Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T10:47:59.095Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Word and Action: Reconciling Rules and Know-How in Moral Cognition*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Abstract

Recent work in cognitive science highlights the importance of exemplar- based know-how in supporting human expertise. Influenced by this model, certain accounts of moral knowledge now stress exemplarbased, non-sentential know-how at the expense of rule-and-principle based accounts. I shall argue, however, that moral thought and reason cannot be understood by reference to either of these roles alone. Moral cognition — like other forms of ‘advanced’ cognition — depends crucially on the subtle interplay and interaction of multiple factors and forces and especially (or so I argue) between the use of linguistic tools and formulations and more biologically basic forms of thought and reason.

Type
II. Biology and Moral Discourse
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Thanks to Bruce Hunter for some very helpful comments on an earlier draft.

1

Thanks to Bruce Hunter for pointing this out, and for some related comments concerning Kant.

References

Aristotle, 1972. The Nicomachean Ethics. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Arthur, W. B. 1994. “On the Evolution of Complexity.” In Complexity: Metaphors, Models, and Reality. Ed. Cowan, G.A.Pines, D. and Meltzer, D.Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Bakhtin, M. 1981. The Dialogic Imagination. Ed. Holquist, M.Austin: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Berk, L. 1994. “Why Children Talk to Themselves.” Scientific American, November: 7883.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.S. and Sejnowski, T.J. 1992. The Computational Brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1989. A Neurocomputational Perspective. Cambridge: MIT/ Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1995. The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1996a. “The Neural Representation of the Social World.” In Mind and Morals. Ed. May, L.Friedman, M. and Clark, A.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1996b. “Flanagan on Moral Knowledge.” In The Churchlands and Their Critics. Ed. McCauley, R.Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1989. Microcognition: Philosophy, Cognitive Science and Parallel Distributed Processing. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1993. Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts and Representational Change. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1996. “Connectionism, Moral Cognition and Collaborative Problem Solving.” In Minds and Morals. Ed. May, L.Friedman, M. and Clark, A.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1997a. “Economic Reason: The Interplay of Individual Learning and External Structure.” In The Frontiers of the New Institutional Economics. Ed. Drobak, J. and Nye, J.London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1997b. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. in press. “Minds, Brains and Tools: Comments on Dennett.” In Philosophers of Mental Representation. Ed. Clapin, H.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. and Thornton, C. 1997. “Trading Spaces: Connectionism and the Limits of Uninformed Learning.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20: 5767.Google Scholar
Dehaene, S. 1997. The Number Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dehaene, S.Spelke, E. et al. 1999. “Sources of Mathematical Thinking: Behavioral and Brain Imaging Evidence.” Science 284: 970–4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dennett, D. 1996. Kinds of Minds. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Donagan, A. 1977. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. and Dreyfus, S. 1990. “What is Morality? A Phenomenological Account of the Development of Ethical Expertise.” In Universalism vs. Communitarianism: Contemporary Debates in Ethics. Ed. Rasmussen, D.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. 1996. “Ethics Naturalized: Ethics as Human Ecology.” In Mind and Morals. Ed. May, L.Friedman, M. and Clark, A.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. and Lepore, E. 1993. “Reply to Churchland.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53: 679–82.Google Scholar
Fraser, N. 1989. Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1993. “Ethics and Cognitive Science.” Ethics 103: 337–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackendoff, R. 1996. “How Language Helps Us Think.Pragmatics and Cognition 4: 134.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. 1999. “Emergent Law and Order.” In The Biology of Business: Decoding the Natural Laws of Enterprise. Ed. Clippinger, J.San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.Google Scholar
Johnson, M. 1993. Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, E. 1781 (=A). A Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kant, E. 1787 (=B). Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kant, E. 1977. Critique of Practical Reason. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Khin Zaw, S. 1996. “Moral Rationality.” In Minds and Morals. Ed. May, C.Friedman, M. and Clark, A.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
McClelland, J. L. 1989. “Parallel Distributed Processing- Implications for Cognition and Development.” In Parallel Distributed Processing: Implications for Psychology and Neurobiology. Ed. Morris, R.G.M.Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McClelland, J.RumelhartL., D. L., D. and Hinton, G. 1986. “The Appeal of Parallel Distributed Processing.” In Rumelhart, D. E.McClelland, J. L. and the PDP Research Group, Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cogntion. Vol. 1. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1884. A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green & Co.Google Scholar
O, O'Neill 1989. Constructions of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rosch, E. 1973. “Natural Categories.” Cognitive Psychology 4: 324–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, E. and Medin, D. 1981. Categories and Concepts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterba, J. 1996. “Justifying Morality and the Challenge of Cognitive Science.” In Mind and Morals. Ed. May, L.Friedman, M. and Clark, A.Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, R.Oden, D. and Boyson, S. In press. “Language-naive Chimpanzees judge relations between relations in an abstract mapping task.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes.Google Scholar
Todorov, T. 1984. Mikhail Bakhtin: The Dialogical Principle. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Vygotsky, L. 1986. Thought and Language. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wellman, C. 1999. The Proliferation of Rights. Boulder, Co.: Westview.Google Scholar