Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T01:02:34.902Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - ‘My station and its duties’: social-role accounts of obligation in Green and Bradley

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2013

Robert Stern
Affiliation:
University of Sheffield
Nicholas Boyle
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Liz Disley
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Karl Ameriks
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Different elements in the reception history of German Idealism have had different impacts – such as the Young Hegelians on the philosophy of religion, neo-Kantianism on the philosophy of science, Kojève on accounts of recognition, Croce on theories of art, and so on. When it comes to the British Idealists, arguably the most obvious candidate for such impact is in the idea of ‘my station and its duties’; for while the British Idealists engaged with many aspects of the thought of both Kant and Hegel (and to a lesser degree also of Fichte and Schelling), it seems that it is their notion of ‘my station and its duties’ that has the greatest resonance today, while their accounts of the Absolute, of relations, of the concrete universal, and other aspects of their idealist metaphysics, epistemology and philosophy of mind have been largely forgotten.

In this essay, I want to look again at this idea of ‘my station and its duties’, particularly as it figures in the work of T. H. Green and F. H. Bradley, who pioneered its significance. For, while it is widely used as a slogan to represent both their ethical and political philosophy and that of Idealism more generally, and while it is of continuing influence within certain strands of contemporary ethical and political thinking as an alternative to other approaches, it is rarely given any detailed treatment in historical terms. In particular, I would like to ask precisely what theory of duty or obligation this position is meant to embody: that is, how an appeal to this notion is meant to answer a fundamental question in ethical theory, namely how moral obligation is to be accounted for and best understood. It is most usually assumed, I think, that in tying obligations to social roles, the British Idealists were offering what I will call an identificatory account of obligation: that is, acting in a certain way has an obligatory force because it relates to a role which constitutes your identity.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Impact of Idealism
The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought
, pp. 299 - 322
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Hegelian Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)
Mander, W. J., British Idealism: a history (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinton, Anthony, ‘Absolute Idealism’, reprinted in his Thoughts and Thinkers (London: Duckworth, 1982), 186–206Google Scholar
Prolegomena to Ethics, ed. Bradley, A. C. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1883)Google Scholar
Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. Wood, Allen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 193
Newman, John Henry, Parochial and Plain Sermons, vol I, 1834, sermon 18
Cheap, Eliza, My Station and Its Duties: a narrative for girls going to service, London: R. B. Seeley and W. Burnside, 1836Google Scholar
Norman, Richard, The Moral Philosophers: an introduction to ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), 145–72Google Scholar
Horton, John, Political Obligation (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardimon, Michael, ‘Role obligations’, Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994), 333–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horton, John, ‘In defence of associative political obligations’, Parts One and Two, Political Studies 54 (2006), 427–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sciaraffa, Stefan, ‘Identification, meaning, and the normativity of social roles’, European Journal of Philosophy 19 (2011), 107–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Candlish, Stewart, ‘Bradley on my Station and its duties’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 56 (1978), 155–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The philosophy of Aristotle’, North British Review 45 (1866), 105–44
The Works of T. H. Green, ed. Nettleship, R. L. (London: Longmans Green, 1885–1888), III, 49–91
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Green, T. H. and Grose, T. H. (London: Longmans Green, 1874–1875), I, 1–299Google Scholar
Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation and Other Writings, ed. Harris, Paul and Morrow, John (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 13–193
Stern, Robert, Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012)Google Scholar
Adams, Robert Merrihew, Finite and Infinite Goods: a framework for ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 242Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M., The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. J, Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 81–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neuhouser, Frederick, Foundations of Hegel's Social Theory: actualizing freedom (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), 97−98Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H., ‘Morality and personality: Kant and Green’, in Wood, Allen W. (ed.), Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1984), 31–56Google Scholar
The Development of Ethics, vol. 3 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 581–624
Brink, David O., Perfectionism and the Common Good: themes from the philosophy of T. H. Green (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 92–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nicholson, Peter P., The Political Philosophy of the British Idealists: selected studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 50–51Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A., ‘Does moral philosophy rest on a mistake?’, Mind 21 (1912), 21–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moral Writings, ed. MacAdam, Jim (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 7–20
Wolf, Susan, ‘Moral obligations and social commands’, in Newlands, Samuel and Jorgensen, Larry M. (eds), Metaphysics and the Good: themes from the philosophy of Robert Merrihew Adams (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 343–67, at 345CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×