Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T04:46:53.662Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Language Animal and the Passive Side of the Human Condition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

NIKOLAI MÜNCH*
Affiliation:
Johannes Gutenberg-University, Mainz

Abstract

In some strains of current philosophy, there is a growing interest in the passive and receptive aspects of the human condition. This interest is often paired with a criticism that ‘Western’ philosophy unduly neglects those aspects because of an ‘agential bias.’ This criticism has also been directed against the philosophy of Charles Taylor. I try to show that this criticism has some force in principle but is not plausible in the case of Taylor. First, I analyse John Rawls’ hugely influential concept of a life plan and show how this ‘agential bias’ applies here. Second, I argue that such a bias does not apply to Taylor’s The Language Animal by showing how active and passive moments are interwoven in his concepts of articulation and narration.

On note, dans certains courants de la philosophie contemporaine, un intérêt croissant pour les aspects passifs et réceptifs de la condition humaine. Cet intérêt s’accompagne souvent d’une critique selon laquelle la philosophie «occidentale» négligerait à tort ces aspects en raison d’un «biais d’agentivité». Cette critique a également été émise à l’endroit de la philosophie de Charles Taylor. J’entends montrer ici que cette critique, bien qu’elle ait en principe une certaine force, ne peut raisonnablement s’appliquer dans le cas de Taylor. J’analyserai dans un premier temps le concept fort influent de «projet de vie» et montrerai comment le biais d’agentivité s’y applique. Dans un second temps, en présentant comment les moments actifs et passifs sont liés dans ses concepts d’articulation et de narration, je montrerai que ce biais ne saurait valoir pour The Language Animal de Taylor.

Type
Special Issue: Charles Taylor’s The Language Animal
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andermann, Kerstin 2011 “Widerfahrnisse. Dimensionen der Passivität und der Anonymität im Handlungsgeschehen.” Phänomenologische Forschungen: 6185.Google Scholar
Angehrn, Emil 1997 “Glück und Gelingen.” In: Angehrn, Emil and Beartschi, Berhard (eds.), Philosophie und die Frage nach dem Glück. Bern: Haupt, 125138.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry 1988 The Importance of What We Care About. Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heyd, David, and Miller, Franklin G. 2010 “Life Plans: Do They Give Meaning to Our Lives?” The Monist 93 (1): 1737.Google Scholar
Kamlah, Wilhelm 1973 Philosophische Anthropologie. Sprachkritische Grundlegung und Ethik. Mannheim, Wien, Zürich: Bibliographisches Institut.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel 2002 Critique of Practical Reason. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett.Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles 1999 “The Idea of a Life Plan.” Social Philosophy & Policy 16 (1): 96112.Google Scholar
Münch, Nikolai, and Sigwart, Hans-Jörg 2014 “Wir, die Gesellschaft: Politik und Hermeneutik bei Charles Taylor.” In: Bohmann, Ulf (ed.), Wie wollen wir leben? Das politische Denken und Staatsverständnis von Charles Taylor. Baden-Baden: Nomos, 140175.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha 1986 The Fragility of Goodness. Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John 1973 A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reader, Soran 2007 “The Other Side of Agency.” Philosophy 82 (4): 579604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandel, Michael J. 2008 Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2 nd ed.Google Scholar
Schapp, Wilhelm 2012 In Geschichten verstrickt. Zum Sein von Mensch und Ding. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. 5 th ed.Google Scholar
Seel, Martin 1995 Versuch über die Form des Glücks. Studien zur Ethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Seel, Martin 2002 Sich bestimmen lassen. Studien zur praktischen Philosophie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Seel, Martin 2006 Paradoxien der Erfüllung. Philosophische Essays. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.Google Scholar
Seel, Martin 2012 “Glaube, Hoffnung, Liebe—und einige andere nicht allein christliche Tugenden.” In: Kühnlein, Michael and Lutz-Bachmann, Matthias (eds.), Unerfüllte Moderne? Neue Perspektiven auf das Werk von Charles Taylor. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 797820.Google Scholar
Smith, Nicholas H. 2002 Charles Taylor. Meaning, Morals, and Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles 1985 Human Agency and Language. Philosophical Papers I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles 1985 “Philosophy and the Human Sciences.” Philosophical Papers II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles 1992 Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles 1995 Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles 2016 The Language Animal. The Full Shape of the Human Linguistic Capacity. Cambridge, MA and London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard 1995 Moral Luck. Philosophical Papers 1973-1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar