Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T18:08:37.926Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rationality, Morality, and Impossibility Theorems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Fred M. Frohock*
Affiliation:
Syracuse University

Abstract

The impossibility theorem developed by Kenneth Arrow has implications for both rationality and morality in political thought. Transitivity in a collective ordering can be assured only with a decisive set, but this outcome is acknowledged as morally undesirable. The alternatives exhibited by the theorem thus seem to require a choice between rationality and morality. But exit routes can be cut out of this dilemma with the idea of a conditional ordering, one where warranting factors attach to a ranking of alternatives. Conditional orderings form two senses of collective rationality. One is represented by compound directives, which avoid the rational problems of the theorem by warranting local orderings. The second is moral fusion, which requires a reasoned dominance in collective outcomes. These two forms of conditional rationality put into relief the restricted scope of the composition rules and individualism of Arrow's theorem, and suggest alternative relationships of individual and social whole.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arrow, Kenneth (1963; first published 1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth (1967). “Values and Collective Decision Making.” In Laslett, P. and Runciman, W. G. (eds.), Philosophy, Politics and Society. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth (1977). “Extended Sympathy and the Possibility of Social Choice.” American Economic Review 67: 219–25.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (1946). Language, Truth and Logic. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton (1962). “The Two Faces of Power.” American Political Science Review 56:947–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, Kurt (1958). The Moral Point of View. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Baldwin, David A. (1979). “Power and Social Exchange.” American Political Science Review 72: 1229–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy (1823). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Blau, Julian H. (1972). “A Direct Proof of Arrow's Theorem.” Econometrica 40: 6167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braybrooke, David, and Lindblom, Charles (1963). A Strategy of Decision. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Brecht, Arnold (1959). Political Theory. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, Robert, and Lindblom, Charles (1953). Politics, Economics and Welfare. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert, and Lindblom, Charles (1956). A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa (1958). “Moral Arguments.” Mind. 67: 502–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gewirth, Alan (1978). Reason and Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alan H. (1976). “Rawls's Original Position and the Difference Principle.” The Journal of Philosophy 73: 845–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1952). The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1965). Freedom and Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, John (1955). “Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility.” Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, John (1975). “Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality?American Political Science Review 69: 595606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holden, Barry (1974). The Nature of Democracy. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney, ed. (1967). Human Values and Economic Policy. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Hudson, W. D. (1970). Modern Moral Philosophy. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1959). Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. New York: Liberal Arts.Google Scholar
Kelly, Jerry S. (1978). Arrow Impossibility Theorems. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Lukes, Steven (1974). Power, A Radical View. New York: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1966). A Short History of Ethics. New York: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macpherson, C. B. (1967). The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macpherson, C. B. (1973). Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval. New York: Oxford.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1969). “Newcomb's Problem and Two Principles of Choice.” In Rescher, Nicholas (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Plott, Charles R. (1971). “Recent Results in the Theory of Voting.” In Intriligator, M. (ed.), Frontiers of Quantitative Economics. Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
Plott, Charles R. (1976). “Axiomatic Social Choice Theory: An Overview and Interpretation.” American Journal of Political Science 20: 511–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiman, Jeffrey (1972). In Defense of Political Philosophy. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas (1966). Distributive Justice. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Reynolds, James, and Paris, David (1979). “The Concept of Choice and Arrow's Theorem.” Ethics 89: 354–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riker, William, and Ordeshook, Peter (1973). An Introduction to Positive Political Theory. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall).Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1978). On the Social Contract. Edited by Masters, Roger. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (1974). “Choice, Ordertags and Morality.” In Korner, Stephen (ed.), Practical Reason. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (1977). “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory.” Philosophy and Public Affairs.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (1977). “Social Choice Theory: A Re-Examination.” Econometrica 45: 5389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1944). Ethics and Language. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Strasnick, Steven (1976a). “Social Choice and the Derivation of Rawls's Difference Principle.” The Journal of Philosophy 73: 8599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strasnick, Steven (1976b). “The Problem of Social Choice: Arrow to Rawls.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 5: 241–73.Google Scholar
Strasnick, Steven (1977). “Ordinality and the Spirit of the Justified Dictator.” Social Research 44: 668–90.Google Scholar
Toulmin, Stephen (1960). The Place of Reason in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ullman-Margalit, Edna, and Morgenbesser, Sidney (1977). “Picking and Choosing.” Social Research 44: 757–85.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1968). The Emotive Theory of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul (1970). In Defense of Anarchism. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul (1976). “On Strasnick's ‘Derivation’ of Rawls's Difference Principle.” The Journal of Philosophy 73: 849–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar