Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T00:01:24.525Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fragmentation and Old Evidence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 February 2021

Will Fleisher*
Affiliation:
Northeastern University, Khoury College of Computer Sciences, 360 Huntington Avenue, Boston, MA 02115, USA

Abstract

Bayesian confirmation theory is our best formal framework for describing inductive reasoning. The problem of old evidence is a particularly difficult one for confirmation theory, because it suggests that this framework fails to account for central and important cases of inductive reasoning and scientific inference. I show that we can appeal to the fragmentation of doxastic states to solve this problem for confirmation theory. This fragmentation solution is independently well-motivated because of the success of fragmentation in solving other problems. I also argue that the fragmentation solution is preferable to other solutions to the problem of old evidence. These other solutions are already committed to something like fragmentation, but suffer from difficulties due to their additional commitments. If these arguments are successful, Bayesian confirmation theory is saved from the problem of old evidence, and the argument for fragmentation is bolstered by its ability to solve yet another problem.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alchourrón, C.E., Gärdenfors, P. and Makinson, D (1985). ‘On the Logic of Theory Change: Partial Meet Contraction and Revision Functions.’ Journal of Symbolic Logic 50(2), 510–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.C. (1999). ‘The Quantitative Problem of Old Evidence.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50(2), 249–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callahan, L.F. (2020). ‘Epistemic Existentialism.’ Episteme, Online first. doi: 10.1017/epi.2019.25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cherniak, C. (1983). ‘Rationality and the Structure of Human Memory.’ Synthese 57(2), 163–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crupi, V. (2015). ‘Confirmation.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/confirmation/.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. (1985). ‘Problems of Old Evidence.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66(3), 283302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E. and Fitelson, B. (2000). ‘Measuring Confirmation and Evidence.’ Journal of Philosophy 97(12), 663672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egan, A. (2008). ‘Seeing and Believing: Perception, Belief Formation and the Divided Mind.’ Philosophical Studies 140(1), 4763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. and Rayo, A. (Ms). ‘Fragmentation and Information Access.’ (2019).Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (1999). ‘The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity.’ Philosophy of Science 66(3), S362S378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2007). ‘Likelihoodism, Bayesianism, and Relational Confirmation.’ Synthese 156(3), 473489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2008). ‘A Decision Procedure for Probability Calculus with Applications.’ Review of Symbolic Logic 1(1), 111125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleisher, W. (2020). ‘How to Endorse Conciliationism.’ Synthese Online first. doi: 10.1007/s11229-020-02695-z.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, A. (1990). Experiment, Right or Wrong. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, D. (1983). ‘Old Evidence and Logical Omniscience in Bayesian Confirmation Theory.’ In Earman, J. (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories, Vol. 10, pp. 99131. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of the Epistemic States. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gillies, A.S. (2001). Rational Belief Change. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Dissertation.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and Evidence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Greco, D. (2014). ‘Iteration and Fragmentation.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88(1), 656–73.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2019). ‘Interpretations of Probability.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/probability-interpret/.Google Scholar
Hansson, S.O. (2017). ‘Logic of Belief Revision.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/logic-belief-revision/.Google Scholar
Hartmann, S. and Fitelson, B. (2015). ‘A New Garber-Style Solution to the Problem of Old Evidence.’ Philosophy of Science 82(4), 712–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2005). ‘Degree-of-Belief and Degree-of-Support: Why Bayesians Need Both Notions.’ Mind 114(454), 277320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. (1991). ‘The ’Old Evidence’ Problem.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42(4), 547–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Huber, F. (2013 a). ‘Belief Revision I: The AGM Theory.’ Philosophy Compass 8(7), 604–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huber, F. (2013 b). ‘Belief Revision II: Ranking Theory.’ Philosophy Compass 8(7), 613–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R.C. (1983). ‘Bayesianism With a Human Face.’ In Earman, J. (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories, pp. 133–56. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R.C. (1990). The Logic of Decision. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, D.A. (2020). Deliberations on Deliberation. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Rutgers University Department of Philosophy, New Brunswick, NJ.Google Scholar
Joyce, J.M. (1998). ‘A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.’ Philosophy of Science 65(4), 575603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J.M. (1999). The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, J.C. (2014). ‘Structured Propositions.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/propositions-structured/.Google Scholar
Kinney, D. (2019). ‘Inductive Explanation and Garber–Style Solutions to the Problem of Old Evidence.’ Synthese 196(10), 39954009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. (2004). Mild Contraction: Evaluating Loss of Information Due to Loss of Belief. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1982). ‘Logic for Equivocators.’ Noûs 16(3), 431–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meacham, C.J.G. (2016). ‘Ur-Priors, Conditionalization, and Ur-Prior Conditionalization.’ Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 3. doi: 10.3998/ergo.12405314.0003.017.Google Scholar
Menzel, C. (2016). ‘Possible Worlds.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/possible-worlds/.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1983). ‘Novel Facts and Bayesianism.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34(4), 375–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A. (2013). The Construction of Logical Space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoenfield, M. (2014). ‘Permission to Believe: Why Permissivism is True and What it Tells Us About Irrelevant Influences on Belief.’ Noûs 48(2), 193218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E. (2015). ‘Belief.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 edn).Google Scholar
Sprenger, J. (2015). ‘A Novel Solution to the Problem of Old Evidence.’ Philosophy of Science 82(3), 383401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech and Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strevens, M. (Ms). ‘Notes on Bayesian Confirmation Theory.’ (2006).Google Scholar
Suzuki, S. (2005). ‘The Old Evidence Problem and AGM Theory.’ Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 13(2), 105–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbott, W. (2015). ‘Bayesian Epistemology.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 edn). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/epistemology-bayesian/.Google Scholar
Titelbaum, M. (Forthcoming). Fundamentals of Bayesian Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weisberg, J. (2011). ‘Varieties of Bayesianism.’ In Gabbay, D., Hartmann, S. and Woods, J. (eds), Handbook of the History of Logic, Vol. 10, pp. 477551. Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
Weisberg, J. (2020). ‘Belief in Psyontology.’ The Philosopher's Imprint 20(11), 127.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2008). ‘Why Epistemology Cannot be Operationalized.’ In Smith, Q. (ed.), Epistemology: New Essays, pp. 277300. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yalcin, S. (2018). ‘Belief as Question-Sensitive.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97(1), 2347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Supplementary material: PDF

Fleisher supplementary material

Fleisher supplementary material

Download Fleisher supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 133.5 KB