Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-24hb2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T13:47:40.255Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CAN UNSTABLE PREFERENCES PROVIDE A STABLE STANDARD OF WELL-BEING?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 March 2010

Krister Bykvist*
Affiliation:
University of Oxford

Abstract

How do we determine the well-being of a person when her preferences are not stable across worlds? Suppose, for instance, that you are considering getting married, and that you know that if you get married, you will prefer being unmarried, and that if you stay unmarried, you will prefer being married. The general problem is to find a stable standard of well-being when the standard is set by preferences that are not stable. In this paper, I shall show that the problem is even worse: inconsistency threatens if we accept both that your desires determine what is good for you and that you must prefer what is better for you. After I have introduced a useful toy model and stated the inconsistency argument, I will go on to discuss a couple of unsuccessful theories and see what we can learn from their mistakes. One important lesson is that how you would have felt about a life had you never led it is irrelevant to the question of how good that life is for you. What counts is how you feel about your life when you are actually leading it. Another lesson is that a life can be better for you even if you would not rank it higher, if you were to lead it.

Type
Essay
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Bricker, P. 1980. Prudence. Journal of Philosophy 77: 381401.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. 2008. Comparing evaluations. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 108: 85100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 2004. Weighing Lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bykvist, K. 1998. Changing Preferences. A Study in Preferentialism. Uppsala: Acta Universitatis Uppsaliensis.Google Scholar
Bykvist, K. 2003. The moral relevance of past preferences. In Time and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, ed. Dyke, H., 115136. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bykvist, K. 2006. What are desires good for? Towards a coherent endorsement theory. Ratio 14: 286304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1964. The descriptive element in the concept of action. Journal of Philosophy 61: 613625.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1999. Valuing activity. In Human Flourishing, ed. Paul, E., Miller, F. and Paul, J., 176196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2002. Sovereign Virtue. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 2005. Basic intrinsic value. In Recent Work on Intrinsic Value, ed. Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. and Zimmerman, M.. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy 17: 379400.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1992. Interpersonal comparisons: preference, good, and the intrinsic reward of a life. In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Elster, J. and Hylland, A., 165193. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1953. Welfare economics of variable tastes. Review of Economic Studies 21: 204213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, T. 2001. Virtue, Vice, and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 1994. Desire and the human good. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 68: 3954.Google Scholar
List, C. 2003. Are interpersonal comparisons of utility indeterminate? Erkenntnis 58: 229260.Google Scholar
McKerlie, D. 2007. Comments on Krister Bykvist ‘Prudence for Changing Selves’. Utilitas 19: 4750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1992. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. and Österberg, J. 1996. Value based on preferences. On two interpretations of Preference Utilitarianism. Economics and Philosophy 12: 127.Google Scholar
Schoeffler, S. 1952. A note on modern welfare economics. American Economic Review 62: 880887.Google Scholar
Sobel, D. 1994. Full information accounts of well-being. Ethics 104: 784810.Google Scholar
Temkin, L. 1996. A continuum argument for intransitivity. Philosophy and Public Affairs 25: 175210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wessels, U. 1998. Procreation. In Preferences, ed. Wessels, U. and Fehige, C.. Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy 19: 429468.Google Scholar