief revision theory to model these features.

2.1. Pretense imagination: a theory

The imagination involved in pretense is strictly propositional imagination. That is, imagining that such and so is the case (Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) – e.g., I imagine that there is a tiger behind the curtain. This is opposed to, e.g., sensory imagination or objectual imagination (Balcerak Jackson Reference Balcerak Jackson, Macpherson and Dorsch2018) – e.g., I imagine what it is like to see a tiger or I imagine a tiger.Footnote 5 In pretense, e.g., in the tea-party example, the entire episode is made up out of a number of (temporally) shorter instances: the pretending that the tea is being poured, that the tea falls towards the ground. These are all ‘part’ of the entire tea-party pretense. It seems obvious that some of these are explicitly ‘intended’ by the agent, while others, e.g., the tea falling to the floor after the cup being held upside-down, develop without any intentions from the agent. Also, it seems that pretense is full of choices from the agents that might go beyond what usually happens at a tea-party; the agent might, for example, say: ‘Oh, a butler comes in to join the party’. I discuss these features in turn.Footnote 6

2.1.1. Explicit input

Let's consider an imaginative episode – e.g., the pretend tea-party – as a sequence of individual imaginative stages – e.g., that the tea is poured; that the cup is kept upside down; etc.Footnote 7 Such an imaginative episode always starts with a particular input. Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) argues that imaginative episodes start with an intention of the agent. The intention provides the proposition that starts the imaginative episode. This is the proposition that makes up the first stage in the sequence of imaginative stages. As Langland-Hassan puts it, “our intentions may be relevant in initiating an imagining” (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 65, emphasis added).Footnote 8

2.1.2. Internal development

Given an explicit input, the imaginative episode develops. As Langland-Hassan puts it: “imagination … has its own norms, logic, or algorithm that shapes the sequence of ix after the initiation of an imagining by a top-down intention” (Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 67). In the case of pretense, the development of this kind of imagination seems to follow a pattern that is very similar to that of rational belief revision. The development of the imaginative episode is governed by the very same mechanisms that guide the inferences we make in rational belief updates (cf. Byrne Reference Byrne2005; Nichols Reference Nichols2006; Williamson Reference Williamson2007; Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016; Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016). For example, Langland-Hassan notes that the things that “govern how [an imaginative episode] then unfolds” are the “inference mechanisms [that] are the same ones that shape and govern the inferences we draw within our ordinary beliefs” (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 67–8). I call this kind of development the internal development of the imaginative episode. In terms of the tea-party example, this development makes the agent automatically imagine that the tea falls towards the ground when the cup is turned upside down. For when an agent revises their pretense-beliefs with ‘the cup is turned upside down’, they would come to believe that its contents will fall downwards.

Relying on the inference mechanisms that we use for our ordinary belief updates nicely allows us to explain some of the features relating to the reality-oriented development of imagination (cf. Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016, Reference Williamson2020). Moreover, the involuntariness of this step explains the non-arbitrary nature of imagination: we are not free to imagine whatever we want given a certain input, which is supposed to render such mental exercises cognitively valuable (cf. Byrne Reference Byrne2005; Kind Reference Kind, Kind and Kung2016; Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016; Balcerak Jackson Reference Balcerak Jackson, Macpherson and Dorsch2018).

2.1.3. Cyclical interventions

Imagination, it is thought, is likely to have evolved in order to test a variety of actions to determine which one would be best to perform without having to actually perform the action and undergo all the risks that come with it (cf. Nichols Reference Nichols2006; Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016; Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016). Yet this feature of imagination requires something more than merely internal development. For, given an input p in a situation s, we would expect the outcome always to be the same with internal development, namely whatever the result of a rational belief revision with p in s is. This way, we can never test the variety of options given p in s through imagination.

One way to think about how these variations occur is that the agent actively intervenes into the imaginative episode. They forcefully add additional content and this content can go beyond what the agent otherwise would have imagined (in that it does not necessarily follow from the previous imaginative stage). So, when testing the variety of potential outcomes given p in s, the agent actively intervenes somewhere in the imaginative episode with additional contents (e.g., q 1, q 2, etc.). In Langland-Hassan's phrasing, imagination allows us to test a variety of actions “because we have intentionally intervened in that processing. To intentionally intervene is to stop the [internal development] where it is and to insert a new initial premise … into the [imaginative episode] for more processing” (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 74, emphasis added).Footnote 9

This framework describes the essential features of pretense imagination and captures all its relevant features: (i) it is a form of propositional (as opposed to objectual) imagination; (ii) imagination has an explicit starting point; (iii) imagination is independent of what one takes the world to be like; (iv) imagination develops as it would in normal belief revision from its starting point; and (v) imagination “is full of choices that are not dictated by the [explicit input]” (Nichols and Stich Reference Nichols and Stich2003: 35).

Next, I will provide a formal model of the development of such imagination over time, in order to then precisely and critically evaluate the claim (amongst others of Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016; Williamson Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016, Reference Williamson2020) that pretense imagination can provide us with justification for certain beliefs. Note that the model presented in the next section is a single agent model with certain idealisations, however, these idealisations are immaterial to our purposes.Footnote 10

3. Branching-time belief revision model

As imagination follows ‘belief-like’ inference patterns and develops in stages, we use a simplified version of branching-time belief revision models introduced by Bonanno (Reference Bonanno2007). These models “provide a way of modeling the evolution of an agent's beliefs over time in response to informational inputs” (Bonanno Reference Bonanno2012: 206).

Let Prop = {p 1, …, p n} be a finite set of propositional variables and ${\cal L}$ be the language of classical propositional logic defined on Prop. The language ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$ of the logic of belief and imagination is then defined by the grammar:

$$\varphi : = p\vert \neg \varphi \vert \varphi \wedge \varphi \vert B\psi \vert I\psi $$

where p ∈ Prop and $\psi \in {\cal L}$. Read ‘’ as ‘the agent believes that φ’ and ‘’ as ‘the agent imagines that φ’. It is important that we allow B and I to range only over Booleans. That is, our language ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$ of belief and imagination follows the cognitive science and philosophy literature on imagination in focusing on first-order attitudes (cf. Nichols and Stich Reference Nichols and Stich2003; Byrne Reference Byrne2005; Williamson Reference Williamson2007; Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan2012, Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016). We interpret this language on branching-time belief revision models:Footnote 11

Definition 1. Branching-time belief revision model

A branching-time belief revision model (in short, model) is a tuple ${\cal M}=\langle S\comma \;{\rm \rightarrowtail }\comma \;W\comma \;{\rm \preceq }\comma \;V\rangle $, where

  1. 1. $\lpar {S\comma \;{\rm \rightarrowtail }} \rpar $ is a rooted next-time branching frame;

  2. 2. W is a finite set of possible worlds or states;

  3. 3. ${\rm \preceq }\colon S\;\rightarrowtail W \times W$, is a function that assigns every stage in s ∈ S a total preorder on W, called the plausibility order at stage s and denoted by ${\rm \preceq }_s$;Footnote 12

  4. 4. V:Prop → ℘ (W), is a valuation function that maps every propositional variable in Prop to a set of possible worlds.

Since W is finite, every non-empty subset of W has a minimal element with respect to each ${\rm \preceq }_s$. The set of minimal elements, $Min_{{\rm \preceq }_s}\lpar U \rpar $, for any UW with respect to ${\rm \preceq }_s$, is defined as

$$Min_{{\rm \preceq }_s}\lpar U \rpar = \lcub {w\in U\colon w\;{\rm \preceq }_sv{\rm \;for\;all\;}v\in U} \rcub $$

So, for each s ∈ S, $\lpar {W\comma \;{\rm \preceq }_s\comma \;V} \rpar $ constitutes a standard plausibility model (cf. Baltag and Smets Reference Baltag, Smets, Bonanno, van der Hoek and Wooldridge2006; van Benthem Reference van Benthem2007), where the order, ${\rm \preceq }_s$, represents the arrangement of worlds to the degree that the agent considers them plausible at stage s (you can read $w\;{\rm \preceq }_sv$ as ‘w is at least as plausible as v at stage s’). This results in a model of the hypothetical beliefs of agents per stage of the branching model, where the stages change over time.

3.1. Histories, upgrades, and semantics

A branching-time belief revision model is intended to represent the evolution of an agent's belief and imagination over time, where imagination can be read off of the actual development of the pretense scenario. This is represented by a finite sequence of linear stages, called history, h (where ‘${\rm \rightarrowtail }$’ denotes the immediate successor relation):

$$h = \lpar s_0\comma \;s_1\comma \;\ldots \comma \;s_n\rpar \;{\rm such\ that}\;s_i {\rm \rightarrowtail } s_{i + 1}\comma \;$$

where s 0 is the root of the underlying next-time branching frame. Let's call s 0 the initial stage and sn the current stage. History h thus keeps track of the past stages, but does not tell us anything about the future. For an illustration of a branching-time belief revision model see Figure 1, where the nodes in the figure represent the stages of the imaginative episode with the plausibility ordering of that particular stage – i.e., ${\rm \preceq }_i$ represents the plausibility ordering at stage s i.

Fig. 1. A toy-example of a branching-time belief revision model: the nodes represent the stages of the imaginative episode with the plausibility ordering of that particular stage.

I suggest that the kind of hypothetical belief revision used by agents in pretense is a lexicographic upgrade, which allows us to explain some of the intuitive features of pretense imagination. This well-known lexicographic upgrade, for example with p, makes all p-worlds more plausible than all ¬p-worlds and keeps the ordering the same within those two zones (cf. van Benthem Reference van Benthem2007: 141).Footnote 13 This is the final auxiliary definition in order to define the semantics for ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$.

Definition 2. Upgraded preorder

Given a pre-ordered set $\langle W\comma \;{\rm \preceq }_s\rangle $ and PW, the upgraded pre-order by P is the tuple $\langle W\comma \;{\rm \preceq }_s^{\Uparrow P} \rangle $, where ${\rm \preceq }_s^{\Uparrow P} $ is the new ordering such that $w\;{\rm \preceq }_s^{\Uparrow P} v$ iff (1) $w\;{\rm \preceq }_sv$ and w ∈ P, or (2) $w\;{\rm \preceq }_sv$ and $v\in W\backslash P$, or (3) ($w\;{\rm \preceq }_sv$ or $v{\rm \preceq }_sw$) and w ∈ P and $v\in W\backslash P$.

In the semantics, formulas of ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$ are evaluated not only with respect to states, but with respect to state-history pairs of the form 〈w, h〉. The intension of φ with respect to h in ${\cal M}$ is $\vert \varphi \vert _{\cal M}^h : = \lcub w\in W\colon {\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle \,{\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\varphi \rcub $.

Definition 3. ${\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }$-Semantics for ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$

Given a model ${\cal M} = \langle S\comma \;{\rm \rightarrowtail }\comma \;W\comma \;{\rm \preceq }\comma \;V\rangle $ and a world-history pair 〈w, h〉 such that h = (s 0, s 1, ….s n), the semantics for ${\cal L}_{{\rm BI}}$ is defined recursively as follows:

$$\matrix{ {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }p} \hfill & {{\rm iff}} \hfill & {w\in V\lpar p\rpar } \hfill \cr {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\neg \varphi } \hfill & {{\rm iff}} \hfill & {{\rm not}\,{\cal M}{\rm \comma \;}\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\varphi } \hfill \cr {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\varphi \wedge \psi } \hfill & {{\rm iff}} \hfill & {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\varphi \,{\rm and}\,{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }\psi } \hfill \cr {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi } \hfill & {{\rm iff}} \hfill & {Min_{{\rm \preceq }_sn }\lpar W\rpar \subseteq \vert \varphi \vert _{\cal M}^h } \hfill \cr {{\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }I\varphi } \hfill & {{\rm iff}} \hfill & {\exists k \lt n\left({{\rm \preceq }_{s_{k + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_k}^\varphi {\rm and\ }{\cal M}{\rm \comma \;}\langle w\comma \;h\lsqb k + 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi } \right)} \hfill \cr } $$

Imagination, here, is dependent on both w and the whole history h. According to the proposed semantics, an agent imagines φ if they have revised their hypothetical belief state with φ at some stage in the history. In other words, we take what the agent imagines at the current stage to be the collection of propositions by which they have upgraded their pretend belief state at some stage before the current one. So, an appropriate reading of , then, is that “the agent has taken φ on board at some stage of the imaginative episode”. In this sense, the imagination operator I is a backward looking modality that keeps track of the informational input the agent uses through an imaginative episode. It is important to stress at this point that the belief modality represents the simulated or pretense beliefs of the agent, except when h = (s 0). The agent's actual beliefs are given by the plausibility model in the initial stage s 0.Footnote 14

So, how, if at all, does this model give a formal interpretation of the development of an imaginative episode? Given a history h = (s 0, …, s n) and k ≤ n, let h[k] = (s 0, s 1, …s k) be the initial segment of h of length k + 1. We then define the kth imaginative stage i k, the set of sentences the agent has imagined up to stage k, as

$$i_k = \lcub \varphi \in {\cal L}\colon \langle w\comma \;h[ k] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }I\varphi \rcub.$$

This way we extract the imaginative stages through the actual history and define the corresponding imaginative episode ${\cal I} = \lpar i_1\comma \;\ldots \comma \;i_n\rpar $ as a sequence of sets of sentences in ${\cal L}$. It is not difficult to see that $i_0 = \emptyset $. An imaginative episode starts with input propositions forming the first imaginative stage i 1. We can distinguish between stages that follow through internal development and stages that are added through intervention by introducing two distinct operators into our language: I and I . The former concerns internally developed stages and the latter concerns added content through intervention.Footnote 15 We interpret these two modalities as follows:

$$\matrix{ {\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }I_i\varphi } & {{\rm iff}} & {\exists k \lt n\lpar \lpar {\rm \preceq }_{s_{k + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_k}^\varphi \;{\rm and}\;\langle w\comma \;h[ k + 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi \rpar \;{\rm and}\;\langle w\comma \;h[ k] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi \rpar } \cr {\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }I_a\varphi } & {{\rm iff}} & {\exists k \lt n\lpar \lpar {\rm \preceq }_{s_{k + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_k}^\varphi \;{\rm and}\;\langle w\comma \;h[ k + 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi \rpar \;{\rm and}\;\langle w\comma \;h[ k] \rangle {{\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar\hskip-11pt / }}\,\,B\varphi \rpar } \cr } $$

Semantically, I iφ states that “the agent takes φ on board at some stage of the actual history where she already hypothetically believes it”. This is what we take internal development to be: the ordinary development of updating your hypothetical beliefs with what you find most plausible given a particular input. On the other hand, I aφ says that “the agent takes φ on board at some stage of the actual history and φ was not believed at that stage”. This implies that φ was imagined not as a result of the agent's belief revision process, but added “externally” to the imaginative episode.Footnote 16

4. Epistemology of pretense imagination

With this formal model of pretense imagination at hand, we now turn to the epistemology thereof. Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) and Williamson (Reference Williamson2007, Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016) both argue that pretense imagination might be central to conditional reasoning and the epistemology of conditionals. However, what we are interested in is the particular use of conditionals to gain knowledge of possibilities and whether pretense imagination plays a crucial role in the epistemology of these particular conditionals (Williamson Reference Williamson2007, Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016, Reference Williamson2020). So, we need to evaluate two claims: (i) can pretense imagination provide justification for believing conditionals and (ii) can pretense imagination, in virtue of (i), play a role in the epistemology of possibility?

The model presented in this paper allows us to very precisely evaluate these claims. We saw that imaginative episodes are sequences of imaginative stages; these stages are either explicitly intervened by the agent or developed through hypothetical belief revisions. So, we can evaluate the epistemic usefulness of pretense imagination through an argument by cases. First, I will argue that internally developed imagination cannot be used to gain justification for new beliefs in conditionals, after which I will argue that particular instances of intervened content do give rise to new beliefs in conditionals. Despite this, I will conclude by arguing that these conditionals (and thus pretense imagination) cannot explain our knowledge of non-actual possibilities.

4.1. Beliefs in conditionals and conditional beliefs

The first thing to stress is that I will focus on our beliefs in indicative conditionals (represented with ‘→’).Footnote 17 However, the logic discussed above does not involve an indicative conditional. In this subsection, I will first argue that we have in fact all we need to evaluate the epistemological question whether pretense imagination can provide us with justification for new beliefs in indicative conditionals.

A venerable tradition of how to determine whether we should believe a conditional has it that we should believe a conditional if we believe the consequent after having (hypothetically) revised our beliefs with the antecedent. This traces back to, at least, Ramsey, who suggested that if we are to determine ‘If φ, then ψ’ and we are uncertain about the antecedent, then we should add φ “hypothetically to [our] stock of knowledge” and then evaluate “on that basis” whether ψ (1929: 247, fn. 1). Stalnaker (Reference Stalnaker, Harper, Stalnaker and Pearce1968) and Williamson (Reference Williamson2007: Ch. 5, Reference Williamson2020: Ch. 2) also suggest epistemologies of conditionals in this vein.Footnote 18 If such theories are correct, then if the agent has a rational conditional belief, then they are equally in a position to justifiably believe the corresponding conditional.

Even though we do not have an indicative conditional in our semantics, we do have everything we need to define conditional beliefs in our model. Given Definitions 1 and 2, we can define conditional beliefs in our models as follows:

Definition 4. Conditional belief

$${\cal M},\langle w,h\rangle ||\joinrel\joinrel\relbar }B^\varphi \psi \;{\rm iff}\; Min\;{\rm \preceq }_{s_n}^\varphi (W)\subseteq |\psi |_{\cal M}^h, {\rm where} \;h = (s_0, \ldots,s_n)$$

B φψ’ is a conditional belief: the agent believes ψ given (or conditional on) φ. Epistemologically speaking, if something like the Ramsey test is a correct epistemology of conditionals, a conditional belief is similar enough to a belief in the corresponding conditional for our purposes.Footnote 19

4.1.1. Some empirical support

There is some empirical evidence that supports the epistemological relation between conditional beliefs and beliefs in conditionals, on which a Ramsey test epistemology for conditionals relies. That is, there is empirical evidence that suggests that people believe conditionals if they also have the corresponding conditional belief. In order to properly spell out the evidence and how it supports (something like) a Ramsey test epistemology for conditionals, we need to say a bit more about the relationship between beliefs, acceptability, and probability.

The empirical data we will use focuses on, what in the psychology of reasoning literature is known as, the Equation (EQ): the subjective probability (or the degree of belief) of a conditional ‘if φ then ψ’ is the corresponding (subjective) conditional probability $\Pr \lpar \psi \vert \varphi \rpar $ (where ‘ψ|φ’ means ‘ψ given φ’). That is, where ‘$\Pr \lpar \varphi \rpar $’ is the subjective probability or degree of belief in φ, $\Pr \lpar \psi \vert \varphi \rpar = {\Pr}\lpar \varphi \to \psi \rpar $. This suggests “that people evaluate the probability of conditionals as the conditional probability for a wide range of conditionals” (Elqayam and Over Reference Elqayam and Over2013: 253).Footnote 20 Importantly, this epistemological claim has,

over the past decade, … been subjected to empirical testing by various experimental psychologists, and it has been found, time and again, that people's judged probabilities of conditionals do closely match their judgments of the corresponding conditional probabilities … Given these experimental results, rejecting (EQ) would amount to attributing massive error to people as far as their judgments of … conditionals are concerned.

(Douven and Verbrugge Reference Douven and Verbrugge2013: 712)

All these empirical tests show that there is an epistemological equivalence in terms of subjective probabilities in conditionals and conditional subjective probabilities; in that “people do generally judge the probability of a conditional to be equal to the corresponding conditional probability” (Douven Reference Douven, Gendler and Hawthorne2013: 11) (see Douven Reference Douven, Gendler and Hawthorne2013: 11, fn. 10, Reference Douven2015; Douven and Verbrugge Reference Douven and Verbrugge2013: 712; Elqayam and Over Reference Elqayam and Over2013 for references to this empirical literature).

These data concern the subjective probabilities of agents (i.e., it is quantitative), whereas our definition of conditional belief is defined as belief tout court (i.e., it is qualitative). So, in order for the data to support the use of Definition 4 in the epistemology of conditionals, we need to find a way to make the data on the quantitative epistemological equivalence relevant to the qualitative relationship between conditional beliefs and beliefs in conditionals. We do so by appeal to the Lockean Thesis for Belief (LTB):Footnote 21

(LTB) A proposition φ is rationally believable for a person iff Pr(φ) > θ, where ‘θ’ is some threshold.

In what follows, I will assume that the threshold is fixed and suppress any mention of it. We can now link subjective probabilities that agents assign to propositions to qualitative beliefs by using (LTB). Going back to the data of Douven and colleagues, we can replace the subjective probabilities with the corresponding beliefs in (EQ) – as per (LTB). For the purposes of this paper, this means that, instead of talking about ‘judge’ or ‘evaluate’, we can say the following:

If people conditionally believe ψ given φ, they are also in the epistemological position to justifiably believe the conditional ‘if φ, (then) ψ’.

This suggests, in line with any epistemology of conditionals that relies on something like the Ramsey test, that Definition 4 is enough to evaluate the claim that pretense imagination provides us with justification for new beliefs in conditionals.

Let me stress that these empirical findings are merely supposed to support the philosophical arguments. One should be careful in how to interpret findings pertaining to the similarity or difference of judgements based on the fact that no difference is shown in the empirical data.Footnote 22 There is, however, some abductive evidence that, despite the fact that we cannot statistically secure an equivalence, the empirical data (i.e., the high correlation) suggests that conditional probability contributes to (or is a determinant of) judgements about the corresponding conditional, which supports the epistemological relation needed for the philosophical argument used in this paper. In particular, there is the size and variety of the empirical findings: the Equation has been tested in many different ways, shapes, and forms and almost always the results are the same. The relation between judgements of the probability of the conditional and judgements of the conditional probability has been tested with both within and between subject designs and with many different kinds of stimuli (e.g., causal, counterfactual, inferential (deductive, inductive, abductive), and betting conditionals both concerning actual matters of fact or fictional affairs); graded and ungraded probability judgements have been tested as well as different methods of determining the conditional probability. In all these cases a high correlation (sometimes a “close-to-perfect” match (Douven and Verbrugge Reference Douven and Verbrugge2013: 718)) was found between the relevant judgements.Footnote 23 Importantly, studies have been done to verify that participants of these tests do not interpret the conditionals as material implications (Evans et al. Reference Evans, Handley and Over2003) nor as conjunctions (Douven and Verbrugge Reference Douven and Verbrugge2010).Footnote 24

Now that it is plausible that we can use Definition 4 to evaluate the claim that pretense imagination plays a role in the epistemology of conditionals and of possibility, let's turn to discuss the epistemic usefulness of the internal development and the intervened content in turn.

5. Epistemic usefulness of internal development

Both Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) and Williamson (Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016) defend the idea that after an imaginative episode with explicit input φ, if at some point you end up imagining ψ, the knowledge that you gain is of the (indicative) conditional φ → ψ (see also Nichols and Stich Reference Nichols and Stich2003; Byrne Reference Byrne2005; and a lot of the suppositional reasoning literature following the Ramsey test). “[T]he inferences drawn in imagination are imported back into one's beliefs as consequents to a newly believed conditional” (Langland-Hassan, Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 68, emphasis added). In this section, I will argue that internally developed conditionals that one might import back into one's beliefs are not newly believed conditionals.

It is important to stress that at this point in the argument by cases, we focus only on internal development: an imaginative episode where we only rely on hypothetical belief revision with (hypothetically) believed propositions. That is, for any world-history pair that we consider here, the history, h = (s 0, …, s n), is such that for any $i \lt n\comma \;{\rm \preceq }_{s_{i + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_i}^\varphi $, for some $\varphi \in {\cal L}$ such that $\langle w\comma \;h[ i] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\varphi $. Let us call such a history an internally developed history.

The claim that the internal development of pretense imagination can provide us with justification for new conditional beliefs is as follows: it is possible to come to have a conditional belief somewhere in an internally developed history such that the agent does not have that conditional belief at the root stage – i.e., the conditional belief is new. For if revising one's beliefs with the antecedent results in believing the consequent and the conditional was not yet believed in the original state of the imaginer, then it can be said that the imaginative episode provided the justification for a new belief in the conditional. Call this the target claim.

I will argue that this is false – i.e., I will argue that the beliefs that are the result of such imaginative episodes are not new beliefs. To show that the target claim is false, I will prove that for any internally developed history, if there is a stage where revising one's beliefs at that stage with φ results in believing ψ at the next stage, then the agent already had a conditional belief in ψ given φ in the root stage – i.e., the conditional belief is not new.

Show: For all internally developed histories, h = (s 0, ….s n), and all formulas φ and ψ, if there is an i < n such that ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{i + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_i}^\varphi $ and $\langle w\comma \;h[ i + 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\psi $, then $\langle w\comma \;s_0\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B^\varphi \psi $.

The first step is to note a consequence of our belief revision policy and the effects this has for an internally developed history. Remember that when we revise our beliefs with φ, the plausibility ordering amongst all the φ-worlds remains the same (see condition (1) of Definition 2).Footnote 25 Thus, upgrading our beliefs with a believed proposition – i.e., a proposition such that it is true at all the most plausible worlds – does not alter the set of most plausible worlds. Given that an internally developed history only involves updates with believed propositions, it follows that the set of most plausible worlds is the same at all stages of an internally developed history. That is, $Min\;{\rm \preceq }_{s_0}\lpar W\rpar $ is identical to that of any state s i in h = (s 0, …, s n) (of an internally developed history) – i.e., $Min\;{\rm \preceq }_{s_i}\lpar W\rpar = Min\;{\rm \preceq }_{s_0}\lpar W\rpar $ for any i ≤ n. Let us call this ‘(NCP)’, for No Change in most Plausible worlds.

Given that the set of most plausible worlds is constant for an internally developed history (NCP), it follows that all beliefs and conditional beliefs, which are based on revisions with believed propositions (see footnote 25), of the agent are also constant at all stages. This suggests that the target claim has to be false. To see this, take an arbitrary s i, where i < n, from an internally developed history h = (s 0, …, s n), such that (i) ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{i + 1}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_i}^\varphi $ and (ii) $\langle w\comma \;h[ i + 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\psi $. Because we focus on internally developed histories, all belief revisions are with believed propositions. So, we can conclude from (i), plus Definition 2 and (NCP), that φ is true in all the most plausible worlds of the agent at all stages of the internally developed history. From (ii), plus Definition 3 and (NCP), it follows that ψ is true in all the most plausible worlds of the agent at all stages of the internally developed history. From this it follows that ${\rm \preceq }_{s_1} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_0}^\varphi $ and $\langle w\comma \;h[ 1] \rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B\psi $. So, by Definition 4, $\langle w\comma \;s_0\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B^\varphi \psi $. Thus, the target claim is false.Footnote 26

This suggests that the internal development of pretense imagination cannot provide justification for new beliefs in conditionals. Any conditional that might be imported back into our actual beliefs was already believed, for otherwise the internal development would never result in the consequent given the antecedent.

The above argument, one might worry, seems to assume that indicative conditionals express propositions, whereas not everyone might agree with this (e.g., Edgington Reference Edgington1986; Levi Reference Levi1988; see Leitgeb Reference Leitgeb2007 for a clear discussion on these and related views). If you think that conditionals do not express propositions, they cannot, strictly speaking, be believed. As Leitgeb points out, “conditionals [on such a view are] accepted by the agent without being believed” (Reference Leitgeb2007: 119). For these theorists, ‘beliefs in conditionals’ simply are conditional beliefs (or degrees of belief in the consequent conditional on the antecedent). Note that the argument against the epistemic usefulness of the internal development of pretense imagination was phrased completely in terms of conditional beliefs. So, the conclusion holds even for those who think that indicative conditionals do not express propositions.

To sum up, despite the fact that it might seem as though our imaginative episode makes us believe certain conditionals, it is not the internal development of the imagination that provides the justification for the beliefs in these conditionals.

6. Epistemic usefulness of intervened content

When focusing on internally developed histories, we saw that we cannot gain knowledge of any new conditionals. Williamson (Reference Williamson2020) points out that this is because we usually rely on conditionals prospectively: “[w]e need ‘if A, C’ most when we do not now that A” (p. 17, original emphasis). Correspondingly, the idea is that pretense imagination really comes into its own when we intervene some content and then look at the resulting hypothetical belief revisions. As we will see, it is indeed the case that we can come to gain conditional beliefs that we did not have at the root stage when we have actively intervened content in the imaginative episode.

To show this, let's construct a model where there is a conditional belief at a stage of the imaginative episode and that conditional belief is not true at s 0 – i.e., it is a new conditional belief. Consider a model such that W = {w 1, w 2, w 3}, V(p) = {w 2, w 3}, V(q) = {w 1, w 3}, and the plausibility orderings per stage are as represented in Figure 2 – i.e., ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{12}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_0}^p $ and ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{21}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_{12}}^q $ (only part of the model is represented). We take the actual history to be h = (s 0, s 12, s 21). Note that both developments are intervened content, as we assume that the explicit input is also intentionally added. For our argument, we focus on the second intervention (i.e., the one within the imaginative episode, not the one that starts it).Footnote 27 After the upgrade with q, the agent hypothetically believes p; that is, at stage s 12 the agent has a conditional belief: they believe p conditional on q. However, it is easy to see that this is not the case at the initial stage: $\langle w\comma \;s_0\rangle {{\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar\hskip-11pt / }}\,\,B^q \; p$. So, it seems that we are able to gain new beliefs in conditionals by upgrading our (hypothetical) beliefs with intervened content. In our toy example, we gain justification for the belief in q → p, which we didn't believe before we engaged in the imaginative episode (i.e., at s 0).Footnote 28

Fig. 2. New conditional beliefs from intervened content.

7. Pretense imagination and the epistemology of possibility

Section 5 showed that if the antecedent is already believed, we gain no new conditional beliefs, which is in line with Williamson's (Reference Williamson2020: 17) comments on prospectivity. In section 6 we say that an imaginative episode with an intentionally intervened (believed to be) false proposition might indeed result in justification for a belief in a conditional. So, pretense imagination can justify us in believing prospective conditionals: conditionals of which we do not (yet) know whether the antecedent is true. The question thus becomes whether we can use this in a conditional-based epistemology of possibility. When considering the epistemological role of conditionals in the epistemology of possibility, we see that researchers often focus on providing us with justification for believing the possibility of the consequent.Footnote 29 How do pretense imagination and prospective conditionals help us in determining the modal status of the consequent? That is, can they, and if so how do they, play a role in a conditional-based epistemology of possibility?

Given that we do not believe the antecedent to be true, there are two prominent options: the antecedent is ‘merely actually false’ (i.e., false in the actual world, though possibly true) or ‘necessarily false’ (i.e., impossible). This difference has a significant effect with regards to the role the conditionals in question play in an epistemology of possibility. Consider the following pairs of conditionals to see this:

  1. (1) If Amy squared the circle, she becomes a famous logician. (Ripley Reference Ripley2012)

  2. (2) If Lamyae works in her office, she is sitting in a comfortable chair.

Let's assume that we justifiably believe both conditionals based on our pretense imagination and we believe both antecedents to be false. If we are unaware of the modal status of the antecedents, what good does knowledge of these conditionals do us in the epistemology of possibility? So, the crucial issue is how we determine that the relevant hypothetical situation (i.e., the antecedent) is possible.

The fact that the antecedent is intervened does not help us here. Intervened content is just content transferred from the intention (to imagine something) to actually imagining it. Correspondingly, merely being the input for an imaginative episode does not allow us to distinguish between merely false or impossible antecedents: there are virtually no constraints on what we use as intervened content and we can intervene content that is true, false, impossible, etc.Footnote 30

Considering the way most conditional-based epistemologies of possibility work, we can see that, in general, they rely on the transfer of possibility from the antecedent to the consequent. That is, they rely on the antecedent being known to be possible and the conditional being believed to be true, in order for you to be justified to believe that the consequent is possible (e.g., Williamson Reference Williamson2007: 156; Kment Reference Kment2014: 4). This shows that in order for the beliefs in the conditional to be useful as a tool for the epistemology of possibility, we need to have prior knowledge of the modal status of the antecedent.

So, once we have independent evidence for the possibility of the input proposition, we might use indicative conditionals (and the corresponding imaginative exercises) to extend our knowledge or beliefs in possibilities. But, prior knowledge of the modal status of the antecedent is crucial; without it pretense imagination is of no help in the epistemology of possibility.

7.1. Prior modal knowledge

Williamson (Reference Williamson2007: Ch. 5) seems to suggest that (something like) pretense imagination is crucial for his conditional-based epistemology of modality. What this paper shows is that it can only play an extending-role. In order for such a condition-based epistemology of possibility to come off the ground, we need prior knowledge of the modal status of the antecedent and pretense imagination does not seem to be able to provide this.

These theorists might be right that the imagination involved in the epistemology of the relevant conditionals is such that if the input is possible, the consequences of the resulting conditionals will be possible. Yet this leaves the crucial question of how we should determine the modal status of the antecedent itself. As Gregory (Reference Gregory2017: 834) puts it,Footnote 31

while the described method may well produce beliefs about possibility that tend to be right, our justification for holding that it does so depends upon our being entitled to assume the customary possibility of the propositions that serve as the starting-points of applications of the relevant process.

The moral of this story is that if we want to use conditionals to gain knowledge of possibilities, we need prior modal knowledge. The reliance on unexplained prior modal knowledge severely undercuts the prospects of the proposed epistemology of modality (Hale Reference Hale2003; Hill Reference Hill and Nichols2006; Roca-Royes Reference Roca-Royes, Fischer and Leon2017; Schoonen Reference Schoonen2020). In this case because the epistemology of possibility crucially leaves us without a story on how we gain knowledge of the possibility of the relevant antecedent.

8. Conclusion: potential objections

To sum up, it seems right that pretense imagination can provide us with justification for beliefs in indicative conditionals (as Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) and Williamson (Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016) suggest). This happens when we intervene content and then allow it to internally develop. However, this kind of conditional reasoning cannot play a fundamental role in the epistemology of possibility. The use of such conditionals might expand our modal knowledge, but it relies on having prior knowledge of the modal status of the antecedent, which can itself not be justified through pretense imagination. Leaving this prior modal knowledge unexplained means that pretense imagination cannot be the foundational method for determining whether something is possible and results in an unsatisfactory epistemology of possibility.

In this conclusion I want to discuss a number of objections to various parts of the epistemological discussions. I will discuss (i) the wrong formalism objection; (ii) the actuality worry; and finally (iii) the wrong conditional objection, in turn.

8.1. The wrong formalism objection

One might worry that the reason why the internal development is not epistemically useful is because of the particular, idealised, formalism in which I chose to model pretense imagination. Perhaps wrong choices were made and the conclusions would be different if one were to use a different formalism.

In response, note that all we relied on from the formalism is the fact that revising one's beliefs with something that is currently believed does not change the set of most plausible worlds. This is a very minimal assumption and is not a particularity of the formalism used here. That is, the arguments of this paper hold for any belief revision policy that is such that updating one's beliefs with a proposition that is believed does not change the set of most plausible worlds.Footnote 32 Other than that, the argument relied on a venerable tradition on the epistemology of conditionals that links conditional beliefs with beliefs in conditionals. The epistemological and psychological relation that we relied on is supported by philosophical arguments and empirical data independent of the formalism used.

8.2. The actuality worry

The reason why we concluded that pretense imagination cannot provide a satisfactory epistemology of possibility is that it requires prior modal knowledge: knowledge that the antecedent is possible. One might respond as follows: if we use only propositions that we believe to be true as antecedents of the conditional, can we then not expand our knowledge of possibilities on the basis of this? Because whatever is actually the case is possible, so having the initial input believed to be true means that we believe it to be possible as well.

Note that if we use ‘believed to be actual’-propositions as antecedents, then we would have to (hypothetically) revise our beliefs with a believed proposition. But, as we saw when discussing the epistemological value of the internal development (section 5), this does not result in new conditional beliefs. Phrased differently, the only way in which pretense imagination is epistemically useful, is if we do not believe the antecedent of the conditional in question to be true (Williamson Reference Williamson2020). Thus, we cannot use the actuality principle in combination with pretense imagination to expand our modal knowledge based on propositions that are believed to be actually true.

8.3. The wrong conditional objection

Throughout the discussion of pretense imagination providing justification for newly believed conditionals, we have focused on indicative conditionals. However, one may object, many who think that conditionals are involved in the epistemology of possibility rely on counterfactual conditionals. For example, Williamson (Reference Williamson2007) seems to suggest that the epistemology of modality is a special case of the epistemology of counterfactuals and Kment (Reference Kment2014) argues for analysing modality based on something akin to similarity-spheres of counterfactuals. The worry is that the result that indicative conditionals cannot play a fundamental role in the epistemology of modality is neither here nor there.Footnote 33

Williamson (Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016: 118) is rather explicit in that he thinks that the cognitive capacities that underlie the justification of counterfactual and indicative conditionals are largely similar. Of course, he also acknowledges that there must be some difference between the two, due to the difference in truth-value of famous pairs of such conditionals. The way that Williamson talks about it makes it seem that the difference is insignificant to the epistemology of modality. The arguments here suggest that either this is not so (that is, pretense imagination as modelled here does not (solely) play a role in the epistemology of counterfactual conditionals), or, if it is, the use of pretense imagination in the evaluation of counterfactual conditionals that feature in the epistemology of possibility also requires problematic prior modal knowledge. In general, the main argument against the use of pretense imagination in the epistemology of possibility concerns the problematic prior modal knowledge required. This holds for any conditional for which pretense imagination plays a crucial role in its epistemology. For example, even though Williamson's epistemology of possibility relies on counterfactual conditionals, rather than indicative conditions, his theory does crucially rely on pretense imagination. The arguments of this paper affect any conditional for which the epistemology is taken to be one of hypothetical belief revision.Footnote 34

Footnotes

1 See Stuart (Reference Stuart2020) for an opposing view. He argues that it is sometimes the lack of restrictions that makes imagination epistemically useful. However, what he considers as ‘epistemically useful’ is significantly different from what we are considering. On his account, it is the exploratory role of imagination that is important, whereas we are concerned with the providing of justification for certain beliefs.

2 Note that I am not claiming that imagination as the recreation of rational belief revision is the only or correct way of thinking about what imagination is. Here, I am interested in which ways of thinking about what imagination is, might explain the epistemic value of imagination.

3 I follow Balcerak Jackson in using the term ‘recreativist’ instead of ‘simulationist’ as the latter has too many connotations (e.g., simulation of theory of mind).

4 It has to be noted here that there is a way in which one can imagine recalcitrant situations with respect to both of these restrictions, namely if the agent explicitly intervenes. I address this in detail below.

5 I am not claiming that propositional imagination is all there is to pretense. For example, a crucial aspect is the resulting behaviour and interaction with props. I just focus on the propositional imagination aspect of pretense.

6 This characterisation is general enough that it would be accepted by almost everyone who works on pretense, even if they disagree on the details of pretense imagination (e.g., by both Nichols and Stich (Reference Nichols and Stich2003) and Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan2012); see Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016 for a discussion).

7 I will use ‘imaginative episode’ and ‘imagination’, ‘pretense’, ‘pretense imagination’, and verbs such as ‘imagining’ as synonymous for the purposes of this paper.

8 Even though I discuss Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) quite a lot, there is much more subtlety in his full account.

9 For those who worry about phenomenology of an imaginative episode and the lack of ‘active choice’ that seems to be involved, note that most of this intervening happens sub- or unconsciously. “What we might pre-theoretically think of as a single imaginative episode could in fact involve many such top-down ‘interventions.’ These interventions would allow for the overall imagining to proceed in ways that stray from what would be generated if one never so intervened” (Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016: 74–5).

10 This model is developed in more detail in Özgün and Schoonen (Ms). For example, there the model is more general and complemented with an additional topic-model, to overcome the idealisations of the model sketched here.

11 For more details on the next-branching time frames see Bonanno (Reference Bonanno2007, Reference Bonanno2012).

12 A total preorder ${\rm \preceq }_s$ on W is a reflexive and transitive binary relation such that either $w{\rm \preceq }_sv$ or $v{\rm \preceq }_sw$ for all w, v ∈ W.

13 See Özgün and Schoonen (Ms), where we abstract away from the particular belief revision procedure.

14 One could thus add a specific modality that reflects the agents actual doxastic state as follows:

$${\cal M}\comma \;\langle w\comma \;h\rangle {\rm \mathrel\vert \,\joinrel\mathrel\vert \joinrel\relbar }B_@\varphi \quad {\rm iff}\quad Min_{{\rm \preceq }_{s_0}}\lpar W\rpar \subseteq \vert \varphi \vert _{\cal M}^h.$$

15 Note that the definition of I aφ only works as a sufficient condition for the content being added. It might still be that the content that is added by intervention is already believed.

16 Let me stress that this does not explicitly capture the ‘active’ aspect of actively intervening. For logics that focus more on this action part of imagination see, e.g., Wansing (Reference Wansing2017).

17 In the conclusion of this paper, we will explicitly consider whether Langland-Hassan and Williamson focus on the indicative conditional and whether the arguments of this paper carry over to other conditionals.

18 For example, “one supposes the antecedent and develops the supposition. … To a first approximation: one asserts the counterfactual conditional if and only if the development eventually leads one to add the consequent” (Williamson Reference Williamson2007: 152–3). See also the quote cited earlier in the paper from Stalnaker (Reference Stalnaker, Harper, Stalnaker and Pearce1968: 44).

19 I say ‘similar enough’ here because, as we will see below, the conditional belief and belief in the conditional occur at different stages in the model.

20 Note that we are not interested in the question of whether these things are the same mental states (see, e.g., Leitgeb Reference Leitgeb2007). Additionally, one might worry that this gives rise to the famous triviality results (Lewis Reference Lewis1976; Gärdenfors Reference Gärdenfors1988). However, given that we allow our belief- and imagination-operators to range only over Booleans, these triviality worries do not seem to apply. See Douven (Reference Douven, Gendler and Hawthorne2013) for a discussion about the tension between the empirical findings and the formal triviality results.

21 See also Foley (Reference Foley1992), Hawthorne (Reference Hawthorne, Huber and Schmidt-Petri2009) and Demey (Reference Demey2013) on something like (LTB).

22 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for urging me to stress this.

23 To further strengthen these empirical results, we should look at the statistical power of these results in combination with their sample size. In order to overcome the limitations of individual studies, ideally a meta-analysis would be performed on the empirical data concerning the Equation. As far as I am aware, no such a meta-analysis has yet been done.

24 There seem to be two main limitations to these findings. First of all, as Douven (Reference Douven, Gendler and Hawthorne2013: 14) points out, these findings are limited to conditionals “whose antecedents and consequents are not themselves conditional in form nor are compounds which have one or more conditionals among their components”. Since we only focus on simple conditionals in the epistemology of possibility, this issue does not affect the arguments made here. Secondly, Skovgaard-Olsen et al. (Reference Skovgaard-Olsen, Singmann and Klauer2016) suggest that the Equation does not seem to hold when the antecedent is irrelevant for the consequent (and the materials are natural, real life scenarios rather than abstract vignettes). This is an important limitation on the empirical findings, but one that we should only welcome. In general, we would want our pretense imagination only to justify the modal status of propositions that are relevantly related to the imaginative episode. See the models in Özgün and Schoonen (Ms), where topic-models are used in the models of pretense imagination to capture this aspect of relevance. We can ignore these complications for the philosophical arguments made in the remainder of the paper.

25 In the conclusion, I will discuss the reliance of the argument on this particular belief revision policy.

26 Interestingly, imagining something through internal development (i.e., imagining that you already (hypothetically) believe) does affect ‘other’ conditional beliefs at the different stages. That is, even though we might not gain beliefs in conditionals such that the antecedent is that which we imagine, we might gain conditional beliefs where the imagined proposition is not part of it. For example, consider a model where there are three worlds, such that V(p) = {w 2, w 3}, V(q) = {w 1, w 3}, and V(r) = {w 1, w 3} and such that ${\rm \preceq }_{s_0} = w_1 \lt w_2 \lt w_3$. If, in this model, we imagine q (which qualifies as an internal development, given that q is believed at s 0), then we have that at the resulting imaginative stage, s 1, the conditional belief B pr is true, even though this conditional belief is false in the original state, s 0.

This raises a number of interesting questions. For example, would we want to say that imagining q could justify the belief in a (potentially unrelated) conditional p → r? Whenever Williamson (Reference Williamson2007) or Langland-Hassan (Reference Langland-Hassan, Kind and Kung2016) talk about imagination, the imagined proposition always features as the antecedent of the corresponding conditional. The same holds for the literature surrounding the Ramsey test and the epistemology of indicative conditionals: we (hypothetically) update our beliefs with the antecedent in order to see if the consequent holds. It seems to me not straightforward to defend the position that imagining q justifies accepting the new belief in the conditional p → r, however, more needs to be said about this. Unfortunately, this is outside the scope of this paper.

27 One could also construct a model where the imaginative episode starts with internally developed content and still make the same argument. In such a case, the model would be as above, but with ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{14}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_0}^q $ and ${\rm \preceq }_{s_{22}} = {\rm \preceq }_{s_{14}}^p $.

28 This toy model is of course a simplification and there are probably a number of internally developed steps in between (which is what, e.g., Williamson seems to mean with ‘develop the supposition’). However, as we saw with internally developed histories, the set of most plausible worlds after the last intervened upgrade is the same throughout the following internally developed upgrades. So, for simplicity, we ignore these potential intermediate internally developed upgrades.

29 This is not a surprise. We just saw that the antecedent – i.e., the intervened content – can be anything and simply being a supposed proposition does not carry any epistemological weight. Furthermore, if it is true that we end up believing the corresponding conditional, then we believe it to be actually true. So, the possibility of the conditional would be of the ‘uninteresting’ kind of knowledge of possibilities resulting from the actuality principle (Hanrahan Reference Hanrahan, Fischer and Leon2017: 211).

30 Note that in the model discussed in this paper, we can only imagine ‘conjoined’ impossibilities. That is, if we upgraded our simulated beliefs with φ and at some later point with ¬φ, we can be said to have imagined φ and, in the same episode, ¬φ. However, we cannot imagine ‘atomic’ impossibilities in this model (e.g., ‘unicorns exist’, ‘there is a round square’, etc.). A more faithful modelling of pretense imagination should ultimately allow for these, potentially with additional impossible worlds (see Berto Reference Berto2017). The fact that the model does not allow for imagining impossibilities is a shortcoming of the model, which can be fixed by, e.g., the incorporation of impossible worlds, and not of the argument.

31 Gregory (Reference Gregory2017) argues against Williamson's epistemology more generally. For example, he argues that it is not obvious that our ordinary capacity to evaluate Williamson's conditionals are reliable when it comes to the cases relevant for the modal implications of such conditionals.

32 Note that the arguments do not require that the plausibility order stays the same when revising our beliefs with a believed proposition. All that we need is that the most plausible worlds do not change – i.e., that $Min_{{\rm \preceq }_{s_n}}\lpar W\rpar $ stays the same.

33 It seems that in more recent work, Williamson (Reference Williamson, Kind and Kung2016) is talking about indicative conditionals.

34 First of all thanks to the reviewers for their helpful feedback. The idea for this paper has its origins in a discussion with Peter Hawke and was more fully developed when Felipe Morales Carbonell and Jan Heylen invited me to give a talk at the Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science Seminar at the University of Leuven. Thanks to Felipe and Jan for inviting me and thanks to the audience of the seminar for invigorating discussions. Earlier versions of this work were also presented at the OZSW Theoretical Philosophy Conference at the University of Tilburg and at the 2019 OZSW conference at the University of Amsterdam. Thanks to these audiences for their feedback. Thanks to Christopher Badura and Thom van Gessel who both read a version of this paper. Finally, thanks to the members of the Logic of Conceivability-gang: Francesco Berto, Peter Hawke, Karolina Krzyżanowska, Aybüke Özgün, and Anthi Solaki: your discussions have significantly improved this paper.

References

Balcerak Jackson, M. (2018). ‘Justification by Imagination.’ In Macpherson, F. and Dorsch, F. (eds) Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory, pp. 209–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baltag, A. and Smets, S. (2006). ‘Dynamic Belief Revision over Multi-Agent Plausibility Models.’ In Bonanno, G., van der Hoek, W. and Wooldridge, M. (eds), Proceedings of the 7th Conference on Logic and the Foundations of Game and Decision (LOFT2006), pp. 1124. Liverpool: University of Liverpool.Google Scholar
Berto, F. (2017). ‘Impossible Worlds and the Logic of Imagination.’ Erkenntnis 82(6), 1277–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonanno, G. (2007). ‘Axiomatic Characterization of the AGM theory of Belief Revision in a Temporal Logic.’ Artificial Intelligence 171(2), 144–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonanno, G. (2012). ‘Belief Change in Branching Time: AMG-consistency and Iterated Revision.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic 4(1), 201–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, R.M.J. (2005). The Rational Imagination. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demey, L. (2013). ‘Contemporary Epistemic Logic and the Lockean Thesis.’ Foundations of Science 18(4), 599610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douven, I (2013). ‘The Epistemology of Conditionals.’ In Gendler, T.S. and Hawthorne, J. (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 4, pp. 333. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douven, I. (2015). The Epistemology of Indicative Conditionals: Formal and Empirical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Douven, I. and Verbrugge, S. (2010). ‘The Adams Family.’ Cognition 117(3), 302–18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Douven, I. and Verbrugge, S. (2013). The Probabilities of Conditionals Revisited. Cognitive Science 37(4), 711–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Edgington, D. (1986). ‘Do Conditionals Have Truth Conditions?Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 18, 339.Google Scholar
Elqayam, S. and Over, D.E. (2013). ‘New Paradigm Psychology of Reasoning.’ Thinking and Reasoning 19(3–4), 249–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J.S.B.T., Handley, S.J. and Over, D.E. (2003). ‘Conditionals and Conditional Probability.’ Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 29(2), 321–35.Google ScholarPubMed
Foley, R. (1992). ‘The Epistemology of Belief and the Epistemology of Degrees of Belief.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 29(2), 111–24.Google Scholar
Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in Flux. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (2006). ‘Imagination and Simulation in Audience Responses to Fiction.’ In Nichols, S. (ed.), The Architecture of the Imagination, pp. 4156. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, D. (2017). ‘Counterfactual Reasoning and Knowledge of Possibilities.’ Philosophical Studies 174(4), 821–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, B. (2003). ‘The Presidential Address: Knowledge of Possibility and of Necessity.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103(1), 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanrahan, R. (2017). ‘Imagination, Possibility, and Plovers.’ In Fischer, B. and Leon, F. (eds), Modal Epistemology After Rationalism, pp. 197219. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2009). ‘The Lockean Thesis and the Logic of Belief.’ In Huber, F. and Schmidt-Petri, C. (eds), Degrees of Belief, pp. 4974. Dordrect: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, C.S. (2006). ‘Modality, Modal Epistemology, and the Metaphysics of Consciousness.’ In Nichols, S. (ed.), The Architecture of the Imagination, pp. 205–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A. (2016). ‘Imagining Under Constraints.’ In Kind, A. and Kung, P. (eds), Knowledge Through Imagination, pp. 145–59. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A. and Kung, P. (eds) (2016). Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kment, B. (2014). Modality and Explanatory Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langland-Hassan, P. (2012). ‘Pretense, Imagination, and Belief: the Single Attitude Theory.’ Philosophical Studies 159, 155–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langland-Hassan, P. (2016). ‘On Choosing What to Imagine.’ In Kind, A. and Kung, P. (eds), Knowledge Through Imagination, pp. 6184. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, H. (2007). ‘Beliefs in Conditionals vs. Conditional Beliefs.’ Topoi 26(1), 115–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leslie, A.M. (1994). ‘Pretending and Believing: Issues in the Theory of ToMM.’ Cognition 50(1–3), 211–38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levi, I. (1988). ‘Iteration of Conditionals and the Ramsey Test.’ Synthese 76(1), 4981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D.K. (1976). ‘Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional Probabilities.’ Philosophical Review 85(3), 297315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (ed.) (2006). ‘Imaginative Blocks and Impossibility: An Essay in Modal Psychology.’ In The Architecture of the Imagination, pp. 237–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S.P. (2003). Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness, and Understanding Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Özgün, A. and Schoonen, T. (Ms). ‘The Logical Development of Pretense Imagination.’Google Scholar
Ramsey, F.P. (1929 [2013]). ‘General Propositions and Causality.’ In Braithwaite, R. (ed.), The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, pp. 237–55. Eastford, CT: Martino Publishing.Google Scholar
Ripley, D. (2012). ‘Structures and Circumstances: Two Ways to Fine-grain Propositions.’ Synthese 189, 97118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roca-Royes, S. (2017). ‘Similarity and Possibility: An Epistemology of de re Possibility for Concrete Entities.’ In Fischer, B. and Leon, F. (eds), Modal Epistemology After Rationalism, Vol. 378, pp. 221–45. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoonen, T. (2020). ‘The Problem of Modally Bad Company.’ Res Philosophica 97(4), 639–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skovgaard-Olsen, N., Singmann, H. and Klauer, K.C. (2016). ‘The Relevance Effect and Conditionals.’ Cognition 150, 2636.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stalnaker, R.C. (1968). ‘A Theory of Conditionals.’ In Harper, W., Stalnaker, R. and Pearce, G. (eds), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time, pp. 4155. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stuart, M.T. (2020). ‘The Productive Anarchy of Scientific Imagination.’ Philosophy of Science. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/17980.Google Scholar
van Benthem, J. (2007). ‘Dynamic Logic for Belief Revision.’ Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 17(2), 129–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wansing, H. (2017). ‘Remarks on the Logic of Imagination. A Step Towards Understanding Doxastic Control Through Imagination.’ Synthese 194(8), 2843–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2016). ‘Knowing by Imagining.’ In Kind, A. and Kung, P. (eds), Knowledge Through Imagination, pp. 113–23. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2020). Suppose and Tell. The Semantics and Heuristics of Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1. A toy-example of a branching-time belief revision model: the nodes represent the stages of the imaginative episode with the plausibility ordering of that particular stage.

Figure 1

Fig. 2. New conditional beliefs from intervened content.