Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
Hostname: page-component-99c86f546-swqlm Total loading time: 1.719 Render date: 2021-12-01T04:21:47.182Z Has data issue: true Feature Flags: { "shouldUseShareProductTool": true, "shouldUseHypothesis": true, "isUnsiloEnabled": true, "metricsAbstractViews": false, "figures": true, "newCiteModal": false, "newCitedByModal": true, "newEcommerce": true, "newUsageEvents": true }

Dutch Book Arguments

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 July 2020

Richard Pettigrew
Affiliation:
University of Bristol

Summary

Our beliefs come in degrees. I'm 70% confident it will rain tomorrow, and 0.001% sure my lottery ticket will win. What's more, we think these degrees of belief should abide by certain principles if they are to be rational. For instance, you shouldn't believe that a person's taller than 6ft more strongly than you believe that they're taller than 5ft, since the former entails the latter. In Dutch Book arguments, we try to establish the principles of rationality for degrees of belief by appealing to their role in guiding decisions. In particular, we show that degrees of belief that don't satisfy the principles will always guide action in some way that is bad or undesirable. In this Element, we present Dutch Book arguments for the principles of Probabilism, Conditionalization, and the Reflection Principle, among others, and we formulate and consider the most serious objections to them.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108581813
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 17 September 2020
Copyright
© Richard Pettigrew 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: cri- tique des postulats et axiomes de l’ecole Americaine. Econometrica, 21(4), 503–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armendt, B. (1993). Dutch Books, Additivity, and Utility Theory. Philosoph- ical Topics, 21 (1).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arntzenius, F. (2002). Reflections on Sleeping Beauty. Analysis, 62(2), 5362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arntzenius, F. (2003). Some Problems for Conditionalization and Reflection. Journal of Philosophy, 100(356–70).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arntzenius, F., Elga, A., & Hawthorne, J. (2004). Bayesianism, Infinite Deci- sions, and Binding. Mind, 113, 251–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berger, J. O. (1985). Statistical Decision Theory and Bayesian Analysis. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernoulli, D. (1738 [1954]). Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk. Econometrica, 22(1), 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, S., & Vandenberghe, L. (2004). Convex Optimization. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, S. (2016). Imprecise Probabilities. In Zalta, E. N(Ed.), StanfordEncy- clopedia ofPhilosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Bradley, S. (2017). Nonclassical Probability and Convex Hulls. Erkenntnis, 82(1), 87101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, S., & Steele, K. (2014). Should Subjective Probabilities Be Sharp? Episteme, 11(3), 277–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Briggs, R. A. (2009). Distorted Reflection. Philosophical Review, 118(1), 5985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Briggs, R. A. (2010). Putting a Value on Beauty. In Gendler, T. S. & Hawthorne, J (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 3 (pp. 334). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. A., & Pettigrew, R. (2018). An Accuracy-Dominance Argument for Conditionalization. Nous.Google Scholar
Buchak, L. (2013). Risk and Rationality. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (1991). Clever Bookies and Coherent Beliefs. Philosophical Review, 100(2), 229–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (1996). Dutch-Book Arguments Depragmatized: Epistemic Consistency for Partial Believers. The Journal of Philosophy, 93(9), 450–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D., McKinsey, J. C. C., & Suppes, P. (1955). Outlines of a Formal Theory of Value, I. Philosophy of Science, 22(2), 140–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1937 [1980]). Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources. In Kyburg, H. E. & Smokler, H. E. K. (Eds.), Studies in Subjective Probability. Huntington, NY: Robert E. Kreiger Publishing Co.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1972). Probability, Induction, and Statistics. London: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of Probability, vol. I. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Dempster, A. P. (1968). A Generalization of Bayesian Inference. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society Series B (Methodological), 30, 205–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easwaran, K. (2016). Dr Truthlove, Or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Bayesian Probabilities. Nous, 50(4), 816–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easwaran, K., & Fitelson, B. (2015). Accuracy, Coherence, and Evidence. In Gendler, T. S. & Hawthorne, J (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 5, (pp. 6196). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. (2000). Self-Locating Belief and the Sleeping Beauty Problem. Analysis, 60(2), 143–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. (2010). Subjective Probabilities Should Be Sharp. Philosophers’ Imprint, 10(5), 111.Google Scholar
Fishburn, P. C. (1986). The Axioms of Subjective Probability. Statistical Science, 1(3), 335–58.Google Scholar
Gerla, B. (2000). MV-Algebras, Multiple Bets and Subjective States. Interna- tional Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 25, 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin Expected Utility with Non- Unique Prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hajek, A. (2008). Dutch Book Arguments. In Anand, P, Pattanaik, P, & Puppe, C (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rational and Social Choice (pp. 17395). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hedden, B. (2013). Incoherence without Exploitability. Nous, 47(3), 482495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1989). Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Jaffray, J.-Y. (1989). Coherent Bets under Partially Resolving Uncertainty and Belief Functions. Theory and Decision, 26, 99105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. (1983). The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. (1999). The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cam- bridge Studies in Probability, Induction, and Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. M. (2010). A Defense of Imprecise Credences in Inference and Decision Making. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 281322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. (1974). On Indeterminate Probabilities. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 391418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinstein, B. A. (2017). A Pragmatist’s Guide to Epistemic Utility. Philosophy of Science, 84(4), 613–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1980). A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance. In Jeffrey, R. C. (Ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, vol. II. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1981). Causal Decision Theory. Australasian JournalofPhilosophy, 59, 530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1999). Why Conditionalize? In Papers in Metaphysics andEpiste- mology (pp. 4037). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (2001). Sleeping Beauty: Reply to Elga. Analysis, 61(3), 171–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarlane, J., & Kolodny, N. (2010). Ifs and Oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 115–43.Google Scholar
Mahtani, A. (2012). Diachronic Dutch Book Arguments. Philosophical Review, 121(3), 443–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahtani, A. (2015). Dutch Books, Coherence, and Logical Consistency. Nous, 49(3), 522–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGee, V (1999). An Airtight Dutch Book. Analysis, 59(4), 257–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, S. (2015). Credal Dilemmas. Nous, 49(4), 665–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, S. (2018). Probabilistic Knowledge. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. (ms). What We Together Do.Google Scholar
Paris, J. B. (2001). A Note on the Dutch Book Method. In Proceedings of the 2nd International Symposium on Imprecise Probabilities and Their Applications, ISIPTA, Ithaca, NY (pp. 301–6).Oxford, UK: Shaker.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2012). Accuracy, Chance, and the Principal Principle. Philo- sophical Review, 121(2), 241–75.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2013). A New Epistemic Utility Argument for the Principal Principle. Episteme, 10(1), 1935.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2019a). On the Expected Utility Objection to the Dutch Book Argument for Probabilism. Nous (DOI:10.1111/nous.12286).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2019b). Is Conditionalization, and Why Should We Do It? Philosophical Studies (DOI:10.1007/s11098-019-01377-y).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piccione, M. & Rubinstein, A. (1997). On the Interpretation of Decision Problems with Imperfect Recall. Games and Economical Behavior, 20, 324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Predd, J., Seiringer, R., Lieb, E. H., Osherson, D., Poor, V., & Kulkarni, S. (2009). Probabilistic Coherence and Proper Scoring Rules. IEEE Transac- tions of Information Theory, 55(10), 4786–92.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1926 [1931]). Truth and Probability. In Braithwaite, R. B (Ed.), The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, chap. VII (pp. 15698). London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.Google Scholar
Rinard, S. (2015). A Decision Theory for Imprecise Probabilities. Philoso- phers’ Imprint, 15(7), 116.Google Scholar
Rothschild, D. (2019). Lockean Beliefs, Dutch Books, and Scoring Systems. Review of Symbolic Logic.Google Scholar
Sahlin, N.-E., & Weirich, P. (2013). Unsharp Sharpness. Theoria, 80(1), 100–3.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. (1971). Elicitation of Personal Probabilities and Expectations. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 66(336), 783801.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schervish, M. J. (1989). A General Method for Comparing Probability Asses- sors. The Annals of Statistics, 17, 1856–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schick, F. (1986). Dutch Bookies and Money Pumps. The Journal of Philoso- phy, 83(2), 112–19.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. (2004). A Contrast between Two Decision Rules for Use with (Convex) Sets of Probabilities: Gamma-Maximin versus E-Admissibility. Synthese, 140, 6988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seidenfeld, T., Schervish, M. J., & Kadane, J. B. (1995). A Representation of Partially Ordered Preferences. Annals of Statistics, 23, 2168–217.Google Scholar
Shafer, G. (1976). A Mathematical Theory of Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1987). Coherence. In Rescher, N (Ed.), Scientific Inquiry in Philosophical Perspective (pp. 22542). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1993). A Mistake in Dynamic Coherence Arguments? Philosophy ofScience, 60(2), 320–8.Google Scholar
Talbott, W. J. (1991). Two Principles of Bayesian Epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 62(2), 135–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. (1984). Belief and the Will. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 235–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. (1990). Figures in a Probability Landscape. In Dunn, J. M. & Gupta, A (Eds.), Truth or Consequences (pp. 34556). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vineberg, S. (2001). The Notion of Consistency for Partial Belief. Philosophi- cal Studies, 102, 281–96.Google Scholar
Vineberg, S. (2016). Dutch Book Arguments. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), Stan- ford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Walley, P. (1991). StatisticalReasoningwith Imprecise Probabilities, vol. 42 of Monographs on Statistics and Applied Probability. London: Chapman and Hall.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, J. R. G. (2012a). Generalized Probabilism: Dutch Books and Accu- racy Domination. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(5), 811–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, J. R. G. (2012b). Gradational Accuracy and Non-classical Semantics. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(4), 513–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, J. R. G. (2014). Decision-Making under Indeterminacy. Philoso- phers’ Imprint, 14(4), 134.Google Scholar
Williamson, J. (1999). Countable Additivity and Subjective Probability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 401–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wronski, L., & Godziszewski, M. T. (2017). The Stubborn Non- probabilist—‘Negation Incoherence’ and a New Way to Block the Dutch Book Argument. In LORI 2017: Logic, Rationality, and Interaction, Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer.Google Scholar
6
Cited by

Send element to Kindle

To send this element to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about sending to your Kindle.

Note you can select to send to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be sent to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Dutch Book Arguments
Available formats
×

Send element to Dropbox

To send content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about sending content to Dropbox.

Dutch Book Arguments
Available formats
×

Send element to Google Drive

To send content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about sending content to Google Drive.

Dutch Book Arguments
Available formats
×