Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T23:23:18.276Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Culture in Mind – An Enactivist Account

Not Cognitive Penetration but Cultural Permeation

from Section 2 - The Situated Brain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2020

Laurence J. Kirmayer
Affiliation:
McGill University, Montréal
Carol M. Worthman
Affiliation:
Emory University, Atlanta
Shinobu Kitayama
Affiliation:
University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
Robert Lemelson
Affiliation:
University of California, Los Angeles
Constance A. Cummings
Affiliation:
The Foundation for Psychocultural Research
Get access

Summary

Advancing a radically enactive account of cognition, this chapter argues for the possibility that cultural factors permeate rather than penetrate cognition such that cognition extensively and transactionally incorporates cultural factors in lieu of there being any question of cultural factors having to break into the restricted confines of cognition. We review the limitations of two classical cognitivist, modularist accounts of cognition in addition to a revisionary new order variant of cognitivism – a predictive processing account of cognition (PPC). We argue that the cognitivist interpretation of PPC is conservatively and problematically attached to the idea of inner models and stored knowledge. Instead, we offer a radically enactive alternative account of how cultural factors matter to cognition – one that abandons all vestiges of the idea that cultural factors might contentfully communicate with basic forms of cognition. In place of that idea, we promote the possibility that culture permeates cognition.

Type
Chapter
Information
Culture, Mind, and Brain
Emerging Concepts, Models, and Applications
, pp. 163 - 187
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, M. L. (2014). After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Balázsi, G., van Oudenaarden, A., & Collins, J. J. (2011). Cellular decision making and biological noise: From microbes to mammals. Cell, 144(6), 910–25. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2011.01.030CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barrett, L. F., & Bar, M. (2009). See it with feeling: Affective predictions during object perceptionPhilosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences364(1521), 1325–34. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2008.0312CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boroditsky, L. (2001). Does language shape thought? Mandarin and English speakers’ conceptions of time. Cognitive Psychology, 43(1), 122. https://doi.org/10.1006/cogp.2001.0748Google Scholar
Branquinho, J. (Ed.). (2001). The foundations of cognitive science. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brogaard, B., & Chomanski, B. (2015). Cognitive penetrability and high-level properties in perception: Unrelated phenomena? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96(4), 469–86. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12111Google Scholar
Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–59. https://doi.org/10.1016/0004-3702(91)90053-MGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind: Massive modularity and the flexibility of thought. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199207077.001.0001Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2015). Perceiving mental states. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 498507. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2015.04.009Google Scholar
Ceci, S. J., & Roazzi, A. (1994). The effects of context on cognition: Postcards from Brazil. In Sternberg, R. J. & Wagner, R. K. (Eds.), Mind in context: Interactionist perspectives on human intelligence (pp. 74101). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cibelli, E., Xu, Y., Austerweil, J. L., Griffiths, T. L., & Regier, T. (2016). The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis and probabilistic inference: Evidence from the domain of colorPLoS ONE11(7), e0158725. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0158725Google Scholar
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and the world together again. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. (2015). Embodied prediction. In Metzinger, T. & Windt, J. M. (Eds.), Open mind: MIND group. MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570115Google Scholar
Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190217013.001.0001Google Scholar
Costall, A. (1995). Socializing affordancesTheory & Psychology5(4), 467–81. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0959354395054001Google Scholar
Dedrick, D. (2015). Colour language, thought, and culture. In Sharifian, F. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of language and culture (pp. 270–93). Routledge.Google Scholar
Delk, J. L., & Fillenbaum, S. (1965). Differences in perceived color as a function of characteristic colorThe American Journal of Psychology78(2), 290–3. https://doi.org/10.2307/1420503CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Firestone, C., & Scholl, B. J. (2016). Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for “top-down” effectsBehavioral and Brain Sciences39, e229. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X15000965Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (2009). Where is my mind? London Review of Books31(3), 1315.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Friston, K. (2013). Active inference and free energyBehavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 212–13. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12002142Google Scholar
Friston, K. (2018). Does predictive coding have a future? Nature Neuroscience, 21(8), 1019–21. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41593–018-0200-7Google Scholar
Friston, K., Thornton, C., & Clark, A. (2012). Free-energy minimization and the dark-room problemFrontiers in Psychology3(130), 17. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00130Google Scholar
Frith, C. D. (2017). Discovering the social mind: Selected works of Christopher D. Frith. Routledge.Google Scholar
Fuchs, T. (2017). Ecology of the brain: The phenomenology and biology of the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fulda, F. C. (2017). Natural agency: The case of bacterial cognition. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(1), 6990. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2017.5Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198794325.001.0001Google Scholar
Gallagher, S., & Bower, M. (2014). Making enactivism even more embodied. AVANT. Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies, 5(2), 232–47. https://doi.org/10.26913/50202014.0109.0011Google Scholar
Gallagher, S., Hutto, D. D., Slaby, J., & Cole, J. (2013). The brain as part of an enactive system. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(4), 421–2. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12002105Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In Shaw, R. & Bransford, J. (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing: Toward an ecological psychology (pp. 6782). Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Goldstone, R. L. (1994). Influences of categorization on perceptual discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 123(2), 178200. https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.123.2.178Google Scholar
Goldstone, R. L., Lippa, Y., & Shiffrin, R. M. (2001). Altering object representations through category learning. Cognition, 78(1), 2743. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010–0277(00)00099-8Google Scholar
Harnad, S. (Ed.). (1987 ). Categorical perception: The groundwork of cognition. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heyes, C. (2012). New thinking: The evolution of human cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1599), 2091–6. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2012.0111Google Scholar
Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682737.001.0001Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D. (2005). Knowing what? Radical versus conservative enactivism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 389405. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097–005-9001-zGoogle Scholar
Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D., & Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Looking beyond the brain: Social neuroscience meets narrative practice. Cognitive Systems Research, 34 –35, 517. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogsys.2015.07.001Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Basic minds without content, MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–36. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406–015-9644-0Google Scholar
Kay, P. (1999). ColorJournal of Linguistic Anthropology9(1–2), 32–5. https://doi.org/10.1525/jlin.1999.9.1-2.32Google Scholar
Kay, P., & Kempton, W. (1984). What is the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis? American Anthropologist, 86(1), 6579. https://doi.org/10.1525/aa.1984.86.1.02a00050Google Scholar
Locke, J. C. W. (2013). Systems biology: How bacteria choose a lifestyle. Nature, 503, 476–7. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature12837Google Scholar
Losick, R., & Desplan, C. (2008). Stochasticity and cell fate. Science, 320(5872), 65–8. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1147888Google Scholar
Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 2462. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00481.xGoogle Scholar
Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind: A theory of material engagement. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marchi, F., & Newen, A. (2015). Cognitive penetrability and emotion recognition in human facial expressions. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 828. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00828Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational approach. Freeman. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262514620.001.0001Google Scholar
Newen, A., & Vetter, P. (2017). Why cognitive penetration of our perceptual experience is still the most plausible account. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 2637. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.09.005Google Scholar
Newen, A., Marchi, F., & Brössel, P. (2017). Introduction – Cognitive penetration and predictive coding: Pushing the debate forward with the recent achievements of cognitive science. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 15. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.12.001Google Scholar
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT press.Google Scholar
O’Callaghan, C., Kveraga, K., Shine, J. M., Adams, R. B. Jr., & Bar, M. (2017). Predictions penetrate perception: Converging insights from brain, behaviour and disorderConsciousness and Cognition47, 6374. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.05.003Google Scholar
O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–73. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X01000115Google Scholar
Overmann, K. A. (2016). Beyond writing: The development of literacy in the ancient Near East. Cambridge Archaeological Journal, 26(2), 285303. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0959774316000019Google Scholar
Perkins, T. J., & Swain, P. S. (2009). Strategies for cellular decision-making. Molecular Systems Biology, 5(1), 326. https://doi.org/10.1038/msb.2009.83Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition?: The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–65. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X99002022Google Scholar
Raftopoulos, A. (2001). Is perception informationally encapsulated?: The issue of the theory-ladenness of perceptionCognitive Science25(3), 423–51. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog2503_4Google Scholar
Raftopoulos, A. (2015). The cognitive impenetrability of perception and theory-ladennessJournal for General Philosophy of Science46(1), 87103. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838–015-9288-6Google Scholar
Raftopoulos, A. (2017). Pre-cueing, the epistemic role of early vision, and the cognitive impenetrability of early visionFrontiers in Psychology8, 1156. https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffpsyg.2017.01156Google Scholar
Raftopoulos, A., & Lupyan, G. (2018). Pre-cueing effects on perception and cognitive penetrabilityFrontiers in Psychology9, 230. https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffpsyg.2018.00230Google Scholar
Ramstead, M. J. D., Veissière, S. P. L., & Kirmayer, L. J. (2016). Cultural affordances: Scaffolding local worlds through shared intentionality and regimes of attentionFrontiers in Psychology7, 1090. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01090Google Scholar
Rauss, K., Schwartz, S., & Pourtois, G. (2011). Top-down effects on early visual processing in humans: A predictive coding frameworkNeuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews35(5), 1237–53. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2010.12.011Google Scholar
Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions (Anderson, F., Trans.). Oxford University Press. (Original work published in 2006)Google Scholar
Roepstorff, A., Niewöhner, J., & Beck, S. (2010). Enculturing brains through patterned practices. Neural Networks, 23(8–9), 1051–9. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neunet.2010.08.002Google Scholar
Shuler, M. G., & Bear, M. F. (2006). Reward timing in the primary visual cortex. Science, 311(5767), 1606–9. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1123513Google Scholar
Siegel, S. (2012). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Noûs, 46(2), 201–22. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00786.xGoogle Scholar
Sohoglu, E., Peelle, J. E., Carlyon, R. P., & Davis, M. H. (2012). Predictive top-down integration of prior knowledge during speech perceptionJournal of Neuroscience32(25), 8443–53. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5069-11.2012Google Scholar
Tagkopoulos, I., Liu, Y.-C., & Tavazoie, S. (2008). Predictive behavior within microbial genetic networks. Science, 320(5881), 1313–17. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1154456Google Scholar
Thierry, G., Athanasopoulos, P., Wiggett, A., Dering, B., & Kuipers, J.-R. (2009). Unconscious effects of language-specific terminology on preattentive color perceptionProceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America106(11), 4567–70. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0811155106Google Scholar
Thompson, E., Lutz, A., & Cosmelli, D. (2005). Neurophenomenology: An introduction for neurophilosophers. In Brook, A. & Atkins, K. (Eds.), Cognition and the brain: The philosophy and neuroscience movement (pp. 4097). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610608.003Google Scholar
Toribio, J. (2018). Visual experience: Rich but impenetrableSynthese195(8), 3389–406. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229–015-0889-8Google Scholar
Vetter, P., & Newen, A. (2014). Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 6275. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.04.007Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1983). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics (Anscombe, G. E. M., Trans.; von Wright, G. H. & Rhees, R., Eds.). Blackwell. (Original work published 1956)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical investigations (4th ed., Anscombe, G.E.M., Hacker, P. M. S., & Schulte, J., Trans., Hacker, P. M. S., & Schulte, J., Eds.). Blackwell Publishing. (Original work published 1953)Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2007). Rule-following without reasons: Wittgenstein’s quietism and the constitutive questionRatio20(4), 481502. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2007.00379.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeimbekis, J., & Raftopoulos, A. (Eds.). (2015). The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×