Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T15:55:40.676Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rights, Boundaries, and the Bonds of Community: A Qualified Defense of Moral Parochialism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 June 1985

Richard Dagger*
Affiliation:
Arizona State University

Abstract

One effect of the cosmopolitan turn in recent political philosophy is that widely held beliefs and intuitions are being called into question. My purpose here is to scrutinize one of these beliefs—that we should attend to the needs of our compatriots before the needs of the foreigners—from the perspective of a rights-based theory. After sketching a theory that takes the right of autonomy as its cornerstone, I consider four arguments that might support the intuition that compatriots take priority. Only one of the four is sound, I conclude, and even this argument, the argument from reciprocity, supports the intuition only in a highly qualified form.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arneson, R. The principle of fairness and free-rider problems. Ethics, 1982, 92, 616633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. L. A plea for excuses. In Austin, J. L., Philosophical papers. Urmson, J. O. & Warnock, G. J. (Eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970.Google Scholar
Barry, B. Humanity and justice in global perspective. NOMOS XXIV: Ethics, economics, and the law. Pennock, J. R. & Chapman, J. W. (Eds.). New York: New York University Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. Political theory and international relations. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979.Google Scholar
Bell, N. K. Nozick and the principle of fairness. Social Theory and Practice, 1978, 5, 6573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benn, S. Human rights—for whom and for what? Human rights. Kamenka, E. & Tay, A. Ehr-Soon (Eds.). New York: St. Martin's Press, 1978.Google Scholar
Brown, P., & MacLean, D. (Eds.). Human rights and U.S. foreign policy. Lexington, Mass.: Lexington Books, 1979.Google Scholar
Brown, P., & Shue, H. (Eds.). Food policy: The responsibility of the United States in life and death choices. New York: The Free Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Brown, P., & Shue, H. (Eds.). Boundaries: National autonomy and its limits. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1981.Google Scholar
Dagger, R. Harm, utility, and the obligation to obey the law. Archiv fur Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 1982, 68, 102108.Google Scholar
Dworkin, G. Paternalism. Morality and the Law. Wasserstrom, R. (Ed.). Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1971.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, P. J. Voluntary and involuntary acts. Oxford essays in jurisprudence. Guest, A. G. (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961.Google Scholar
Flathman, R. The practice of rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. The moral significance of national boundaries. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 1982, 7, 437453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R. Political theory and public policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Gorovitz, S. Bigotry, loyalty, and malnutrition. Food policy: The responsibility of the U.S. in life and death choices. Brown, P. & Shue, H. (Eds.). New York: The Free Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. Are there any natural rights? Human rights. Melden, A. I. (Ed.). Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1970.Google Scholar
Lackey, D. Missiles and morals: A utilitarian look at nuclear deterrence. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1982, 11, 189231.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. Forms and limits of utilitarianism. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, J. Consent, coercion, and hard choices. Virginia Law Review, 1981, 67, 7995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, J. Three mistakes about retributivism. In Murphy, J., Retribution, justice, and therapy. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. Anarchy, state, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books, 1974.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richards, D.A.J. International distributive justice. NOMOS XXIV: Ethics, economics, and the law. Pennock, J. R. & Chapman, J. W. (Eds.). New York: New York University Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Shue, H. Basic rights: Subsistence, affluence, and U.S. foreign policy. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Shue, H. Rights in the light of duties. Human rights and U.S. foreign policy. Brown, P. & MacLean, D. (Eds.). Lexington, Mass.: Lexington Books, 1979.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. J. Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979.Google Scholar
Smith, M. B. E. Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law? Law in Philosophical Perspective. Feinberg, J. & Gross, H. (Eds.). Encino and Belmont, Calif.: Dickenson Publishing Co., 1977.Google Scholar
Sullivan, D. Rules, fairness, and formal justice. Ethics, 1975, 85, 322331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, M. Just and unjust wars. New York: Basic Books, 1977.Google Scholar