Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T08:55:01.691Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

10 - Bad faith

from Part II - ONTOLOGY: FREEDOM, AUTHENTICITY AND SELF-CREATION

David Detmer
Affiliation:
Purdue University Calumet
Jack Reynolds
Affiliation:
La Trobe University, Australia
Get access

Summary

“Bad faith”, as a first approximation, refers to self-deception. While lying to oneself might be the clearest example of what is meant by bad faith, most of the examples that Sartre discusses involve techniques that are subtler than overt lying, and might better be characterized as attempts to evade the truth and to keep it hidden from oneself. Such conduct is widespread and common, according to Sartre, especially when the truth to be evaded concerns one's own freedom and consequent responsibility. Accordingly, Sartre, as a champion of both freedom and truth, devotes a great deal of attention to describing, explaining, and attacking bad faith. Indeed, bad faith emerges as a central concept in his thought, one that is repeatedly taken up both in his philosophical work and (implicitly) in his literary writings, and throughout all phases of his career.

The concept of bad faith serves a number of functions in Sartre's work. For example:

  1. • It helps him to explain the widespread acceptance of certain beliefs that he regards as obviously false.

  2. • It aids him in his attempt to prove that the being of consciousness must be radically different from that of non-conscious things.

  3. • As a central concept in his “existential psychoanalysis”, it serves as an indispensable tool in his attempt to understand human lives, both real (as in his biographical studies of Genet and Flaubert) and fictional (as in his development of characters in the story “The Childhood of a Leader” and the play No Exit, among other works).

  4. Implicitly in his early works, and explicitly in his later ones, it functions as an instrument of moral criticism, as it is identified as a vice to be overcome, and is contrasted with a corresponding virtue, that of “authenticity”.

Type
Chapter
Information
Jean-Paul Sartre
Key Concepts
, pp. 118 - 130
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×