Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T14:51:18.430Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Competing Conceptions of Public Reason

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 December 2010

Ronald C. Den Otter
Affiliation:
California Polytechnic State University
Get access

Summary

In the previous chapter, I tried to show how a concern about public justification emerges when the state legislates on the basis of reasons that reasonable people may be justified in rejecting. In exercising the power of judicial review, the judge assesses the quality of the reasons that the state has offered on behalf of the law in question. The less controversial the underlying reasons, the more publicly justified, and thus legitimate, that law is likely to be. After taking into account a presumption of freedom and equality, if the judge concludes that a reasonable person would accept those reasons, then the law is constitutional. If a reasonable person would reject the reasons, then the law is unconstitutional. An ideal of public justification serves a normative standard for the use of public reason. However, those who adhere to this ideal are divided over how to draw the line between public and nonpublic reasons and whether deliberators may rely on nonpublic reasons in certain situations. As a consequence, there are “competing conceptions of public reason.” In this chapter, my aim is to sketch the debate about public reason, to spell out the similarities and differences of the three basic paths to public justification, and to identify some of the main questions about how such justification can be accomplished.

THE THREE CONCEPTIONS

According to Lawrence Solum, there are three basic principles of public reason: “laissez-faire,” “exclusion,” and “inclusion.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Solum, Lawrence B., “Constructing an Ideal of Public Reason,” 30 San Diego Law Review (1993), 730Google Scholar
Solum, Lawrence B., “Inclusive Public Reason,” 75 Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (1994), 217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solum, Lawrence B., “Pluralism and Public Legal Reason,” Symposium: Religion, Division, and the Constitution, 15 William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal (2006), 11Google Scholar
Solum, Lawrence B., “Public Legal Reason,” 92 Virginia Law Review (2006), 1466Google Scholar
White, Stephen K., The Recent Work of Jürgen Habermas: Reason, Justice and Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, Gerald F., “Liberal Neutrality: A Compelling and Radical Principle,” in Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory, ed. Wall, Stephen and Klosko, George (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), 138Google Scholar
Gauthier, David, “Public Reason,” 12 Social Philosophy and Policy (1995), 30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press, 1986), 221Google Scholar
Kukathas, Chandran and Pettit, Philip, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and Its Critics (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1990), 33Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, “The Public Use of Reason,” in Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 38Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Smith, Norman Kemp (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965), 593Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M., “The Reasons We Share,” in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 295CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. Lenhardt, Christian and Nicolsen, Shierry Weber (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1990), 68Google Scholar
McCarthy, Thomas, “Kantian Constructivism and Reconstructivism: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue,” 105 Ethics (1994), 45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olafson, Frederick A., “Habermas as Philosopher,” 100 Ethics (1990), 645Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen, “Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls's Political Liberalism,” 92 Journal of Philosophy (1995), 131Google Scholar
Moon, J. Donald, “Practical Discourse and Communicative Ethics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Habermas, ed. White, Stephen K. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 148Google Scholar
Wolfe, Alan, One Nation, After All: What Middle-Class Americans Really Think about God, Country, Family, Racism, Welfare, Immigration, Homosexuality, Work, the Right, the Left, and Each Other (New York: Viking Books, 1998)Google Scholar
Greenawalt, Kent, Private Consciences and Public Reasons (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), 52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shenkman, Rick, Just How Stupid Are We? Facing the Truth about the American Voter (New York: Basic Books, 2008), 3Google Scholar
Meiklejohn, Alexander, Free Speech and Its Relation to Self-Government (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1948), 22Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992), 169Google Scholar
Audi, Robert, “The Separation of Church and State and the Obligations of Citizenship,” 18 Philosophy and Public Affairs (1989), 278Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy,” 16 Philosophy and Public Affairs (1987), 229Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles, Patterns of Moral Complexity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987), xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980), 10–11Google Scholar
Bertram, Christopher, “Theories of Public Reason,” 2 Imprints (1997), 76Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald F., “Public Justification and Democratic Adjudication,” 2 Constitutional Political Economy (1991), 257CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, Gerald F., Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 11Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), ixGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Toleration: An Impossible Virtue?” in Toleration: An Elusive Virtue, ed. Heyd, David (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 18–27Google Scholar
Bohman, James, “Public Reason and Cultural Pluralism,” 23 Political Theory (1995), 259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Deanna, The Skills of Argument (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 139–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lister, Andrew, “Public Justification and the Limits of State Action,” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, forthcoming 2010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolgast, Elizabeth A., “The Demands of Public Reason,” 94 Columbia Law Review (1994), 1943–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce, “Why Dialogue?86 Journal of Philosophy (1989), 16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marneffe, Peter, “Rawls's Idea of Public Reason,” 75 Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (1994), 250n17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles, “Public Reason,” in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Freeman, Samuel (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 368Google Scholar
Rawls, John, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 131–80Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel, Rawls (New York: Routledge, 2007), 372Google Scholar
Quong, Jonathan, “The Scope of Public Reason,” 52 Political Studies (2004), 234CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenawalt, Kent, “On Public Reason,” 69 Chicago-Kent Law Review (1994), 685–9Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael J., “Political Liberalism,” review, 107 Harvard Law Review (1994), 1789CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph, “Facing Diversity: The Case for Epistemic Abstinence,” 19 Philosophy and Public Affairs (1990), 9Google Scholar
Brower, Bruce W., “The Limits of Public Reason,” 91 Journal of Philosophy (1994), 26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neal, Patrick, “Is Public Reason Innocuous?11 Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy (2008), 133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul, In Defense of Anarchism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1970)Google Scholar
Westmoreland, Robert, “The Truth about Public Reason,” 18 Law and Philosophy (1999), 283Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M., “The Difficulty of Tolerance,” in Toleration: An Elusive Virtue, ed. Heyd, David (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 232Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×