Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-rnj55 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-14T03:34:30.222Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Federalism, Biculturalism, and International Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 March 2016

Edward McWhinney*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto, Member of the Prime Minister of Ontario’s Advisory Committee on Confederation
Get access

Extract

The Contemporary “Great Debate” over the future of Canadian Confederation, whatever else it may have done, has at least shattered a number of comfortable old maxims as to the inevitable course and development of federal constitutions. “Bryce’s law” — or the asserted axiom that federalism is simply a transitory step on the way to political unity — has been exposed for what it really is, a generalization based too easily upon the experience of the essentially “Anglo-Saxon,” English-speaking federal systems with which Lord Bryce happened to be acquainted at the time he was writing. Even Dicey’s triadic critique long accepted as a truism in Empire and Commonwealth legal circles — that federalism inevitably means weak government, conservatism, and legalism — may be seriously doubted, as to its first two points at least, in the light of the strongly centripetal governmental trends in the main federal systems in modern times, and the concomitant association of that centralizing trend with political concepts of social and economic planning and community determination and direction of financial policy. It may be, as a French-Canadian jurist contended at a conference on Federalism held in Toronto in November 1964, that those English-speaking Canadian jurists who, in the 1930’s and the 1940’s, preached both the desirability and also the inexorability of the march to Ottawa were “plucking the Socialist fruit from the tree before it was fully ripe.” We are, in any case, indebted to French Canada for reminding us that theories of historical inevitability, when applied to social phenomena, must inevitably tend to break down if they ignore the crucial variable of the human factor. For while complex political-legal relationships and interactions often seem to be shaped and conditioned by intractable social and economic forces, in the end the dynamic element in the community power process must still be the free will of the main actors or participants in it. This is in essence William James’s point that truth is not an abstract quality inherent in an idea but something that happens to it in the unfolding of events. In constitutional law, what may have seemed right and proper and, if you wish, true for Canada in the 1930’s and the 1940’s may not necessarily be so today.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Canadian Council on International Law / Conseil Canadien de Droit International, representing the Board of Editors, Canadian Yearbook of International Law / Comité de Rédaction, Annuaire Canadien de Droit International 1965

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See McWhinney, , Constitutionalism in Germany and the Federal Constitutional Court (1962).Google Scholar

2 See generally McWhinney, , “The Relevance of Federalism for Contemporary Constitution-making,” in Comparative Federalism. States’ Rights and National Power 90 et seq. (1962).Google Scholar

3 In the argument that follows, I have drawn freely upon my earlier examination, “Classical Federalism and Supranational Integration or Treaty-based Association: the European Community Movement as a Case Study,” in Proceedings of the American Society of International Law, 1963 at 241.

4 Attorney-General for Canada v. Attorney-General for Ontario, [1937] A.C. 336 (P.C.).

5 Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920).

6 See Lord Wright’s remarks, as reported in (1955) 33 Can. Bar Rev. 1123.

7 See the discussion, “Labour Conventions Case: Lord Wright’s Undisclosed Dissent?” (1956) 34 Can. Bar Rev. 114, 115, 243.

8 See per Kerwin, C. J. C., Francis v. The Queen (1956), 3 D.L.R. (2d) 641 Google Scholar.

9 252 U.S. 416 (1920).

10 U.S. v. Curtiss-Wright Export Corporation, 299 U.S. 304 (1936).

11 (1937) A.C. 326 (P.C.).

12 See the decision of the Bundesverfassungsgericht (Second Senate), March 26, 1957. 6 B Verf GE 309 (1957). And see generally McWhinney, , Constitutionalism in Germany and the Federal Constitutional Court 46 et seq.(1962)Google Scholar; McWhinney, , Comparative Federalism. States’ Rights and National Power 36 et seq. (1962)Google Scholar.

13 The foregoing criticisms are not, however, intended to derogate from the general intellectual value of some of the current Quebec proposals for constitutional revision. See, for example, the thoughtful suggestions by Morin, Jacques-Yvan, “Un statut constitutionnel particulier pour le Québec,Le Devoir, April 22, 23, 24, 1964 Google Scholar; “Liberté nationale et fédéralisme,” 14 Thémis 91 (1964); “Un nouveau rôle pour un Sénat moribond,” Cité Libre, (June 1964). The general problems of Federal Constitutionalism in multi-cultural societies will be considered by the writer in some greater detail in a forthcoming monograph study. The pioneering group study in the field still remains Bowie, Robert R. and Friedrich, Carl J. (editors), Studies in Federalism (1954)Google Scholar.