Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T05:12:08.170Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Social Samaritan Justice: When and Why Needy Fellow Citizens Have a Right to Assistance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 November 2015

LAURA VALENTINI*
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
*
Laura Valentini is Associate Professor of Political Science, Department of Government, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK (l.m.valentini@lse.ac.uk)

Abstract

In late 2012, Hurricane Sandy hit the East Coast of the U.S., causing much suffering and devastation. Those who could have easily helped Sandy's victims had a duty to do so. But was this a rightfully enforceable duty of justice, or a nonenforceable duty of beneficence? The answer to this question is often thought to depend on the kind of help offered: the provision of immediate bodily services is not enforceable; the transfer of material resources is. I argue that this double standard is unjustified, and defend a version of what I call “social samaritanism.” On this view, within political communities, the duty to help the needy—whether via bodily services or resource transfers—is always an enforceable demand of justice, except when the needy are reckless; across independent political communities, it is always a matter of beneficence. I defend this alternative double standard, and consider its implications for the case of Sandy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Anderson, Elizabeth S. 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109 (2): 287337.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard J. 2000. “Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism.” Ethics 110 (2): 339–49.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1991. “Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective.” In Liberty and Justice: Essays in Political Theory 2, 182210. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1987. “Justice and Charity.” Ethics 97 (3): 558–75.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2003. “Facts and Principles.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 31 (3): 211–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Stephanie. 2013. “Collectives’ Duties and Collectivization Duties.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (2): 231–48.Google Scholar
Cumminskey, David. 1996. Kantian Consequentialism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
D'Anna, Eddie. 2012. “As Hurricane Sandy Nears, Mayor Bloomberg Orders Evacuation of Zone A; Thousands of Staten Islanders Affected.” Staten Island Advance - SILive.com. http://www.silive.com/news/index.ssf/2012/10/mayor_bloomberg.html.Google Scholar
Daniels, Norman. 2013. “Reflective Equilibrium.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N., Winter 2013. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflective-equilibrium/.Google Scholar
Duff, Antony. 2013. “Theories of Criminal Law.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/criminal-law/.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2002. “Good Samaritanism: A Matter of Justice.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5 (4): 128–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1984. “The Moral and Legal Responsibility of the Bad Samaritan.” Criminal Justice Ethics 3 (1): 5669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to Self. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
French, Peter A. 1984. Collective and Corporate Responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Gilabert, Pablo. 2010. “Kant and the Claims of the Poor.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (2): 382418.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 1989. On Social Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1955. “Are There Any Natural Rights?The Philosophical Review 64 (2): 175–91.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara. 1984. “Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons.” Ethics 94 (4): 577602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hernandez, Raymond. 2013. “Congress Gives Final Approval to Hurricane Sandy Aid.” The New York Times, January 28, sec. N.Y./Region. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/29/nyregion/congress-gives-final-approval-to-hurricane-sandy-aid.html.Google Scholar
Heyman, Steven J. 1994. “Foundations of the Duty to Rescue.” Vanderbilt Law Review 47: 674755.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas E. Jr. 2002. “Meeting Needs and Doing Favors.” In Human Welfare and Moral Worth: Kantian Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 201–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Julius, A. J. 2006. “Nagel's Atlas.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 34 (2): 176–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, Frances M. 2002. “Rights.” In The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, eds. Coleman, Jules L., Himma, Kenneth E., and Shapiro, Scott J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 476513.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Metaphysical Elements of Justice: Part I of The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Ladd, John. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Kaufman, Alexander. 2004. “Choice, Responsibility and Equality.” Political Studies 52 (4): 819–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lamont, W. D. 1941. “Justice: Distributive and Corrective.” Philosophy 16 (61): 318.Google Scholar
Law, Jonathan, and Martin, Elizabeth A.. 2009. A Dictionary of Law. 7th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. 2013. “Justice and Bad Luck.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N., Fall 2009. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/justice-bad-luck/.Google Scholar
List, Christian, and Pettit, Philip. 2011. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Loriaux, Sylvie. 2006. “Beneficence and Distributive Justice in a Globalising World.” Global Society 20 (3): 251–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malm, H. M. 1995. “Liberalism, Bad Samaritan Law, and Legal Paternalism.” Ethics 106 (1): 431.Google Scholar
Malm, H. M. 2000. “Bad Samaritan Laws: Harm, Help, or Hype?Law and Philosophy 19 (6): 707–50.Google Scholar
Marshall, S. E., and Duff, R. A.. 1998. “Criminalization and Sharing Wrongs.” Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 11 (01): 722.Google Scholar
Martin, Douglas. 1989. “About New York; Kitty Genovese: Would New York Still Turn Away?” The New York Times, March 11, sec. N.Y./Region. http://www.nytimes.com/1989/03/11/nyregion/about-new-york-kitty-genovese-would-new-york-still-turn-away.html.Google Scholar
McDermott, Daniel. 2008. “Analytic Political Philosophy.” In Political Theory: Methods and Approaches, eds. Leopold, David and Stears, Marc, 1128. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McIntyre, Alison. 1994. “Guilty Bystanders? On the Legitimacy of Duty to Rescue Statutes.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 23 (2): 157–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, David. 2001. “Distributing Responsibilities.” Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4): 453–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, David. 2002. “‘Are They My Poor?’: The Problem of Altruism in the World of Strangers.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5 (4): 106–27.Google Scholar
Murphy, Liam B. 2000. Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Olsaretti, Serena. 2009. “Responsibility and the Consequences of Choice.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1): 165–88.Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 1996. Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Øverland, Gerhard. 2009. “Forced Assistance.” Law and Philosophy 28 (2): 203–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patten, Alan. 2012. “Liberal Neutrality: A Reinterpretation and Defense.” Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (3): 249–72.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2008. World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms. Cambridge, UK: Polity.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2000. “Three Duties to Rescue: Moral, Civil, and Criminal.” Law and Philosophy 19 (6): 751–79.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2004a. “Authority and Coercion.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32 (1): 235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2004b. “Justice and Responsibility.” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 17 (2): 361–86.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2006. “Beyond the Harm Principle.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 34 (3): 215–45.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2009. Force and Freedom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ronzoni, Miriam. 2009. “The Global Order: A Case of Background Injustice? A Practice-Dependent Account.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37 (3): 229–56.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2007. “Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (1): 339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scordato, Marin, Roger. 2008. “Understanding the Absence of a Duty to Reasonably Rescue in American Tort Law.” Tulane Law Review 82 (4): 1447–503.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2005. “Human Rights and Capabilities.” Journal of Human Development 6 (2): 151–66.Google Scholar
Silver, Jay Sterling. 2012. “Can the Law Make ‘Bad Samaritans’ Be Decent?” The New York Times, November 6, sec. Opinion. http://www.nytimes.com/2012/11/07/opinion/can-the-law-make-bad-samaritans-be-decent.html.Google Scholar
Singer, Peter. 1972. “Famine, Affluence, and Morality.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (3): 229–43.Google Scholar
Stilz, Anna. 2009. Liberal Loyalty: Freedom, Obligation, and the State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stohr, Karen. 2011. “Kantian Beneficence and the Problem of Obligatory Aid.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1): 4567.Google Scholar
Tuomela, Raimo. 2013. Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2011a. “Coercion and (Global) Justice.” American Political Science Review 105 (01): 205–20.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2011b. Justice in a Globalized World: A Normative Framework. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2013. “Justice, Charity, and Disaster Relief: What, If Anything, Is Owed to Haiti, Japan and New Zealand?American Journal of Political Science 57 (2): 491503.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1981. “A Right to Do Wrong.” Ethics 92 (1): 2139.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1986. “Welfare and the Images of Charity.” The Philosophical Quarterly 36 (145): 463–82.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar