Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T22:59:44.677Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Disability Discrimination and Patient-Sensitive Health-Related Quality of Life

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 November 2022

Lasse Nielsen*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, Department for the Study of Culture, University of Southern Denmark, Odense, Denmark
*

Abstract

It is generally accepted that morally justified healthcare rationing must be non-discriminatory and cost-effective. However, given conventional concepts of cost-effectiveness, resources spent on disabled people are spent less cost-effectively, ceteris paribus, than resources spent on non-disabled people. Thus, it is reasonable to assume that standard cost-effectiveness discriminates against the disabled. Call this the disability discrimination problem. Part of the disability discrimination involved in cost-effectiveness stems from the way in which health-related quality of life is accounted for and measured. This paper offers and defends a patient-sensitive account of health-related quality of life, which can effectively make cost-effectiveness less discriminatory against the disabled and thus more morally justified.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Bognar, G, Hirose, I. The Ethics of Health Care Rationing. London: Routledge; 2014 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ubel, P, DeKay, ML, Boran, J, Asch, DA. Cost-effectiveness Analysis in a Setting of Budget Constraints: Is it Equitable? New England Journal of Medicine 1996;334:1174–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2. Baron, J. Blind justice: Fairness to groups and the do-no-harm principle. Journal of Behavioural Decision Making 1995;8:7183 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rawlins, M, Dillon, A. NICE Discrimination. Journal of Medical Ethics 2005;31:683–4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

3. Nord, E, Pinto, JL, Richardson, J, Menzel, P, Ubel, P. Incorporating societal concerns for fairness in numerical valuations of health programmes. Health Economics 1999;8:2539 3.0.CO;2-H>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

4. Campbell, S, Nyholm, S, Walter, JK. Disability and the Good Life. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 2021;46:704–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5. Aas, S, Wasserman, D. Disability, disease, and health sufficiency. In: Fourie, C, Rid, A, eds. What is Enough? Sufficiency, Justice, and Health. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2017:164–83, p. 178 Google Scholar.

6. For different accounts of disability, see Barnes, E. The Minority Body: A Theory of Disability. Oxford: Oxford University Press CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Chap. 1; Bickenbach, J. Disability, health, and difference. In: Cureton, A, Wasserman, DT. eds. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Disability. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2020:4662 Google Scholar.

7. Note that 1 am here only referring to a difference in level of functioning and not welfare. That is, I am not implying anything about their overall happiness or quality of life.

8. For a useful comparison, see Arnesen, T, Nord, E. The value of DALY life: Problems with ethics and validity of disability adjusted life years. British Medical Journal 1999;319:1423–5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

9. Bognar, G. Does cost effectiveness unfairly discriminate against people with disabilities? Journal of Applied Philosophy 2010;27(4):394408 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10. Kamm, F. Aggregation, allocating scarce resources, and the disabled. Social Philosophy and Policy 2009;26(1):148–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kerstein, SJ. Dignity, disability, and lifespan. Journal of Applied Philosophy 2017;34(5):635–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11. The Standard Case is depicted with QALYs but could simply be translated to DALYs with the same effect of differential treatment.

12. Definition adopted and revised from Lippert-Rasmussen, K. Born Free and Equal: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Nature of Discrimination. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2013:15 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13. See note 12, Lippert-Rasmussen 2013; Hellman, D. When is Discrimination Wrong? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 2008 Google Scholar; Alexander, L. What makes wrongful discrimination wrong? Biases, preferences, stereotypes, and proxies. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1992;141(1):149219 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Brown JM. What makes disability discrimination wrong? Law and Philosophy 2021;40:1–31.

14. Hadorn, DC. The problem of discrimination in health care priority setting. JAMA 1992;268:1454–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Menzel, PT. Oregon’s denial: Disabilities and quality of life. Hasting Center Reports 1992;22:21–5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Singer, P, McKie, J, Kuhse, H, Richardson, J. Double jeopardy and the use of QALYs in health care allocation. Journal of Medical Ethics 1995;21:144–50CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Stein, MS. Utilitarianism and the disabled: distribution of resources. Bioethics 2004;16:119 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15. Harris, J. QALYfying the value of life. Journal of Medical Ethics 1987;13:117–23CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Kamm, F. Deciding whom to help, health-adjusted life years, and disabilities. In: Anand, S, Peters, F, Sen, A, eds. Public Health, Ethics and Equity. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2004:225–42Google Scholar.

16. Brock, D. Cost-effectiveness and disability discrimination. Economics and Philosophy 2009;25:2747 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ottesen, T. Lifetime QALY prioritarianism in priority setting. Journal of Medical Ethics 2013;39:175–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17. See note 16, Brock 2009.

18. Smith, D, Sherriff, R, Damschroder, L, Loewenstein, G, Ubel, P. Misremembering colostomies? former patients give lower rankings than do current patients. Health Psychology 2006;25:688–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19. For a useful discussion, see Hausman, D. Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2015:90–6Google Scholar.

20. Bognar, G. Cost-effectiveness analysis and disability discrimination. In: Cureton, A, Wasserman, D, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Disability. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2020:653–68Google Scholar.

21. Schramme, T. Theories of Health Justice: Just Enough Health. London: Rowman & Littlefield; 2018.Google Scholar

22. Needs, Wiggins D., Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987 Google Scholar.

23. Scanlon, T. Preferences and urgency. The Journal of Philosophy 1975:72(19):655–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24. Reader, S. Needs and Moral Necessity. London: Routledge; 2007:55 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25. See note 24, Reader 2007, p. 51.

26. Gustavsson, E. From needs to health care needs. Health Care Analysis 2014:22:2235 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

27. See note 26, Gustavsson 2014, p. 33.

28. Gustavsson calls this “condition-specificity”, see Gustavsson E. Patient with multiple needs for healthcare and priority to the worse off. Bioethics 2019;33:261–6.

29. See note 15, Harris 1987; Kamm 2004, p. 235.

30. See note 3, Nord et al. 1999.

31. See note 4, Campbell, Nyholm, Walter 2021, p. 721.

32. See note 5, Aas, Wasserman 2017, p. 178.

33. Boorse, CA. Rebuttal on health. In: Humber, JM, Almeider, RF, eds. What is Disease? Biomedical Ethics Reviews, Totowa, NJ: Humana Press; 1997:3134 Google Scholar.

34. Nordenfeldt, L. On the relevance and importance of the notion of disease. Theoretical Medicine 1993;14:277–85Google Scholar.

35. See note 10, Kamm 2009.

36. See note 10, Kerstein 2017.

37. See note 16, Brock 2009.