Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Cited by 1
  • Print publication year: 2010
  • Online publication date: October 2010

9 - Parliamentary sovereignty and statutory interpretation

Summary

Introduction

How statutes are interpreted is crucial to the implementation of the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. The doctrine maintains that every statute that Parliament enacts is legally valid, and therefore that all citizens and officials, including the courts, are legally obligated to obey it. The courts' legal obligation is therefore to interpret and apply every statute in a way that is consistent with Parliament's legal authority to enact it, and their corresponding obligation to obey it. In a small number of cases, what is called ‘interpretation’ might be tantamount to disobedience under cover of a ‘noble lie’. But if that were to become more routine, and generally condoned by the other branches of government, Parliament would no longer be sovereign.

Statutory interpretation is central to debates about many specific issues discussed in the next chapter. The nature and justification of the ultra vires doctrine in administrative law, the protection of common law principles by ‘presumptions’ of legislative intention, the judicial response to statutes in cases such as Anisminic and Factortame, all raise questions about the relationship between statutory interpretation and parliamentary sovereignty. But the topic of this chapter is statutory interpretation in general, including in Australia and New Zealand as well as in Britain, and not in cases to which the Human Rights Act 1998 (UK) applies.

There are two possible methods of investigating how the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty helps determine the way in which statutes should be interpreted. The first is normative and deductive.

Ekins, R., ‘The Relevance of the Rule of RecognitionAustralian Journal of Legal Philosophy 31 (2006) 95 at 103
Goldsworthy, J., The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), p. 1
Rotunda, Ronald D. and Nowak, John E., Treatise on Constitutional Law: Substance and Procedure (3rd edn) (St Paul Minn.: Thomson/West, 1999), § 15.1
Kent, James, Commentaries on American Law (10th edn) (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1860), p.503
Cooley, Thomas M., A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations Which Rest Upon the Legislative Power of the States of the American Union (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1868), pp. 87–9
Pound, Roscoe, ‘Common Law and LegislationHarvard Law Review 21 (1908) 383 at 392
Edlin, D., Judges and Unjust Laws (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2008), p. 51
Greenawalt, Kent, Legislation: Statutory Interpretation – Twenty Questions (New York: Foundation Press, 1999), p. 23
MacCormick, D. Neil and Summers, Robert S. (eds.), Interpreting Statutes: A Comparative Study (Aldershot: Dartmouth, 1991), 407 at p. 450
Eskridge, W., ‘Spinning Legislative SupremacyGeorgia Law Review 78 (1989) 319
Farber, D., ‘Statutory Interpretation and Legislative SupremacyGeorgia Law Review 78 (1989) 281
Correia, E.O., ‘A Legislative Conception of Legislative SupremacyCase W Res L Rev. 42 (1992) 1129
Maltz, E.M., ‘Rhetoric and Reality in the Theory of Statutory Interpretation: Underenforcement, Overenforcement, and the Problem of Legislative SupremacyBUL Rev 71 (1981) 767
Manning, J., ‘Textualism and the Equity of the StatuteColumbia Law Review 101 (2001) 1 at 6–7 and 9–22
Goldsworthy, J., ‘Raz on Constitutional InterpretationLaw and Philosophy 22 (2003) 167
Dickerson, R., The Interpretation and Application of Statutes (Boston: Little Brown, 1975), pp. 2–5
Whittington, K., Constitutional Interpretation: Textual Meaning, Original Intent, and Judicial Review (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1999), pp. 5–9
Altman, A., Critical Legal Studies, a Liberal Critique (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990)
Schauer, F., Playing By the Rules (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991)
Pound, R., ‘Spurious InterpretationColumbia Law Review 6 (1907) 379
Easterbrook, F., ‘The Role of Original Intent in Statutory ConstructionHarvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 11 (1988) 61
Markesinis, B.S. (ed.), The Clifford Chance Millennium Lectures; The Coming Together of the Common Law and the Civil Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000) pp. 79 and 81
Hurd, H., ‘Sovereignty in SilenceYale Law Journal 99 (1990) 945 at 966
Bennion, F.A.R., Statutory Interpretation (2nd edn) (London: Butterworths, 1992), pp. 668–9
Bell, J. and Engle, G., Statutory Interpretation (3rd edn) (London: Butterworths, 1995), pp. 67–8
Thesis, D. Phil, The Nature of Legislative Intent (University of Oxford, 26 March 2009)
Sperber, D. and Wilson, D., ‘Pragmatics’, in Jackson, F. and Smith, M. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005)
Marmor, A., ‘The Immorality of TextualismLoyola University Law Review 38 (2005) 2063
Simmonds, N.E., ‘Between Positivism and IdealismCambridge Law Journal 50 (1991) 308 at 311–12
Searle, J., ‘Literal Meaning’, in his Expression and Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 117 at p. 127
Goldsworthy, J., ‘Implications in Language, Law and the Constitution’, in Lindell, G. (ed.), Future Directions in Australian Constitutional Law (Sydney: Federation Press, 1994), 150 at p. 160–1
Searle, J.R., Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), p. 142
Searle, J., Keifer, F. and Bierwisch, M. (eds.), Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics (Holland: Reidel, 1980), p. 228
Martinich, A.P., Communication and Reference (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1984), p. 45
Dascal, M., Pragmatics and the Philosophy of Mind I (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1983), p. 86
Goldsworthy, J., ‘Marmor on Meaning, Interpretation, and Legislative IntentionLegal Theory 1 (1995) 439 at 461–3
Kramer, A., ‘Implication in Fact as an Instance of Contractual InterpretationOxford Journal of Legal Studies 63 (2004) 384 at 385
Bell, J., ‘Studying StatutesOxford Journal of Legal Studies 13 (1993) 130 at 133
Kavanagh, A., Constitutional Review Under the UK Human Rights Act (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), p. 99
Grice, H.P., Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1989), chs. 2 and 3
Evans, J., ‘Reading Down Statutes’, in R. Bigwood (ed.), The Statute, Making and Meaning (Wellington: LexisNexis, 2004), p. 123
Peden, E., Good Faith in the Interpretation of Contracts (Sydney: LexisNexis Butterworths, 2003), pp. 60–71
Lucke, H., ‘Ad Hoc Implications in Written ContractsAdelaide Law Review 5 (1973) 32 at 34
Allan, T.R.S., ‘Legislative Supremacy and the Rule of Law: Democracy and ConstitutionalismCambridge Law Journal 44 (1985) 111 at 117–18
Goldsworthy, J., ‘Moderate versus Strong Intentionalism: Knapp and Michaels RevisitedSan Diego Law Review 42 (2005) 669
Maxwell, P.B., On the Interpretation of Statutes (London: W. Maxwell & Son, 1875), pp. 20–1
Langan, P., Maxwell on the Interpretation of Statutes (12th edn) (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1969), pp. 47–50
Driedger, E., Construction of Statutes (2nd edn) (Toronto: Butterworths, 1983), pp. 149–51
Devenish, G., Interpretation of Statutes (South Africa: Juta & Co., 1992), pp. 127–9 and 130–3
Gifford, D., Statutory Interpretation (Sydney: Law Book, 1990), pp. 117–19
Evans, J., Statutory Interpretation; Problems of Communication (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1988), ch. 12
Manning, J., ‘Textualism and the Equity of the Statute’, Columbia Law Review 101 (2001) 1 at 6–7 and 9–22
Loveland, I., ‘Redefining Parliamentary Sovereignty? A New Perspective on the Search for Meaning in LawParliamentary Affairs 46 (1993) 319
Fuller, L., ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor HartHarvard Law Review 71 (1958) 630 at 662–9
Marmor, Andrei, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 136–7
Schauer, Frederick, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), pp. 209–10
Meyer, Linda (ed.), Rules and Reasoning: Essays in Honour of Fred Schauer (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1999), 79 at p. 90
Dworkin, R., Law's Empire (Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), p. 16
Raz, Joseph, Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 359
Posner, Richard A., The Problems of Jurisprudence (Cambridge Mass., Harvard University Press, 1990), pp. 269–73
Moore, Michael S., ‘The Semantics of JudgingSouthern California Law Review 54 (1980) 151 at 263–5
Moore, Michael S., ‘A Natural Law Theory of InterpretationSouthern California Law Review 58 (1985) 277 at 354
Allan, T.R.S., ‘Legislative Supremacy and Legislative Intent: A Reply to Professor CraigOxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (2004) 563 at 567–8 and 570 (on Dworkin)
Allan, T.R.S., ‘Legislative Supremacy and Legislative Intention: Interpretation, Meaning, and AuthorityCambridge Law Journal 63 (2004) 685 at 694
Ekins, R., ‘The Relevance of the Rule of RecognitionAustralian J Legal Philosophy 31 (2006) 95, 100
Allan, T.R.S., Law, Liberty and Justice: the Legal Foundations of British Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), p. 17
Dworkin, R., ‘Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe and NerveFordham Law Review 65 (1997)
Dworkin, R., Freedom's Law; The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 292–3
Scalia, A., A Matter of Interpretation; Federal Courts and the Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997)
McConnell, M., ‘The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: a Comment on Ronald Dworkin's “Moral Reading” of the ConstitutionFordham Law Review 65 (1997)
Goldsworthy, J., ‘Dworkin as an OriginalistConstitutional Commentary 17 (2000) 49
Pearce, D. and Geddes, R., Statutory Interpretation in Australia (3rd edn) (Sydney: Butterworths, 1988), pp. 15 and 63
Bowers, F., Linguistic Aspects of Legislative Expression (Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press, 1989), pp. 8–9
Black, H., Handbook on the Construction and Interpretation of the Laws (St. Paul, Minn.: West Pub. Co., 1896)
Chrimes, S.B., English Constitutional Ideas in the Fifteenth Century (New York, 1966 reprint)
Hamburger, P., Law and Judicial Duty (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2008), pp. 52–8
Berger, R., ‘The Founders Views – According to Jefferson PowellTexas Law Review 67 (1989) 1033 at 1059–65
Llewellyn, K., ‘Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How Statutes Are to be ConstruedVanderbilt Law Review 3 (1950) 395