Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T02:01:29.283Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reading One's Own Mind: Self-Awareness and Developmental Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

The idea that we have special access to our own mental states has a distinguished philosophical history. Philosophers as different as Descartes and Locke agreed that we know our own minds in a way that is quite different from the way in which we know other minds. In the latter half of the twentieth century, however, this idea carne under serious attack, first from philosophy (Sellars 1956) and more recently from developmental psychology. The attack from developmental psychology arises from the growing body of work on “mindreading,” the process of attributing mental states to people (and other organisms). During the last fifteen years, the processes underlying rnindreading have been a major focus of attention in cognitive and developmental psychology. Most of this work has been concerned with the processes underlying the attribution of mental states to other people. However, a number of psychologists and philosophers have also proposed accounts of the mechanisms underlying the attribution of mental states to oneself. This process of reading one's own mind or becoming self-aware will be our primary concern in this paper.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. 1989. “Are Autistic Children ‘behaviorists'?”. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 19: 579600.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. 1991. “The Development of a Theory of Mind in Autism: Deviance and Delay?Psychiatric Clinics of North America 14: 3351.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S.Leslie, A. and Frith, U. 1985. “Does the Autistic Child Have a ‘Theory of Mind'?Cognition 21: 3746.Google Scholar
Block, N. forthcoming. Mental Paint.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 1996. “Autism as Mind-blindness: An Elaboration and Partial Defence.” In Theories of Theories of Mind, ed. Carruthers, P. and Smith, P.257273. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Ericsson, K. and Simon, H. 1993. Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports As Data. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Flavell, J.Everett, B.Croft, K. and Flavell, E. 1981. “Young Children's Knowledge About Visual Perception.Developmental Psychology 17: 99103.Google Scholar
Flavell, J.Flavell, E. and Green, F. 1987Young Children's Knowledge About the Apparent-real and Pretend-real Distinctions.Developmental Psychology 23: 816-22.Google Scholar
Flavell, J.Flavell, E.Green, F. and Moses, L. 1990. “Young Children's Understanding of Fact Beliefs Versus Value Beliefs.Child Development 61:915-28.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1992. “A Theory of the Child's Theory of Mind.Cognition 44: 283-96.Google Scholar
Frith, C. 1994. “Theory of Mind in Schizophrenia.” In The Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia, ed. David, A. and Cutting, J.147161. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.Google Scholar
Frith, U. and Happé, F. 1999. “Theory of Mind and Self Consciousness: What Is It Like to Be Autistic?Mind & Language 14: 122.Google Scholar
German, T. and Leslie, A. forthcoming. Self-Other Differences in False Belief: Recall versus Reconstruction.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1993a. Philosophical Applications of Cognitive Science. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1993b. “The Psychology of Folk Psychology”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28, 101-13.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1997. “Science, Publicity, and Consciousness.Philosophy of Science 64:525-46.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2000. “The Mentalizing Folk.” In Metarepresentation, ed. Sperber, D.171196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. 1983. Fact, Fiction & Forecast. Fourth edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. 1993. “How We Know Our Own Minds: The Illusion of Firstperson Knowledge of Intentionality.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 114.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Astington, J. 1988. “Children's Understanding of Representational Change and its Relation to the Understanding of False Belief and the Appearance-Reality Distinction.Child Development 59: 2637.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Graf, P. 1988. “Knowing How You Know: Young Children's Ability to Identify and Remember the Sources of Their Beliefs.Child Development 59: 1366–71.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, A. 1994. “Minds, Bodies, and Persons: Young Children's Understanding of the Self and Others as Reflected in Imitation and Theory of Mind Research.” In Self-awareness in animals and humans, ed. Parker, S.Mitchell, R. and Boccia, M.166186. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, A. 1997. Words, Thoughts and Theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Slaughter, V. 1991. “Young Children's Understanding of Changes in Their Mental States.Child Development 62: 98-110.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Wellman, H. 1994. “The Theory Theory.” In Mapping the Mind, ed. Gelman, S. and Hirschfeld, L.257293. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 1995. “Simulation Without Introspection or Inference from Me to You” In Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications, ed. Stone, T. and Davies, M.5367. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 1996. “Radical Simulationism.” In Theories of Theories of Mind, ed. Carruthers, P. and Smith, P.1121. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lempers, J.Flavell, E. and Flavell, J. 1977. “The Development in Very Young Children of Tacit Knowledge Concerning Visual Perception.Genetic Psychology Monographs 95: 353.Google Scholar
Leslie, A. 1994a.”Pretending and Believing: Issues in the Theory of ToMM.“ Cognition 50: 211-38.Google Scholar
Leslie, A. 1994b. ToMM, ToBY and Agency: Core Architecture and Domain Specificity. In Mapping the mind, ed. Hirschfeld, L. and S.\Gelman, 119-48. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lillard, A. 1993. “Young Children's Conceptualization of Pretense: Action or Mental Representational State?Child Development 64: 372-86.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Masangkay, Z.McCluskey, K.Mcintyre, C.Sims-Knight, J.Vaughan, B. and Flavell, J. 1974. “The Early Development of Inferences About the Visual Percepts of Others.Child Development 45: 357-66.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. and Tye, M. 1998. “Is Content Externalism Compatible With Privileged Access?Philosophical Review 107: 349-80.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. 1993. “Developmental Evidence and Introspection.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1): 6465.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 1998. “Rethinking Co-cognition.Mind & Language 13:499-512.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2000. “A Cognitive Theory of Pretense.Cognition 74: 115-47.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2003a. How to Read Your Own Mind: A Cognitive Theory of Self-Consciousness. In Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Smith, Q. and Jokic, P.157200. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2003b. Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S.Stich, S. and Leslie, A. 1995. “Choice Effects and the Ineffectiveness of Simulation: Response to Kuhberger et al.” Mind & Language 10: 437-45.Google Scholar
Nichols, S.Stich, S.Leslie, A. and Klein, D. 1996. “Varieties of Off-line Simulation.” In Theories of Theories of Mind, ed. Carruthers, P. and Smith, P.3974. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. and Schacter, S. 1966. Cognitive Manipulation of Pain. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 21: 227-36.Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. and Wilson, T. 1977. “Telling More Than We Can Know.Psychological Review 84: 231-59.Google Scholar
O'Neill, D.Astington, J. and Flavell, J. 1992. “Young Children's Understanding of the Role that Sensory Experiences Play in Knowledge Acquisition.Child Development 63: 474-91.Google Scholar
O'Neill, D. and Gopnik, A. 1991. “Young Children's Understanding of the Sources of their Beliefs.Developmental Psychology 27: 390397.Google Scholar
Perner, J. 1991. Understanding the Representational Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Perner, J.Leekam, S. and Wimmer, H. 1987. “Three-year-olds’ Difficulty with False Belief: The Case for a Conceptual Deficit.British Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 39: 437-71.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. “The Meaning of Meaning.” In Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rosen, C.Schwebel, D. and Singer, J. 1997. “Preschoolers’ Attributions of Mental States in Pretense.Child Development 68: 11331142.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1956. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, 253329. University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Sellars (1963), Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1992. “What Is a Theory of Mental Representation?Mind 101: 243-61.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1996. Deconstructing the Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. and Nichols, S. 1992. Folk Psychology: Simulation or Tacit Theory. Mind & Language 7 (1): 3571.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1995. Second Thoughts on Simulation. In Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications, ed. Stone, A. and Davies, M.87108. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1997. “Cognitive Penetrability, Rationality, and Restricted Simulation.Mind & Language 12: 297326.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1998. “Theory Theory to the Max: A Critical notice of Gopnik & Meltzoff's Words, Thoughts, and Theories.” Mind & Language 13: 421-49.Google Scholar
Stich, S. and Ravenscroft, I. 1994. “What is Folk Psychology?Cognition 50: 1-3, 447-68.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wellman, H. and Estes, D. 1986. “Early Understanding of Mental Entities: A Reexamination of Childhood Realism.Child Development 57: 910-23.Google Scholar
Wimmer, H. and Hartl, M. 1991. “The Cartesian View and the Theory View of Mind: Developmental Evidence from Understanding False Belief in Self and Other.British journal of Developmental Psychology 9: 125-28.Google Scholar
Wimmer, H. and Perner, J. 1983. “Beliefs About Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children's Understanding of Deception.Cognition 13: 103128.Google Scholar
Wimmer, H.Hogrefe, G. and Perner, J. 1988. “Children's Understanding of Informational Access as a Source of Knowledge.Child Development 59: 386-96.Google Scholar
Young, A. 1994. “Neuropsychology of Awareness.” In Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience, ed. Revonsuo, A. and amppinen, M.173203. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.Google Scholar
Young, A. 1998. Face and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar